Skip to main content
Log in

Decision-making under uncertainty: biases and Bayesians

  • Review
  • Published:
Animal Cognition Aims and scope Submit manuscript

It is not certain that everything is uncertain.

Blaise Pascal

Abstract

Animals (including humans) often face circumstances in which the best choice of action is not certain. Environmental cues may be ambiguous, and choices may be risky. This paper reviews the theoretical side of decision-making under uncertainty, particularly with regard to unknown risk (ambiguity). We use simple models to show that, irrespective of pay-offs, whether it is optimal to bias probability estimates depends upon how those estimates have been generated. In particular, if estimates have been calculated in a Bayesian framework with a sensible prior, it is best to use unbiased estimates. We review the extent of evidence for and against viewing animals (including humans) as Bayesian decision-makers. We pay particular attention to the Ellsberg Paradox, a classic result from experimental economics, in which human subjects appear to deviate from optimal decision-making by demonstrating an apparent aversion to ambiguity in a choice between two options with equal expected rewards. The paradox initially seems to be an example where decision-making estimates are biased relative to the Bayesian optimum. We discuss the extent to which the Bayesian paradigm might be applied to the evolution of decision-makers and how the Ellsberg Paradox may, with a deeper understanding, be resolved.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Abrams PA (1994) Should prey overestimate the risk of predation? Am Nat 144:317–328

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Al-Najjar N, Weinstein J (2009) The ambiguity aversion literature: a critical assessment. Econ Philos 25:249–284

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bach DR, Seymour B, Dolan RJ (2009) Neural activity associated with the passive prediction of ambiguity and risk for aversive events. J Neurosci 29:1648–1656

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Basile BM, Hampton RR, Suomi SJ, Murray EA (2009) An assessment of memory awareness in tufted capuchin monkeys (Cebus apella). Anim Cogn 12:169–180

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Bednekoff PA, Houston AI (1994) Dynamic models of mass-dependent predation, risk-sensitive foraging, and premigratory fattening in birds. Ecology 75:1131–1140

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Binmore K (2009) Making decisions in large worlds. http://www.else.econ.ucl.ac.uk/papers/uploaded/266.pdf

  • Blanchette I, Richards A (2003) Anxiety and the interpretation of ambiguous information: beyond the emotion-congruent effect. J Exp Psychol Gen 132:294–309

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Bouskila A, Blumstein DT (1992) Rules of thumb for predation hazard assessment - predictions from a dynamic model. Am Nat 139:161–176

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burman OHP, Parker R, Paul ES, Mendl M (2008) A spatial judgement task to determine background emotional state in laboratory rats, Rattus norvegicus. Anim Behav 76:801–809

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Call J (2010) Do apes know that they could be wrong? Anim Cogn (in press). doi:10.1007/s10071-010-0317-x

  • Camerer C, Weber M (1992) Recent developments in modeling preferences—uncertainty and ambiguity. J Risk Uncertainty 5:325–370

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carlin BP, Louis TA (1996) Bayes and empirical Bayes methods for data analysis. Monographs on statistics and applied probability 69. Chapman & Hall, London, pp 50–52

    Google Scholar 

  • Christopoulos GI, Tobler PN, Bossaerts P, Dolan RJ, Schultz W (2009) Neural correlates of value, risk, and risk aversion contributing to decision making under risk. J Neurosci 29:12574–12583

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Dayan P, Daw ND (2008) Decision theory, reinforcement learning, and the brain. Cognitive Affective & Behavioral Neuroscience 8(4):429–453

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dobbs IM (1991) A Bayesian approach to decision-making under ambiguity. Economica, New Series 58(232):417–440

  • Ellsberg D (1961) Risk, ambiguity and the Savage axioms. Q J Econ 75(4):643–669

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Erichsen JT, Krebs JR, Houston AI (1980) Optimal foraging and cryptic prey. J Anim Ecol 49:271–276

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G, Hoffrage U (1995) How to improve Bayesian reasoning without instruction: frequency formats. Psychol Rev 102(4):684–704

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G, Todd PM (1999) Simple heuristics that make us smart. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Halevy Y, Feltkamp V (2005) A Bayesian approach to uncertainty aversion. Rev Econ Stud 72(2):449–466

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hampton RR, Zivin A, Murray EA (2004) Rhesus monkeys (Macaca mulatta) discriminate between knowing and not knowing and collect information as needed before acting. Anim Cogn 7:239–246

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Harding EJ, Paul ES, Mendl M (2004) Animal behavior–cognitive bias and affective state. Nature 427:312

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Hayden BY, Platt ML (2009) Gambling for Gatorade: risk-sensitive decision making for fluid rewards in humans. Anim Cogn 12:201–207

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Hayden BY, Heilbronner SR, Platt ML (2010) Ambiguity aversion in rhesus macaques. Frontiers in Neuroscience 4:1–7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hazen GB (1992) Decisions versus policy: an expected utility resolution of the Ellsberg Paradox. In: Geweke J (ed) Decision making under risk and uncertainty: new models and empirical findings. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp 25–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Hertwig R, Barron G, Weber EU, Erev I (2004) Decisions from experience and the effect of rare events in risky choice. Psychol Sci 15:534–539

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Houston AI (2009) Flying in the face of nature. Behav Process 80:295–305

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Houston AI, McNamara JM (1982) A sequential approach to risk-taking. Anim Behav 30:1260–1261

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Houston AI, McNamara JM (1985) The choice of two prey types that minimises the probability of starvation. Behav Ecol Sociobiol 17(2):135–141

    Google Scholar 

  • Houston AI, McNamara JM (1989) The value of food: effects of open and closed economies. Anim Behav 37:546–562

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Houston AI, McNamara JM (1999) Models of adaptive behaviour. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Houston AI, Krebs JR, Erichsen JT (1980) Optimal prey choice and discrimination time in the great tit Parus major. Behav Ecol Sociobiol 6:169–175

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Houston AI, Kacelnik A, McNamara JM (1982) Some learning rules for acquiring information. In: McFarland DJ (ed) Functional Ontogeny. Pitman, London, pp 140–191

    Google Scholar 

  • Houston AI, McNamara JM, Steer MD (2007) Violations of transitivity under fitness maximization. Biol Lett 3:365–367

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Hsu M, Bhatt M, Adolphs R, Tranel D, Camerer CF (2005) Neural systems responding to degrees of uncertainty in human decision-making. Science 310(5754):1680–1683

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson RR, Pollard SD, Li D, Fijn N (2002) Interpolation variation in the risk-related decisions of Porta labiata, an araneophagic jumping spider (Araneae, Salticidae), during predatory sequences with spitting spiders. Anim Cogn 5:215–223

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kacelnik A, Bateson M (1996) Risky theories - the effects of variance on foraging decisions. Am Zool 36:402–434

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D, Tversky A (1972) Subjective probability: a judgement of representativeness. Cogn Psychol 3:430–454

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kawamori A, Matsushima T (2010) Subjective value of risky foods for individual domestic chicks: a hierarchical Bayesian model. Anim Cogn 13:431–441

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Klaassen RHG, Nolet BA, van Gils JA, Bauer S (2006) Optimal movement between patches under incomplete information about the spatial distribution of food items. Theor Popul Biol 70:452–463

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Knight FH (1921) Risk. uncertainty and profit. Houghton Mifflin Company, New York, pp 43–46

    Google Scholar 

  • Krebs JR, Kacelnik A, Taylor P (1978) Test of optimal sampling by foraging great tits. Nature 275:27–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lagorio CH, Hackenberg TD (2010) Risky choice in pigeons and humans: a cross-species comparison. J Exp Anal Behav 93:27–44

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Lange A, Dukas R (2009) Bayesian approximations and extensions: optimal decisions for small brains and possibly big ones too. J Theor Biol 259(3):503–516

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Langen TA (1999) How western scrub-jays (Alphelocoma californica) select a nut: effects of the number of options, variation in nut size, and social competition among foragers. Anim Cogn 2:223–233

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein G, Lerner JS (2003) The role of affect in decision making. In: Davidson RJ, Scherer KR, Goldsmith HH (eds) Handbook of Affective Sciences. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 619–642

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein GF, Weber EU, Hsee CK, Welch N (2001) Risk as feelings. Psychol Bull 127(2):267–286

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • McNamara JM, Dall SRX (2010) Information is a fitness enhancing resource. Oikos 119:231–236

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McNamara JM, Houston AI (1980) The application of statistical decision theory to animal behaviour. J Theor Biol 85:673–690

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • McNamara JM, Houston AI (1985) A simple model of information use in the exploitation of patchily distributed food. Anim Behav 33:553–560

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McNamara JM, Houston AI (1987) A general framework for understanding the effects of variability and interruptions on foraging behaviour. Acta Biotheor 36:3–22

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • McNamara JM, Houston AI (1992) Risk-sensitive foraging—a review of the theory. Bull Math Biol 54:355–378

    Google Scholar 

  • McNamara JM, Houston AI (1997) Currencies for foraging based on energetic gain. Am Nat 150:603–617

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • McNamara JM, Houston AI (2009) Integrating function and mechanism. Trends Ecol Evol 24(12):670–675

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • McNamara JM, Merad S, Houston AI (1991) A model of risk-sensitive foraging for a reproducing animal. Anim Behav 41:787–792

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McNamara JM, Green RF, Olsson O (2006) Bayes’ theorem and its applications in animal behaviour. Oikos 112:243–251

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mendl M, Burman OHP, Parker RMA, Paul ES (2009) Cognitive bias as an indicator of animal emotion and welfare: emerging evidence and underlying mechanisms. Appl Anim Behav Sci 118:161–181

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mendl M, Burman OHP, Paul ES (2010) An integrative and functional framework for the study of animal emotion and mood. Proc R Soc B 277:2895–2904

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Mogg K, Bradbury KE, Bradley BP (2006) Interpretation of ambiguous information in clinical depression. Behav Res Ther 44:1411–1419

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Naug D, Arathi HS (2007) Sampling and decision rules used by honey bees in a foraging arena. Anim Cogn 10:117–124

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Nettle D (2004) Adaptive illusions: optimism, control and human rationality. In: Evans D, Cruse P (eds) Emotion, evolution and rationality. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 193–208

    Google Scholar 

  • Oaksford M, Chater N (2009) Precis of Bayesian rationality: the probabilistic approach to human reasoning. Behav Brain Sci 32:69–120

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Olsson O, Holmgren NMA (1998) The survival-rate-maximizing policy for Bayesian foragers: wait for good news. Behav Ecol 9:345–353

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olsson O, Wiktander U, Holmgren NMA, Nilsson S (1999) Gaining ecological information about Bayesian foragers through their behaviour. II. A field test with woodpeckers. Oikos 87:264–276

    Google Scholar 

  • Ozdenoren E, Peck J (2008) Ambiguity aversion, games against nature, and dynamic consistency. Game Econ Behav 62:106–115

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parker GA, Maynard Smith J (1990) Optimality theory in evolutionary biology. Nature 348:27–33

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paul ES, Harding EJ, Mendl M (2005) Measuring emotional processes in animals: the utility of a cognitive approach. Neurosci Biobehav 29:469–491

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Platt ML, Huettel SA (2008) Risky business: the neuroeconomics of decision making under uncertainty. Nature Neurosci 11:398–403

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Pulford BD (2009) Is luck on my side? Optimism, pessimism, and ambiguity aversion. Q J Exp Psychol 62:1079–1087

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raiffa H (1961) Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms: comment. Q J Econ 75:690–694

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raiffa H, Schlaifer R (1961) Applied statistical decision theory. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts

    Google Scholar 

  • Real L, Caraco T (1986) Risk and foraging in stochastic environments. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 17:371–390

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rilling JK, Sanfey AG, Aronson JA, Nystrom LE, Cohen JD (2004) The neural correlates of theory of mind within interpersonal interactions. NeuroImage 22:1694–1703

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts HV (1963) Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms: comment. Q J Econ 77(2):327–336

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rode C, Cosmides L, Hell W, Tooby J (1999) When and why do people avoid unknown probabilities in decisions under uncertainty? Testing some predictions from optimal foraging theory. Cognition 72(3):269–304

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Rosati AG, Hare B (2011) Chimpanzees and bonobos distinguish between risk and ambiguity. Biol Lett 7(1):15–18

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Schultz W, Preuschoff K, Camerer C, Hsu M, Fiorillo CD, Tobler PN, Bossaerts P (2008) Explicit neural signals reflecting reward uncertainty. Phil Trans R Soc B 363:3801–3811

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Smith JD, Redford JS, Beran MJ, Washburn DA (2010) Rhesus monkeys (Macaca mulatta) adaptively monitor uncertainty while multi-tasking. Anim Cogn 13:93–101

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Stephens DW, Krebs JR (1986) Foraging theory. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Trautmann ST, Vieder FM, Wakker PP (2008) Causes of ambiguity aversion: known versus unknown preferences. J Risk Uncertainty 36:225–243

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trimmer PC, Houston AI, Marshall JAR, Bogacz R, Paul ES, Mendl MT, McNamara JM (2008) Mammalian choices: combining fast-but-inaccurate and slow-but-accurate decision-making systems. Proc R Soc B 275:2353–2361

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Uehara T, Yokomizo H, Iwasa Y (2005) Mate-choice copying as Bayesian decision making. Am Nat 165(3):403–410

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Valone TJ (2006) Are animals capable of Bayesian updating? An empirical review. Oikos 112:252–259

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Gils JA, Schenk IW, Bos O, Piersma T (2003) Incompletely informed shorebirds that face a digestive constraint maximize net energy gain when exploiting patches. Am Nat 161:777–793

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Viscusi WK, Magat WA (1992) Bayesian decisions with ambiguous belief aversion. J Risk Uncertainty 5(4):371–387

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waite TA (2008) Preference for oddity: uniqueness heuristic or hierarchical choice process? Anim Cogn 11:707–713

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Weber EU, Shafir S, Blais AR (2004) Predicting risk sensitivity in humans and lower animals: risk as variance or coefficient of variation. Psychol Rev 111:430–445

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Welton NJ, McNamara JM, Houston AI (2003) Assessing predation risk: optimal behaviour and rules of thumb. Theor Popul Biol 64:417–430

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Zhu L, Gigerenzer G (2006) Children can solve Bayesian problems: the role of representation in mental computation. Cognition 98:287–308

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

PCT was supported by ERC grant 250209 Evomech.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pete C. Trimmer.

Appendices

Appendix 1: optimal bias for a frequentist estimate

If p a is estimated after having witnessed k successes from n previous trials, the unbiased frequentist estimate of the probability of success is k/n. If the estimated probability of success, p est, is used as if it is the true probability of success, then the expected pay-off for true p a will be given by

$$ \sum\limits_{{k:p_{\text{est}} > p_{r} }} {P(k|n)(p_{a} b - (1 - p_{a} )c)} $$

where

$$ P(k|n) = {\frac{n!}{k!(n - k)!}}\,p_{a}^{k} (1 - p_{a} )^{n - k} $$

is the probability of k successes from n trials.

We introduce a bias, s, as the fraction of the distance from k/n upward (downward) towards 1 (0) for positive (negative) values of bias. By regarding p a as having been chosen from a uniform distribution over the interval (0,1), we can then calculate the minimal optimal bias for a range of n and b/c, as shown in Fig. 2. By minimal optimal bias, we mean the bias closest to zero for which the expected return is maximised; the reason for the qualification is that there is typically a range of values of bias for which the expected return is maximised.

Fig. 2
figure 2

Optimal bias as a function of number of trials and benefit/cost

The ridges in the graph are a result of the discrete nature of the number of successes and the number of trials. As the number of trials increases and the resulting estimate improves, the optimal bias reduces towards zero, together with the step changes becoming smaller.

Appendix 2: use of the beta distribution

A beta distribution is a probability distribution on the interval [0,1], the pdf of which is defined by the two shape parameters (hyperparameters), α > 0 and β > 0, according to:

$$ {\text{Beta}}(\alpha ,\beta ) = f(x;\alpha ,\beta ) = {\frac{{x^{\alpha - 1} (1 - x)^{\beta - 1} }}{B(\alpha ,\beta )}} $$

where B (α, β) is the beta function, in this case serving as a normalisation constant.

For α = β = 1, the beta distribution is no longer a function of x, so provides the uniform distribution.

Due to the Bernoulli nature of the trials, the posterior distribution following an update is also a beta distribution, as are all subsequent updates (Carlin & Louis, 1996). To see that this is so, let \( f(k|p) = p^{k} (1 - p)^{n - k} \) denote the likelihood of witnessing k successes from n trials when the probability of success is p. Then, if the prior \( \pi (p) \) is a beta distribution, we have:

$$ \begin{aligned} P(p|k) & \propto f(k|p)\pi (p) \\ & \propto p^{k + \alpha - 1} (1 - p)^{n - k + \beta - 1} \\ & \propto {\text{Beta}}(\alpha^{\prime } ,\beta^{\prime } ) \\ \end{aligned} $$

where \( \alpha^{\prime } = \alpha + k \) and \( \beta^{\prime } = \beta + n - k \).

The mean of the posterior distribution, \( \alpha^{\prime } /(\alpha^{\prime } + \beta^{\prime } ) \), then provides the expected value of p a as \( E(p_{a} ) = {\frac{k + \alpha }{n + \alpha + \beta }} \).

Appendix 3: comparing the mean of the posterior with the critical probability

The expected probability of success at any stage is given by

$$ P({\text{success}}) = \int\limits_{0}^{1} {f(p)p{\text{d}}p = E(p_{a} )} $$

Using this expected value, it is best not to apply any bias before comparing with p r .

Let us assume that, having updated the uniform prior with the trial data and obtained a posterior beta distribution with mean p m , the individual finds that p m  = p r . Will it matter whether the individual chooses to act or not?

If the individual chooses to act, then integrating the expected pay-off across the distribution of possible p values, where E (p) = p m  = p r , the expected value of acting is:

$$ \int\limits_{0}^{1} {f(p)(pb - (1 - p)c){\text{d}}p = E(p)b - (1 - E(p)c) = p_{r} b - (1 - p_{r} )c = 0} $$

which is the same expected value as not acting. Therefore, if the posterior estimate was greater than the critical probability (i.e. p m  > p r ), it would be best to act and vice versa with p m  < p r . The mean of the posterior is therefore a sufficient statistic to compare with p r when deciding whether to act.

Thus, it is best not to apply any bias before comparing with p r .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Trimmer, P.C., Houston, A.I., Marshall, J.A.R. et al. Decision-making under uncertainty: biases and Bayesians. Anim Cogn 14, 465–476 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10071-011-0387-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10071-011-0387-4

Keywords

Navigation