Skip to main content
Log in

Toss one’s cake, and eat it too: partial divisions can improve social welfare in cake cutting

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We consider the problem of fairly dividing a heterogeneous good (a.k.a. “cake”) between a number of players with different tastes. In this setting, it is known that fairness requirements may result in a suboptimal division from the social welfare standpoint. Here we show that, in some cases, leaving some of the cake unallocated, and fairly dividing only the remainder of the cake may be socially preferable to any fair division of the entire cake. We study this phenomenon, providing asymptotically-tight bounds on the social improvement achievable by such partial divisions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We note that for very small values of n, the bound of \(\frac{n}{2}\) can actually be obtained.

  2. For a function f(n) we say that \(f(n) = \varTheta (g(n))\) if \(\lim \sup _{n \rightarrow \infty }{\frac{f(n)}{g(n)}} < \infty \) and \(\lim \inf _{n \rightarrow \infty }{\frac{f(n)}{g(n)}} > 0\); conceptually, this means that asymptotically “f(n) behaves similarly to g(n)”.

  3. Since single points have no value, it is often easier to consider all allotted pieces to be open intervals, and not worry who gets the border between two adjacent pieces.

  4. We note, however, that this method for determining the optimal division assumes full knowledge of the valuation functions, and is thus not in the Robertson-Webb query model Robertson and Webb (1998).

  5. Under stronger conditions, namely that the valuation functions of the players are absolutely continuous w.r.t. each other, Gale (1993) has shown envy-free divisions cannot be even non-strictly Pareto dominated.

  6. \(\lceil \alpha \rceil \) is the smallest integer such that \(\lceil \alpha \rceil \ge \alpha \).

  7. The measure \(V_i\) is non-atomic if for any A with \(V_i(A)>0\) there exists \(B\subset A\) with \(V_i(A)>V_i(B)>0\). In particular, all single points have measure 0.

  8. Another possible justification for this is by assuming that the players themselves may dispose of any excess cake.

References

  • Aumann Y, Dombb Y (2010) The efficiency of fair division with connected pieces. In: Proceedings of the 6th International Workshop on Internet and Network Economics (WINE), pp 26–37

  • Barbanel JB, Brams SJ, Stromquist W (2009) Cutting a pie is not a piece of cake. Am Math Mon 116(6):496–514

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bei X, Chen N, Hua X, Tao B, Yang E (2012) Optimal proportional cake cutting with connected pieces. In: Proceedings of the 26th Conference on Artificial Intelligence (AAAI)

  • Braess D (1968) Uber ein paradoxon aus der verkehrsplanung. Unternehmensforschung 12:258–268

    Google Scholar 

  • Brams SJ, Jones MA, Klamler C (2013) N-person cake-cutting: there may be no perfect division. Am Math Mon 120(1):35–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brams SJ, Taylor AD (1995) An envy-free cake division protocol. Am Math Mon 102(1):9–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brams SJ, Taylor AD (1996) Fair Division: From cake cutting to dispute resolution. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Caragiannis I, Kaklamanis C, Kanellopoulos P, Kyropoulou M (2009) The efficiency of fair division. In: Proceedings of the 5th International Workshop on Internet and Network Economics (WINE), pp 475–482

  • Caragiannis I, Lai J, Procaccia A (2011) Towards more expressive cake cutting. In: Proceedings of the 22nd international joint conferences on artificial intelligence (IJCAI), pp 127–132

  • Chambers CP (2005) Allocation rules for land division. J Econ Theory 121(2):236–258

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen Y, Lai J, Parkes DC, Procaccia AD (2010) Truth, justice, and cake cutting. In: Proceedings of the 24th conference on artificial intelligence (AAAI)

  • Cohler YJ, Lai J, Parkes DC, Procaccia A (2011) Optimal envy-free cake cutting. In: Proceedings of the 25th conference on artificial intelligence (AAAI)

  • Cole R, Dodis Y, Roughgarden T (2003) How much can taxes help selfish routing? In: ACM Conference on Electronic Commerce, pp 98–107

  • Dubins LE, Spanier EH (1961) How to cut a cake fairly. Am Math Mon 68(1):1–17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edmonds J, Pruhs K (2003) Cake cutting really is not a piece of cake. In: Proceedings of the 17th annual ACM-SIAM symposium on discrete algorithms (SODA), pp 271–278

  • Even S, Paz A (1984) A note on cake cutting. Discret Appl Math 7(3):285–296

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gale D (1993) Mathematical entertainments. Math Intell 15(1):48–52

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartline JD, Roughgarden T (2008) Optimal mechanism design and money burning. In: Proceedings of the 2008 ACM International symposium on theory of computing (STOC), pp 75–84

  • Hill TP (1983) Determining a fair border. Am Math Mon 90(7):438–442

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koutsoupias E, Papadimitriou CH (1999) Worst-case equilibria. In: Proceedings of the 16th annual symposium on theoretical aspects of computer science (STACS), pp 404–413

  • Maccheroni F, Maccheroni F, Marinacci M, Marinacci M (2003) How to cut a pizza fairly: fair division with decreasing marginal evaluations. Soc Choice Welf 20:457–465

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magdon-Ismail M, Busch C, Krishnamoorthy MS (2003) Cake-cutting is not a piece of cake. In: Proceedings of the 20th annual symposium on theoretical aspects of computer science (STACS), pp 596–607

  • Moulin HJ (2004) Fair Division and Collective Welfare. The MIT Press

  • Procaccia AD (2009) Thou shalt covet thy neighbor’s cake. In: Proceedings of the 21st international joint conferences on artificial intelligence (IJCAI), pp 239–244

  • Robertson J, Webb W (1998) Cake-cutting algorithms: Be fair if you can. A K Peters Ltd, Natick

    Google Scholar 

  • Sgall J, Woeginger GJ (2003) A lower bound for cake cutting. In: Proceedings of the 11th Annual European symposium on algorithms (ESA), pp 459–469

  • Steinhaus H (1949) Sur la division pragmatique. Econometrica 17(Supplement: Report of the Washington Meeting):315–319

  • Stromquist W (1980) How to cut a cake fairly. Am Math Mon 87(8):640–644

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stromquist W (2008) Envy-free cake divisions cannot be found by finite protocols. Electron J Comb 15(1).http://dblp.uni-trier.de/db/journals/combinatorics/combinatorics15.html#Stromquist08

  • Thomson W (2007) Fair allocation rules. Rochester center for economic research

  • Weller D (1985) Fair division of a measurable space. J Math Econ 14(1):5–17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodall DR (1980) Dividing a cake fairly. J Math Anal Appl 78(1):233–247

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zivan R (2011) Can trust increase the efficiency of cake cutting algorithms? In: Proceedings of the 10th international conference on autonomous agents and multiagent systems (AAMAS), pp 1145–1146

Download references

Acknowledgments

We are grateful to the anonymous referees for comments that helped improve this paper. Yonatan Aumann is supported, in part, by ISF grant 1083/13.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yair Dombb.

Appendices

Appendix A No PD-improvement with multiple intervals per player

Throughout the paper we considered the case where each player gets a single interval. Here we show that if each player can get multiple intervals then there is no PD-improvement. To formalize this, we first need to extend the model to this setting, and, in particular, extend the definitions of: pieces, valuations functions, and divisions. In the multiple interval setting a piece is element of the Borel \(\sigma \)-algebra over [0, 1]. Each valuation function \(V_i\) is a non-atomic measure over this \(\sigma \)-algebra.Footnote 7 In particular, the valuations functions are monotone (that is, \(V_i(d)\le V_i(c)\) for pieces \(d\subset c\)). A division assigns disjoint pieces to the players.

Proposition 2

In the multiple interval setting, there can be no PD-improvement for any monotone welfare function. In addition, in this setting no envy-free partial division can Pareto dominate all envy-free complete divisions.

Proof

Fix some cake instance, and let x be a partial envy-free division. We construct a complete envy-free division \(\hat{x}\), in which each player gets a piece that contains the piece it gets in x. Thus, by monotonicity of \(V_i\), x does not Pareto dominate \(\hat{x}\), and by monotonicity of the welfare function w, \(w(\hat{x}) \ge w(x)\). Thus, there is no PD-improvement.

Let \(d_i\) be the piece allotted to i in x, and set \(D=\cup _{i=1}^n d_i\). Then, D is measurable, and hence \(C=[0,1]\setminus D\) is also measurable. Thus, by  Dubins and Spanier (1961) there exists a complete envy-free division, y of C. Let \(c_i\) be the piece (of C) allotted to i by y. Let \(\hat{x}\) be the division in which player i gets \(d_i\cup c_i\) (for all i). Then, \(\hat{x}\) is a complete division of [0, 1], and for any ij

$$\begin{aligned} V_i(d_i\cup c_i) = V_i(d_i)+ V_i(c_i) \ge V_i(d_j)+ V_i(c_j) = V_i(d_j\cup c_j), \end{aligned}$$

where the inequality is provided by the envy-freeness of x and y. Thus, \(\hat{x}\) is envy-free.

We note that a similar statement also holds if we allow each player to get only a finite number of intervals (rather than any measurable set). The proof in this case would be similar, but invoking  Stromquist (1980) existence theorem rather than the one of  Dubins and Spanier (1961).

Appendix B Non-additive valuations

Throughout the paper, we have assumed that the players’ valuations are additive. In this appendix we study the extent to which this assumption can be weakened while maintaining the results. First note that most of the results in the paper are lower bound constructions. Thus, all of these results remain true for any class of valuation functions that generalize additivity (in particular—no additivity requirement).

As for the upper bounds, we now identify some natural weakened requirements under which the results still hold.

The first requirement is that the valuations are continuous, in the sense that the value of a piece changes “smoothly” with small additions or subtractions from the piece (this in particular implies the non-atomicity requirement). Clearly, without this assumption envy-free divisions may not even exist (e.g. if all players give value of 1 to any piece containing the point \(\frac{1}{2}\) and 0 to any piece not containing it), and the PD-improvement is not well-defined. On the other hand, Stromquist (1980) shows that this requirement is sufficient to guarantee existence of envy-free divisions.

  • Continuity For any piece \(I\subseteq [0,1]\) and every \(\epsilon >0\) there exists \(\delta >0\) such that for any other piece J if \(|I\bigtriangleup J| < \delta \) (where \(|I\bigtriangleup J|\) is the total length of the symmetric difference between I and J) then \(|V_i(I) - V_i(J)| < \epsilon \).

Our second requirement formalizes the idea that the cake is a “good”, and therefore getting less of it is never preferred.Footnote 8

  • Monotonicity For pieces IJ, if \(I\subseteq J\) then \(V_i(I)\le V_i(J)\).

These two assumptions turn out to be already sufficient for proving some of the results. In particular, no further assumptions are required for proving Proposition 2, showing that there is no PD-improvement with non-connected pieces, Proposition 1, showing the connection between the Price of Envy-Freeness and the PD-improvement, and the first part of Theorem 4, showing that no strict Pareto improvement exists when starting from a complete envy-free division.

For proving the remaining upper bounds, we also need to assume that the value of a piece is never greater than the sum of the value of its parts.

  • Sub-additivity For any piece I and partitions \(I=I_i\cup I_2\) (with \(I_1, I_2\) disjoint pieces), \(V_i(I) \le V_i(I_1) + V_i(I_2)\).

With this assumption, we can also prove the second part of Theorem 4, showing that one cannot increase the utility of half the players by more than a twofold simultaneously, and the upper bound on the utilitarian Price of Envy-Freeness used in Theorem 7. This assumption also allows us to show an upper bound of n on the egalitarian Price of Envy-Freeness, since it implies that any envy-free division must give each player a piece of value \(\ge \frac{1}{n}\); thus, the upper bound in Theorem 6 can be replaced with n, which also asymptotically matches the lower bound of \(\frac{n}{3}\).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Arzi, O., Aumann, Y. & Dombb, Y. Toss one’s cake, and eat it too: partial divisions can improve social welfare in cake cutting. Soc Choice Welf 46, 933–954 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-015-0943-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-015-0943-y

Keywords

Navigation