Skip to main content
Log in

Inference to the Best Explanation Is an Important Form of Reasoning in Mathematics

  • Viewpoint
  • Published:
The Mathematical Intelligencer Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Figure 1

Notes

  1. Brown [1, p. 164], [2, p. 48], and Franklin [3, p. 12] have pointed this out.

  2. The arithmetic–geometric mean agm(x,y) is the limit of both of the linked sequences ai and bi, where an+1 = (an + bn)/2, bn+1 = \(\sqrt{{a}_{n}{b}_{n}}\), a0 = x, b0 = y, 1/agm(1,\(\sqrt{2}\)) = 0.8346268… . Borwein and Devlin [4, pp. 4–5] and Rodriguez Villegas [5, p. ix] portray Gauss as justified in regarding his evidence as strongly confirmatory. (My thanks to James Robert Brown for suggesting the former book and several other useful references.) This example of Gauss’s approach is not unusual. In 1817, Gauss wrote (quoted by Gray [6, p. ix]: “It is characteristic of higher arithmetic that many of its most beautiful theorems can be discovered by induction with the greatest of ease but have proofs that lie anywhere but near at hand… .” (Regarding “induction,” see note 3.)

  3. By “inductive,” Pólya is not referring to mathematical induction, which is a form of proof (i.e., deductive reasoning). Rather, Pólya means the kind of reasoning by which hypotheses are confirmed but not proved.

  4. Pólya [7, p.4]. Franklin [8, p. 16] likewise takes this pattern of reasoning to be central.

  5. The philosophy of science literature is full of examples in which a generalization’s making some successful (and no unsuccessful) predictions fails to confirm some of its other, as yet unverified, predictions. Two classic discussions are Goodman [9, pp. 66–83] and Salmon [10].

  6. For the tradition of characterizing some confirmation as operating by IBE, see the surveys and references in Lipton [11] and Lycan [12]. The label “inference to the best explanation” was popularized by Harman [13]. Peirce [14, pp. 5.180–5.212] referred to (very roughly) the same sort of reasoning as “abduction.” IBE has also had its share of opponents, notably van Fraassen [15], Salmon [16], and (more recently) Roche and Sober [17], to which Lange [18] replies.

  7. Darwin [19, p. 421], my emphasis.

  8. The gleaning appeared on page 283 of volume 70, number 454. I am grateful to Roy Sorensen for calling my attention to this example in a lovely unpublished essay.

  9. In Leavitt [21, p. 182], for instance. (This example is also mentioned by Sorensen op. cit.) I will not try here to spell out what it would take for a proof to give a unified uniform treatment of the various cases falling under the theorem being proved. To do so would require an account of natural mathematical properties and kinds (as Baker [22, p. 144] puts it) so that an arbitrary pair of proofs cobbled together does not count as a unified uniform proof of the conjunction of the two theorems proved. My argument for IBE’s role in mathematics will fortunately not depend on any particular account of what it is for a proof in mathematics to be explanatory. I discuss all of these topics (mathematical coincidence, natural mathematical properties and kinds, explanation in mathematics, unification, …) in greater detail in Lange [23].

  10. I discuss this example more fully in Lange [23], where I also refer briefly to some earlier discussions of this example’s methodological lessons.

  11. For instance, suppose one circle is centered at (0, 20) with radius 16 and the other circle is centered at (0, –15) with radius 9. These circles intersect nowhere in the Euclidean plane. But their equations are x2 + (y – 20)2 = 162 and x2 + (y + 15)2 = 92, which have common solutions (12i, 0) and (–12i, 0). This example generalizes (though the confirmation that I am characterizing as IBE does not depend on the mathematicians’ having already proved that this example generalizes, since the mathematicians could merely have confirmed that it does). Let the two circles be centered at (x1, y1) and (x2, y2) with radii r1 and r2, respectively. To keep the following expressions relatively compact, let L be the distance between the centers and let A be the area of a “triangle” with sides of lengths r1, r2, and L. Then the circles’ two points of intersection (x, y) are \(x = \frac{{x_{1} + x_{2} }}{2} + \frac{{r_{1}^{2} - r_{2}^{2} }}{{2L^{2} }} \left( {x_{2} - x_{1} } \right) \pm 2A\frac{{y_{2} - y_{1} }}{{L^{2} }} ,\) \(y = \frac{{y_{1} + y_{2} }}{2} + \frac{{r_{1}^{2} - r_{2}^{2} }}{{2L^{2} }} \left( {y_{2} - y_{1} } \right) \mp 2A\frac{{x_{2} - x_{1} }}{{L^{2} }}.\) These expressions apply whether the two circles intersect at two points in the Cartesian plane or none. Imaginary coordinates for points of intersection arise when there is no Euclidean triangle with sides of lengths r1, r2, and L, which occurs when L > r1 + r2 (case (b) in the figure) or L < |r1 \(-\) r2| (case (c) in the figure). In all cases, A is to be evaluated by Heron’s formula: \(A = \frac{1}{4} \sqrt {\left( {L + r_{1} + r_{2} } \right)\left( {L + r_{1} - r_{2} } \right)\left( {L - r_{1} + r_{2} } \right)\left( { - L + r_{1} + r_{2} } \right)} .\) This formula gives imaginary A for an impossible triangle.

  12. For another example, see the discussion of Desargues’s theorem in Lange [23, pp. 314–346].

References

  1. James Robert Brown 2008. Philosophy of Mathematics: A Contemporary Introduction to the World of Proofs and Pictures, 2nd ed. London: Routledge.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  2. James Robert Brown 2017. Proofs and Guarantees. The Mathematical Intelligencer 39(4): 47–50.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  3. James Franklin 2013. Non-Deductive Logic in Mathematics: The Probability of Conjectures. In Andrew Aberdein and Ian J. Dove (eds.), The Argument of Mathematics. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 11–29.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  4. Jonathan Borwein and Keith Devlin 2009. The Computer as Crucible: An Introduction to Experimental Mathematics. Wellesley: AK Peters.

  5. Fernando Rodriguez Villegas 2007. Experimental Number Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  6. Jeremy Gray 2018. A History of Abstract Algebra. Cham: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  7. George Pólya 1954. Mathematics and Plausible Reasoning, vol. 2: Patterns of Plausible Inference. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  8. James Franklin 2016. Logical Probability and the Strength of Mathematical Conjectures. The Mathematical Intelligencer 38(3): 14–19.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  9. Nelson Goodman 1983. Fact, Fiction and Forecast, 4th edition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Wesley Salmon 1975. Confirmation and Relevance. In Induction. Probability, and Confirmation, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. VI. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 3–36.

  11. Peter Lipton 2004. Inference to the Best Explanation, 2nd ed. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  12. William G. Lycan 2002. Explanation and Epistemology. In Paul Moser (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 408–433.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  13. Gilbert Harman 1965. Inference to the Best Explanation. Philosophical Review 74: 88–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Charles Sanders Peirce 1931. Collected Papers, ed. C. Hartshorn and P. Weiss. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  15. Bas van Fraassen 1989. Laws and Symmetry. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  16. Wesley Salmon 2001. Explanation and Confirmation: A Bayesian Critique of Inference to the Best Explanation. In Giora Hon and Sam Rakover (eds.), Explanation: Theoretical Approaches and Applications. Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 61–92.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  17. William Roche and Elliott Sober 2013. Explanatoriness Is Evidentially Irrelevant, or Inference to the Best Explanation Meets Bayesian Confirmation Theory. Analysis 73: 659−668.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  18. Marc Lange 2017. The Evidential Relevance of Explanatoriness: A Reply to Roche and Sober. Analysis 77(2): 303–312.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  19. Charles Darwin 1889. The Origin of Species, 6th ed. London: Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Eric Nummela 1987. No Coincidence. Mathematical Gazette 71(456):147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. David Leavitt 2007. The Indian Clerk. New York: Bloomsbury USA.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Alan Baker 2009. Mathematical Accidents and the Ends of Explanation. In Otávio Bueno and Øystein Linnebo (eds.), New Waves in the Philosophy of Mathematics. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 137–159.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  23. Marc Lange 2017. Because Without Cause. New York: Oxford University Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  24. J. D. van der Waals 1890. The Continuity of the Liquid and Gaseous States of Matter. In Physical Memoirs Selected and Translated from Foreign Sources, vol. 1. London: Taylor and Francis, pp. 333–496.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Michael Spivak 1980. Calculus, 2nd ed. Berkeley: Publish or Perish.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  26. Gilbert Strang 1992. Calculus. Wellesley: Wellesley-Cambridge Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marc Lange.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

The Viewpoint column offers readers of the Mathematical Intelligencer the opportunity to write about any issue of interest to the international mathematical community. Disagreement and controversy are welcome. The views and opinions expressed here, however, are exclusively those of the author. The publisher and editors-in-chief do not endorse them or accept responsibility for them. Articles for Viewpoint should be submitted to the editors-in-chief, Karen Parshall (khp3k@virginia.edu) and Sergei Tabachnikov (sot2@psu.edu).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lange, M. Inference to the Best Explanation Is an Important Form of Reasoning in Mathematics. Math Intelligencer 44, 32–38 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00283-021-10112-7

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00283-021-10112-7

Navigation