Skip to main content
Log in

The scoring rules in an endogenous election

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Plurality rule is mostly criticized from being capable of choosing an alternative considered as worst by a strict majority. This paper considers elections in which the agenda consists of potential candidates strategically choosing whether or not to enter the election. In this context, we examine the ability of scoring rules to fulfil the Condorcet criterion. We show for the case of three potential candidates that Plurality rule is the only scoring rule that satisfies a version of the Condorcet criterion in two cases: 1) when preferences are single-peaked and, 2) when preferences are single-dipped.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Unanimity requires that if all voters find the same candidate most preferred out of the entering candidates, then that candidate is selected.

  2. Note that in two-candidate elections, all scoring rules coincide with Majority rule.

  3. This assumption is also made by Osborne and Slivinsky [13]. Besley and Coate [1] assume however that voting is strategic.

  4. For n sufficiently large the voting numbers can be obtained as integer numbers.

  5. Note that when either a or c are Condorcet winner, they indeed are strong Condorcet winner.

  6. Furthermore, it can be shown that in an endogenous election involving three candidates no scoring rule elects a Condorcet loser. By contrast Lepelley et al. [10] show, in the classical three candidate election, that a Scoring rule can elect a Condorcet loser if and only if \(0 \leqslant w <\frac{1} {2}\).

  7. Our conjecture is that the result in Theorem 3 can be extended to any number of candidates.

  8. These preferences are separable since alternative a is never middle-ranked.

  9. This Theorem was suggested by an anonymous referee.

  10. Which is defined as the conditional probability that the rule selects the Condorcet winner.

  11. See Lepelley [8] (Sections 4 and 5) for further comments on this point. This author also provides the example P=(3, 0, 2, 2) to illustrate that candidate a is a Condorcet loser selected by Plurality rule.

  12. These authors show by means of experiments that, under Plurality rule, pre-election polls provide coordination signals which help voters to defeat Condorcet losers.

References

  1. Besley T, Coate S (1997) An economic model of representative democracy. Q J Econ 112:84–94

    Google Scholar 

  2. Condorcet M (1785) Éssai sur l’Application de l’Analyse à la Probabilité des Décisions Rendues à la Pluralité des Voix, Paris

  3. Dummett M (1984) Voting procedures. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  4. Dutta B, Jackson MO, Le Breton M (2001) Strategic candidacy and voting procedures. Econometrica 69:1013–1037

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Dutta B, Jackson MO, Le Breton M (2002) Voting by successive elimination and strategic candidacy. J Econ Theory 103:190–218

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Fishburn PC, Gehrlein WV (1976) Borda’s rule, positional voting and Condorcet’s simple majority principle. Public Choice 28:79–88

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Forsythe R, Myerson RB, Rietz TA, Weber RJ (1993) An experiment on coordination in multi-candidate elections. Soc Choice Welf 10:223–248

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Lepelley D (1993) On the probability of electing the Condorcet loser. Math Soc Sci 25:105–116

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Lepelley D, Merlin V (1998) Choix social positionnel et principe majoritaire. Ann Econ Stat 51:29–48

    Google Scholar 

  10. Lepelley D, Pierron P, Valognes F (2000) Scoring rules, Condorcet efficiency and social homogeneity. Theory Decis 49:175–196

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Moreno B, Puy MS (2003) Plurality Rule Works in Three-Candidate Elections. CentrA, Documento de trabajo E2003/09

  12. Moulin H (1988) Axioms of cooperative decision making. Chapter 9. Econometric Society Monographs no 15, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  13. Osborne MJ, Slivinski A (1996) A model of political competition with citizen-candidates. Q J Econ 111:64–96

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Saari DG (1994) Geometry of voting. Springer, Berlin Heidelberg New York

    Google Scholar 

  15. Saari DG, Valognes F (1999) The geometry of black’s single-peakedness and related conditions. J Math E 32:429–456

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Sanver MR (2002) Scoring rules cannot respect majority in choice and elimination simultaneously. Math Soc Sci 43:151–155

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Woeginger G (2003) A note on scoring rules that respect majority in choice and elimination. Math Soc Sci 46:347–354

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank Pablo Amorós, Carmen Beviá, Vincent Merlin and Matthias Messner for helpful comments and suggestions. We also thank two anonymous referees for their helpful comments. Financial support from Fundación Ramón Areces and the research project SEC2002-01926 are gratefully acknowledged.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to M. Socorro Puy.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Moreno, B., Socorro Puy, M. The scoring rules in an endogenous election. Soc Choice Welfare 25, 115–125 (2005). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-005-0034-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-005-0034-6

Keywords

Navigation