Skip to main content
Log in

Divide the dollar and conquer more: sequential bargaining and risk aversion

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
International Journal of Game Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We analyze the problem of dividing a fixed amount of a single commodity between two players on the basis of the Nash bargaining solution (NBS). For one-shot negotiations, a cornerstone result of Roth (Axiomatic models of bargaining. Springer, Berlin, 1979) establishes that the more risk averse player will obtain less than half the total amount. In the present paper, we assume that the bargaining procedure occurs over several rounds. In each round, an increasing share of the total amount is negotiated over in accordance with the NBS, the disagreement point being determined by the outcome of the previous round. In line with Roth’s result, the final amount received by the more risk averse player is still bounded by half the total amount. As a new feature, however, this player does not lose from bargaining for more rounds if his opponent exhibits non-increasing absolute risk aversion. What is more, both players’ risk profiles become essentially irrelevant if successive bargaining takes place over sufficiently small commodity increments. Each player then gets approximately half of the commodity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Kihlstrom et al. (1981) have generalized this finding to other bargaining solutions, such as the one proposed by Kalai and Smorodinsky (1975). Regarding the empirical support for these theoretical results, see Murnighan et al. (1988). For variations of the baseline model where risk aversion may be an advantage, see Roth and Rothblum (1982), Safra and Zilcha (1993), Volij and Winter (2002), and Rausser and Simon (2016).

  2. Even though neither the underlying bargaining problem nor the NBS feature any stochastic component, risk in our setting can be interpreted as arising from each player’s ignorance of his opponent’s actions (Roth 1985). The degree of concavity of the players’ utility functions can then be seen as a measure of their risk aversion.

  3. In the language of behavioral economics, this means that the players’ reference points are constant throughout the entire negotiation, thereby giving rise to a form of mental accounting (Kahneman and Tversky 1979; Thaler 1985).

  4. The term salami tactics was first coined by the Hungarian Communist Party to describe their step-by-step strategy to seize power (szalámitaktika, see, e.g., Mevius 2005).

  5. The fact that in such situations the total commodity value is unknown in advance does not alter our model, since we assume that players are backward-looking (taking into account past gains) and not strategic.

  6. Multi-round bargaining procedures similar to ours have also been studied from a non-cooperative viewpoint based on Rubinstein’s (1982) alternating offers model (see e.g. Fershtman 1990; John and Raith 1999, 2001; Kalandrakis 2010).

  7. For non-cooperative foundations of the Raiffa solution, see Myerson (2013) and Acharya and Ortner (2016).

  8. Theorem 1 therein.

  9. Theorem 5 therein, generalized to arbitrary \(x^0\ge 0.\)

  10. We refer to Friend and Blume (1975), Levy (1994) or Wik et al. (2004) for such analyses, as well as to Eisenhauer (2007) and the references therein for deviations from these findings.

  11. Define the function \(f(\tilde{u}_A,\tilde{u}_B):=\tilde{x}_A(\tilde{u}_A)+\tilde{x}_B(\tilde{u}_B),\) where \(\tilde{x}_i(\cdot )\) denotes the inverse of the utility function \(u_i(\cdot ),\) \(i=A,B.\) This enables us to rewrite the feasibility set S,  see Eq. (1), as \(S=\{(\tilde{u}_A,\tilde{u}_B) | f(\tilde{u}_A,\tilde{u}_B)\le Q\}.\) By comparison, our setting can thus be cast in the formulation considered by O’Neill et al. (2004). It is then straightforward to see that \(\phi _i(\cdot )\) defined by \(\phi _i(Q):=u_i(Q/2),\) \(i=A,B,\) is the unique solution to their differential equation.

  12. Note that since \(u_i\) (\(i=A,B\)) is strictly increasing and concave, \(u_i'(x)=0\) can only occur at \(x=Q,\) if at all.

  13. As an example, we consider a one-round protocol over an amount \(Q>0\) and let \(u_A(x)=\lambda {x}^\alpha \) and \(u_B(x)=x^\beta \) be a pair of utility functions. It is readily seen that they satisfy Condition (RA) for \(\alpha <\beta \) and \(\lambda >0.\) If we consider the PR defined by \(u_A(x^*)=u_B(Q-x^*)\) (i.e., the so-called Egalitarian Solution), with \(x_A^0=x_B^0=0\) and \(x^*=x^*(\lambda , Q),\) then a computation shows that \(\frac{\partial x^*}{\partial \lambda }\le 0.\) Hence, \(\lim _{\lambda \searrow 0} x^*\) exists. It then follows from the definition of the PR that \(\lim _{\lambda \searrow 0}x^*=Q.\) Thus, for sufficiently small \(\lambda ,\) the more risk averse player actually obtains almost all of the commodity, in particular more than half.

  14. This trivially generalizes the bargaining procedure introduced in Sect. 2.3, where we assumed that the initial disagreement point was (0, 0).

  15. The \(M_i^\#\) do depend on \(\varepsilon ,\) though. In particular, if and only if \(u_i\) (\(i=A,B\)) is not differentiable at 0 do these constants exhibit blow-up behavior for \(\varepsilon \searrow 0.\)

  16. Like the \(M^\#_i,\) the constants \(m_A'\) and \(m_B'\) do depend on \(\varepsilon .\) In particular, \(\lim _{\varepsilon \searrow 0} m_i' = 0\) if \(u_i'(Q)=0\) (\(i=A,B\)).

  17. If the utility functions \(u_A,\) \(u_B\) have singular derivatives at zero, convergence in the sense of Corollary 2 can still be proved if Conditions (RA) and (N-IARA) are imposed in addition. We provide here a sketch of the proof of this claim. Fix \(\varepsilon >0\) and consider a sequence of protocols \(({\mathcal {P}}^M)_{M\ge 0}=((q_n^M)_{0\le n \le N^M})_{M\ge 0}\) with vanishing meshes, i.e., \(\lim _{M\rightarrow \infty } {\mathrm {mesh}}({\mathcal {P}}^M)=0.\) For each M,  we separate all terms \(y_n^M\) with n such that \(q^M_n<\varepsilon / 2\) instead of merely \(y_1\) as in (39). If M is sufficiently large, there is always a maximal \(n^*,\) with \(1\le n^*\le N^M,\) such that \(\varepsilon /4<q_{n^*}^M<\varepsilon /2.\) Then, by Theorem 1 and the monotonicity of the NBS w.r.t. the amount being bargained over, it follows that \(0<\sigma _* \le \sum _{n \le n^*} y_n^M < \varepsilon /2,\) where \(\sigma _*\) is the outcome for player A of a one-shot negotiation over \(\varepsilon /4.\) Replacing \(\sigma _1\) by \(\sigma _*\) in Definitions (35) and (36) then enables the estimation of all \(y_{n}^M ,\) with \(n^*<n\le N^M,\) along the lines of the proof of Theorem 2. Note that, by construction, the analogue of the middle term in (40) then vanishes as \(M\rightarrow \infty .\)

References

  • Acharya A, Ortner J (2016) Policy reform. Mimeo, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow KJ (1965) Aspects of the theory of risk bearing. Academic Bookstores, Helsinki

    Google Scholar 

  • Diskin A, Koppel M, Samet D (2011) Generalized Raiffa solutions. Games Econ Behav 73(2):452–458

    Google Scholar 

  • Eisenhauer JG (2007) Reviewed work: measuring risk aversion, by Donald J. Meyer and Jack Meyer. J Risk Insur 74(4):898–904

    Google Scholar 

  • Fershtman C (1990) The importance of the agenda in bargaining. Games Econ Behav 2(3):224–238

    Google Scholar 

  • Friend I, Blume ME (1975) The demand for risky assets. Am Econ Rev 65(5):900–922

    Google Scholar 

  • John R, Raith MG (1999) Strategic step-by-step negotiation. J Econ 70(2):127–154

    Google Scholar 

  • John R, Raith MG (2001) Optimizing multi-stage negotiations. J Econ Behav Org 45(2):155–173

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D, Tversky A (1979) prospect theory: an analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica 47(2):263–291

    Google Scholar 

  • Kalai E (1977) Proportional solutions to bargaining situations: interpersonal utility comparisons. Econometrica 45(7):1623–1630

    Google Scholar 

  • Kalai E, Smorodinsky M (1975) Other solutions to Nash’s bargaining problem. Econometrica 43(3):513–518

    Google Scholar 

  • Kalandrakis T (2010) Minimum winning coalitions and endogenous status quo. Int J Game Theory 39(4):617–643

    Google Scholar 

  • Kihlstrom RE, Roth AE, Schmeidler D (1981) Risk aversion and solutions to Nash’s bargaining problem. In: Moeschlein, Pallaschke D (eds) Game theory and mathematical economics. North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp 65–71

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy H (1994) Absolute and relative risk aversion: an experimental study. J Risk Uncertain 8(3):289–307

    Google Scholar 

  • Mevius M (2005) Agents of Moscow: the Hungarian Communist Party and the origins of socialist patriotism, 1941–1953. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Murnighan JK, Roth AE, Schoumaker F (1988) Risk aversion in bargaining: an experimental study. J Risk Uncertain 1(1):101–124

    Google Scholar 

  • Myerson RB (2013) Game theory. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Nash JF (1950) The bargaining problem. Econometrica 18(2):155–162

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill B, Samet D, Wiener Z, Winter E (2004) Bargaining with an agenda. Games Econ Behav 48(1):139–153

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters H, Van Damme E (1991) Characterizing the Nash and Raiffa bargaining solutions by disagreement point axioms. Math Oper Res 16(3):447–461

    Google Scholar 

  • Pratt JW (1964) Risk aversion in the small and in the large. Econometrica 32(1):122–136

    Google Scholar 

  • Raiffa H (1953) Arbitration schemes for generalized two-person games. Ann Math Stud 28:361–387

    Google Scholar 

  • Rausser GC, Simon LK (2016) Nash bargaining and risk aversion. Games Econ Behav 95:1–9

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth AE (1979) Axiomatic models of bargaining. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth AE (1985) A note on risk aversion in a perfect equilibrium model of bargaining. Econometrica 53(1):207–211

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth AE, Rothblum UG (1982) Risk aversion and Nash’s solution for bargaining games with risky outcomes. Econometrica 50(3):639–647

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein A (1982) Perfect equilibrium in a bargaining model. Econometrica 50(1):97–109

    Google Scholar 

  • Safra Z, Zilcha I (1993) Bargaining solutions without the expected utility hypothesis. Games Econ Behav 5(2):288–306

    Google Scholar 

  • Thaler R (1985) Mental accounting and consumer choice. Mark Sci 4(3):199–214

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson W (1987) Monotonicity of bargaining solutions with respect to the disagreement point. J Econ Theory 42(1):50–58

    Google Scholar 

  • Volij O, Winter E (2002) On risk aversion and bargaining outcomes. Games Econ Behav 41(1):120–140

    Google Scholar 

  • Wik M, Aragie Kebede T, Bergland O, Holden ST (2004) On the measurement of risk aversion from experimental data. Appl Econ 36(21):2443–2451

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Conversations with César Martinelli, Hans Gersbach, Heinrich Nax, Oscar Volij, and Eyal Winter, as well as comments from participants in the 2016 UECE Game Theory Lisbon Meetings, the 2017 Conference on Economic Design held in York, and a seminar in Barcelona are gratefully acknowledged. We are also thankful to two anonymous reviewers and the Associated Editor for their comments and suggestions, which helped to improve the paper. All errors are our own.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Philip Grech.

Appendix

Appendix

We first formally present the alternative approach to the sequential bargaining procedure introduced in Sect. 2. We then prove Theorems 1 and 2.

1.1 Alternative approach to the sequential bargaining procedure

To complement the point of view taken in the main body of our paper (Point of View 1: stock-based), we present here an equivalent alternative (Point of View 2: increment-based). To that end, with \(y_0^{\mathcal {P}}=0,\) we define recursively for n,  with \(1\le n\le N,\) the outcome

$$\begin{aligned} y^{{\mathcal {P}}}_n:=x^*(u_{A,n},u_{B,n};0,0;q_n-q_{n-1}), \end{aligned}$$

where \(u_{A,n}, u_{B,n}\) are shifted utility functions defined by

$$\begin{aligned} u_{A,n}(y):= & {} u_A(y+\sigma _{n-1}) -u_A(\sigma _{n-1}),\end{aligned}$$
(7)
$$\begin{aligned} u_{B,n}(y):= & {} u_B(y + q_{n-1}-\sigma _{n-1})-u_B(q_{n-1}-\sigma _{n-1}), \end{aligned}$$
(8)

and \(\sigma _n^{\mathcal {P}} := \sum _{i=1}^n y_n^{{\mathcal {P}}} \) sums the outcomes of all individual rounds up to n for player A.

Figure 3 illustrates the changing utility function of player A from Point of View 2 for the three-round bargaining protocol \({\mathcal {P}}^3\) used in Fig. 1.

Fig. 3
figure 3

Left Utility functions of player A in each round of \({\mathcal {P}}^3.\) Player B’s utility function is simply linear. Right The bargaining sets and outcomes in each of the three rounds. As bargaining is now viewed as happening over increments, the nested structure of Fig. 1 is no longer present

From this second point of view, the two players bargain in the nth round over the amount \(q_n-q_{n-1}.\) This may or may not be larger than the amount bargained over in any of the previous rounds. The focus is now on the incremental variable \(y^{{\mathcal {P}}}_n,\) with the state variable \(\sigma _{n}^{{\mathcal {P}}}\) playing merely an auxiliary role. If the two players do not come to an agreement, they obtain nothing in that round and the negotiation ends with what they obtained in all previous rounds, yielding the outcome vector \((\sigma ^{\mathcal {P}}_{n-1}, q_{n-1}-\sigma ^{\mathcal {P}}_{n-1}).\) This explains the shifts in Eqs. (7) and (8). As opposed to Point of View 1, the disagreement point is now the same in every round—namely zero—but the players’ attitude towards risk is not, as it depends on the outcome of the previous rounds. To be explicit about the evolution of the increments \(y^{{\mathcal {P}}}_n,\) note that for all n,  with \(1\le n \le N,\) Eq. (2) now takes the form

$$\begin{aligned}&u'_A\left( y_{n}^{{\mathcal {P}}}+\sigma _{n-1}^{{\mathcal {P}}}\right) \cdot \left[ u_B\left( q_{n}-y_{n}^{{\mathcal {P}}} -\sigma _{n-1}^{{\mathcal {P}}}\right) -u_B\left( q_{n-1} -\sigma _{n-1}^{{\mathcal {P}}}\right) \right] \nonumber \\&\quad =\left[ u_A\left( y_{n}^{{\mathcal {P}}}+ \sigma _{n-1}^{{\mathcal {P}}}\right) -u_A\left( \sigma _{n-1}^{{\mathcal {P}}}\right) \right] \cdot u'_B\left( q_{n}-y_{n}^{{\mathcal {P}}} -\sigma _{n-1}^{{\mathcal {P}}}\right) . \end{aligned}$$
(9)

Finally, we point out that from Eqs. (4) and (9), it follows that the two points of view are indeed equivalent, as for all n,  with \(1\le n\le N,\) we have

$$\begin{aligned} x^{\mathcal {P}}_n=\sigma _n^{\mathcal {P}} \end{aligned}$$

and

$$\begin{aligned} y_n^{\mathcal {P}}=x_n^{\mathcal {P}}-x_{n-1}^{\mathcal {P}}. \end{aligned}$$

1.2 Proof of Theorem 1

Part (i) Using Point of View 1 (stock-based, cf. p. 7), it suffices to show that for all n,  with \(1\le n \le N,\)

$$\begin{aligned} x_n^{{\mathcal {P}}}\le \frac{q_n}{2}. \end{aligned}$$
(10)

To demonstrate (10) we use induction on n. The case \(n=1\) follows immediately from Corollary 1. Now assume that \(1<n\le N\) and \(x_{n-1}^{{\mathcal {P}}}\le {q_{n-1}}/{2}.\) By Thomson’s theorem (cf. p. 6), we may assume without loss of generality that \(x_{n-1}^{{\mathcal {P}}}= {q_{n-1}}/{2},\) so that the disagreement point in the \(n\text {th}\) round is \(({q_{n-1}}/{2}, {q_{n-1}}/{2}).\) An application of Corollary 1 then yields the claim.

Part (ii) To establish the desired inequality, it suffices to restrict our attention to a comparison of the outcomes of two bargaining protocols, where one is obtained from the other by splitting one round into two rounds, and then to apply a recursive argument to establish the desired relation between \(x^{\mathcal {P}}_N\) and \(x^{{\mathcal {P}}'}_{N'}.\) Without loss of generality, we may assume that \({\mathcal {P}}=(q_n)_{0\le n\le N}=: {\mathcal {P}}^N\) consists of \(N+1\) elements and that \({{\mathcal {P}}'}=(q'_n)_{0\le n\le N+1}=:{\mathcal {P}}^{N+1}\) consists of \(N+2\) elements, with \({\mathcal {P}}^N={\mathcal {P}}^{N+1}\setminus \{q\}\) (as sets) for some \(q\in {\mathcal {P}}^{N+1}.\) Our proof is based on an induction on N.

\(\underline{\textit{Base case}~(N=1){:}}\)

Let \({\mathcal {P}}^1=(0,Q)\) and \({\mathcal {P}}^{2}=(0,q,Q),\) with \(0<q<Q.\) We need to show that

$$\begin{aligned} x_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^1} =y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^1} \le y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+y_2^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}=x_2^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}. \end{aligned}$$
(11)

Using Point of View 2, we start by writing down the governing equations for \({\mathcal {P}}^1\) and \({\mathcal {P}}^2.\) On the one hand, regarding \({\mathcal {P}}^1,\) the bargaining happens in one single round and thus Eq. (9) simplifies to

$$\begin{aligned} u'_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^1}\right) \cdot u_B\left( Q-y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^1}\right) = u_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^1}\right) \cdot u'_B\left( Q-y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^1}\right) . \end{aligned}$$
(12)

On the other hand, as for \({\mathcal {P}}^2,\) where the bargaining takes place in two consecutive rounds, Eq. (9) translates into the following pair of coupled equations for \(y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\) and \(y_2^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\) (recall that we have assumed \(u_A(0)=u_B(0)=0\)):

$$\begin{aligned} u'_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \cdot u_B\left( q-y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) = u_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \cdot u'_B\left( q-y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \end{aligned}$$
(13)

and

$$\begin{aligned}&u'_A\left( y_{2}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \cdot \left[ u_B\left( Q-y_{2}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2} -y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) -u_B\left( q -y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \right] \nonumber \\&\quad =\left[ u_A\left( y_{2}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+ y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) -u_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \right] \cdot u'_B\left( Q-y_{2}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2} -y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) . \end{aligned}$$
(14)

To manipulate these equations efficiently, it will come in handy to introduce the inverse boldness function

$$\begin{aligned} g_i : = \frac{u_i}{u'_i} =: \frac{1}{b_i },\quad i= A,B. \end{aligned}$$
(15)

Note that \(g_i\) is well-defined, positive, and continuous on (0, Q] because \(u_i\) is a strictly increasing element of \(C^2((0,Q])\cap C([0,Q])\) (\(i=A,B\)). Equation (12) can then be rewritten as

$$\begin{aligned} g_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^1}\right) =g_B\left( Q-y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^1}\right) . \end{aligned}$$
(16)

Similarly, Eqs. (13) and (14) become

$$\begin{aligned} g_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) =g_B\left( q-y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \end{aligned}$$
(17)

and

$$\begin{aligned}&u'_A\left( y_{2}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \cdot \left[ u'_B\left( Q-y_{2}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2} -y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \right. \nonumber \\&\qquad \left. \cdot \, g_B\left( Q-y_{2}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2} -y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) -u'_B\left( q -y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \cdot g_B \left( q -y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \right] \nonumber \\&\quad =\left[ u'_A\left( y_{2}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \cdot g_A\left( y_{2}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \right. \nonumber \\&\qquad \left. -\,u'_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \cdot g_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \right] \cdot u'_B\left( Q-y_{2}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2} -y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) , \end{aligned}$$
(18)

respectively. Since \(u_A', u_B'>0,\) Eq. (18), can be further rewritten with the help of Eq. (17) as

$$\begin{aligned}&g_B\left( Q-\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+y_{2}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2} \right) \right) -g_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+y_{2}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \\&\qquad -\, g_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \cdot \left[ \frac{u'_B\left( q-y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) }{u'_B\left( Q- \left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+y_{2}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \right) }-\frac{u'_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) }{u'_A \left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+y_{2}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) }\right] =0, \end{aligned}$$

which is equivalent to

$$\begin{aligned} h \left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+y_{2}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2} \right) =0, \end{aligned}$$

where \(h\in C((0,Q])\) is defined by

$$\begin{aligned} h(w):= g_B(Q-w)-g_A(w)-g_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \cdot \left[ \frac{u'_B\left( q-y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) }{u'_B(Q-w)} -\frac{u'_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) }{u'_A(w)}\right] .\nonumber \\ \end{aligned}$$
(19)

By uniqueness of the NBS, \(h(w)=0\) admits only one solution in (0, Q],  namely \(w=y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+y_{2}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}.\)

To complete the proof of the base case (\(N=1\)), it remains to show the following claim.

Claim Assuming \(y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^1}\ne y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+y_2^{{\mathcal {P}}^2},\) the following inequalities hold:

$$\begin{aligned}&h\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^1}\right) >0,\end{aligned}$$
(20)
$$\begin{aligned}&h\left( y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+Q-q\right) <0, \end{aligned}$$
(21)
$$\begin{aligned}&y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^1}<y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+Q-q. \end{aligned}$$
(22)

Indeed, if \(y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^1}= y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+y_2^{{\mathcal {P}}^2},\) (11) trivially holds. Otherwise, (20)–(22) allow the application of the Intermediate Value Theorem. The zero of h,  namely \(w=y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+y_{2}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\), then has to lie in the interval \((y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^1},y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+Q-q) \subset (y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^1},Q],\) and thus the base case (\(N=1\)) follows.

We now turn to the proof of the three inequalities of the claim.

Proof of (20)

From Eqs. (16) and (19), we obtain

$$\begin{aligned} h(y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^1})= & {} g_B\left( Q-y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^1}\right) -g_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^1}\right) \nonumber \\&-\,g_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \cdot \left[ \frac{u'_B\left( q-y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) }{u'_B\left( Q-y_{1}^{\mathcal { P}^1}\right) }-\frac{u'_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) }{u'_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^1}\right) }\right] \\= & {} -\,g_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \cdot \left[ \frac{u'_B\left( q-y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) }{u'_B \left( Q-y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^1}\right) }-\frac{u'_A \left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) }{u'_A \left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^1}\right) }\right] . \end{aligned}$$

This last expression is positive if the expression in square brackets is negative. Using Eqs. (12) and (13), the inequality in (20) is thus equivalent to

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{u_B\left( q-y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) }{u_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) }< \frac{u_B\left( Q-y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^1}\right) }{u_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^1}\right) }. \end{aligned}$$
(23)

Consider now the function k defined on the interval [qQ] by

$$\begin{aligned} k(r):=\frac{u_B\left( r-y_{1}(r)\right) }{u_A\left( y_{1}(r)\right) }. \end{aligned}$$
(24)

Here, \(y_{1}(r)\) denotes the outcome for player A when bargaining over an amount r in a single round takes place in accordance with the NBS with disagreement point (0, 0)—as captured by the bargaining problem \((u_A,u_B;0,0;r).\) In particular, we have \(y_1(q)=y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\) and \(y_1(Q)=y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^1},\) connecting Eq. (24) with Eq. (23). The defining equation for \(y_1(r)\) is derived from Eq. (2) using Definition (15):

$$\begin{aligned} b_B(r-y_1(r))=\frac{u_B'(r-y_1(r))}{u_B(r-y_1(r))}= \frac{u'_A(y_1(r))}{u_A(y_1(r))}=b_A(y_1(r)). \end{aligned}$$
(25)

Using Definitions (3) and (15), and because \(b_i(x)>0\) for \(x\in [0,Q),\) a direct computation shows that

$$\begin{aligned} b'_i(x)=-a_i (x)b_i(x) -b_i^2(x)<0,\quad \text {for } x\in (0,Q] \text { and } i=A,B. \end{aligned}$$
(26)

Hence the Implicit Function Theorem can be applied to Eq. (25), yielding that \(y_1\) and therefore also k are elements of \(C^2([q,Q]).\)

To show (23), it is sufficient to demonstrate that the derivative of k is non-negative and that k is not a constant function. If it were a constant on [qQ],  we would have an equality in (23) instead of a strict inequality, meaning that \(h(y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^1})=0.\) In this case, \(y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^1}\) would be a zero of h,  thereby implying that \(y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^1}=y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+y_2^{{\mathcal {P}}^2},\) which would contradict the assumption that \(y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^1}\ne y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+y_2^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}.\) To compute the derivative of k,  we use the chain rule as well as Eq. (25) and arrive at

$$\begin{aligned} k'(r)= \frac{u'_B(r-y_1(r)) }{u_A\left( y_{1} (r)\right) } \left( 1- 2 y_1'(r)\right) ,\quad \hbox {for }r\in [q,Q]. \end{aligned}$$

To demonstrate (23), it suffices to show that

$$\begin{aligned} y_1'(r)\le \frac{1}{2},\quad \hbox {for }r\in [q,Q]. \end{aligned}$$
(27)

For all \(r\in [q,Q],\) we thus compute

$$\begin{aligned} y_1'(r)= & {} \frac{b'_B(r-y_1(r))}{b'_B(r-y_1(r))+b'_A(y_1(r)) } \\= & {} \frac{-a_B(r-y_1(r))b_B(r-y_1(r)) -b^2_B(r-y_1(r))}{-a_B(r-y_1(r))b_B(r-y_1(r))-b^2_B(r-y_1(r))-a_A(y_1(r)) b_A(y_1(r))-b^2_A(y_1(r))} \\= & {} \frac{a_B(r-y_1(r))b_A(y_1(r)) +b^2_A(y_1(r))}{ (a_B(r-y_1(r))+a_A(y_1(r))) b_A(y_1(r))+2 b^2_A(y_1(r))} \\= & {} \frac{a_B(r-y_1(r)) +b_A(y_1(r))}{ a_B(r-y_1(r))+a_A(y_1(r))+2 b_A(y_1(r))}, \end{aligned}$$

where the first and third equality hold by Eq. (25) and the Implicit Function Theorem, the second by Eq. (26), and the last because \(b_A(y_1(r))>0\) for all \(r\in [q,Q].\) Hence, (27) is equivalent to

$$\begin{aligned} a_A \left( y_1(r)\right) \ge a_B \left( r-y_1(r)\right) ,\quad \hbox {for }r\in [q,Q]. \end{aligned}$$

But the latter condition must hold because for all \(r\in [q,Q],\)

$$\begin{aligned} a_A \left( y_1(r)\right) \ge a_B \left( y_1(r)\right) \ge a_B \left( r-y_1(r)\right) . \end{aligned}$$

The first inequality is due to Condition (RA). The second inequality holds because player B satisfies (N-IARA) and because Corollary 1 guarantees that \(y_1(r)\le r-y_1(r)\) for all \(r\in [q,Q].\)

Proof of (21)

Using Eq. (17) and the fact that \(u_A\) is strictly increasing, we obtain, after some straightforward algebra, that

$$\begin{aligned} h\left( y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+Q-q\right)= & {} g_B\left( q-y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^2} \right) -g_A\left( y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+Q-q\right) \\&-\,g_A\left( y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) \cdot \left[ 1-\frac{u'_A\left( y_{1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) }{u'_A\left( y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+Q-q)\right) }\right] \\= & {} \frac{u_A\left( y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}\right) -u_A \left( y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+Q-q\right) }{u_A'\left( y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+Q-q\right) } < 0. \end{aligned}$$

Proof of (22)

Consider the function \(v\in C^2([q,Q]),\) where

$$\begin{aligned} v(r):=y_1(r)+Q-r. \end{aligned}$$

It follows immediately from (27) that

$$\begin{aligned} v'(r)< 0,\quad \hbox {for all }r\in [q,Q]. \end{aligned}$$

Hence, because \(q<Q,\)

$$\begin{aligned} y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^1}= & {} y_1(Q)=y_1(Q)+Q-Q = v(Q) < v(q)= y_1(q)+Q-q\\= & {} y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}^2}+Q-q, \end{aligned}$$

as desired.

\(\underline{{ Induction~step}~(N \rightarrow N+1){:}}\)

We assume now that for any pair of utility functions \(u_A\) and \(u_B\) satisfying the assumptions of Part (ii) of Theorem 1, we have

$$\begin{aligned} x_{N-1}^{\mathcal {\tilde{P}}} =\sum _{n=1}^{N-1} y_{n}^{\mathcal {\tilde{P}}}\le \sum _{n=1}^{N} y_{n}^{\mathcal {\tilde{P'}}} =x_{N}^{\mathcal {\tilde{P'}}}, \end{aligned}$$

where \(\mathcal {\tilde{P}}=(\tilde{q}_n)_{0\le n \le N-1}\) and \(\mathcal {\tilde{P}'}=(\tilde{q}'_n)_{0\le n \le N}\) are arbitrary protocols over an arbitrary amount \(\tilde{Q}>0,\) with the sole restriction that \(\tilde{{\mathcal {P}}}'\) is finer than \(\tilde{{\mathcal {P}}}.\) Using the definitions introduced in the beginning of the proof of Part (ii) of Theorem 1, we distinguish two cases.

Case 1: \(q_1\ne q'_1.\)

In this case, the first round of protocol \({\mathcal {P}}={\mathcal {P}}^N\) corresponds to the first two rounds of protocol \({{\mathcal {P}}'}={\mathcal {P}}^{N+1}.\) Figure 4 illustrates this.

Fig. 4
figure 4

Illustration of case 1

For both bargaining protocols \({\mathcal {P}}\) and \({{\mathcal {P}}'},\) the negotiation for the last \(N-1\) rounds may be described by a single protocol \(\tilde{{\mathcal {P}}}:=(\tilde{q}_n)_{0\le n \le N-1}\) with the total amount \(\tilde{Q}:=Q-q_1=Q-q'_2>0,\) where \(\tilde{q}_n:=q_{n+1}=q'_{n+2}\) for \(n>1.\)Footnote 14 However, the initial disagreement point \(x_0^{\tilde{{\mathcal {P}}}}\) differs: it is \(x_0^{\tilde{{\mathcal {P}}}}=x_1^{\mathcal {P}}\) in the case of \({\mathcal {P}}\) and \(x_0^{\tilde{{\mathcal {P}}}}=x_2^{{\mathcal {P}}'}\) in the case of \({{\mathcal {P}}'}.\) Since we know from the base case (\(N=1\)) that \(x_1^{\mathcal {P}}\le x_2^{{\mathcal {P}}'},\) an iterated application of Thomson’s theorem (cf. p. 6) yields \(x_N^{\mathcal {P}} \le x_{N+1}^{{\mathcal {P}}'}.\)

Case 2: \(q_1= q'_1.\)

In this case, the first round for both protocols \({\mathcal {P}}={\mathcal {P}}^N\) and \({{\mathcal {P}}'}={\mathcal {P}}^{N+1}\) is the same, i.e., \(q_1= q_1'.\) This implies that

$$\begin{aligned} x_1^{\mathcal {P}}=y_1^{\mathcal {P}}= y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}'}=x_1^{{\mathcal {P}}'}. \end{aligned}$$

It is useful to think of the divisions of the remaining amount \(\tilde{Q}:=Q-q_1=Q-q_1'\) as protocols in their own right, so that \({\mathcal {P}}\) is replaced by \(\mathcal {\tilde{P}}=(\tilde{q}_n)_{0\le n \le N-1}\), where \(\tilde{q}_0=0\) and \(\tilde{q}_n:=q_{n+1}-q_1\) for \(1\le n\le N-1.\) Similarly, \({{\mathcal {P}}'}\) is replaced by \(\mathcal {\tilde{P}'}=(\tilde{q}'_n)_{0\le n \le N},\) where \(\tilde{q}'_0=0\) and \(\tilde{q}'_n:=q'_{n+1}-q'_1\) for \(1\le n\le N.\) By construction, both \(\mathcal {\tilde{P}}\) and \(\mathcal {\tilde{P}'}\) are protocols over \(\tilde{Q}\) and, moreover, \(\mathcal {\tilde{P}'}\) is finer than \(\mathcal {\tilde{P}}\) by exactly one subdivision. Figure 5 illustrates this.

Fig. 5
figure 5

Illustration of case 2

To stay within the framework in which we can apply our induction hypothesis, we need to shift the corresponding utility functions appropriately. Namely, we use \(u_{i,2}(y)\) instead of \(u_i=u_{i,1}(y),\) \(i=A,B\) (cf. Point of View 2 (increment-based)). This means that we can apply both \(\mathcal {\tilde{P}'}\) and \(\mathcal {\tilde{P}}\) to the bargaining problem defined by \((u_{A,2},u_{B,2};0,0;\tilde{Q}).\) The following relations thus hold by construction:

$$\begin{aligned} x_n^{{\mathcal {P}}}= & {} y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}}+x_{n-1}^{\tilde{{\mathcal {P}}}} \quad \text {for } 2\le n \le N,\end{aligned}$$
(28)
$$\begin{aligned} x_n^{{{\mathcal {P}}'}}= & {} y_1^{{\mathcal {P}}}+x_{n-1}^{\tilde{{\mathcal {P}}}'} \quad \text {for } 2\le n \le N+1. \end{aligned}$$
(29)

Obviously, \({u}_{B,2}\) satisfies Condition (N-IARA). As for Condition (RA), note that

$$\begin{aligned} -\frac{u_{A,2}''(y)}{u_{A,2}'(y)}= & {} -\frac{u_A''(y+y^{\mathcal {P}}_1)}{u_A'(y+y^{\mathcal {P}}_1)} =a_A(y+y^{\mathcal {P}}_1) \ge a_B(y+y^{\mathcal {P}}_1) \ge a_B(y+q_1-y^{\mathcal {P}}_1) \\= & {} -\frac{u_B''(y+q_1-y^{\mathcal {P}}_1)}{u_B'(y+q_1-y^{\mathcal {P}}_1)} =-\frac{u_{B,2}''(y)}{u_{B,2}'(y)}. \end{aligned}$$

Here, we have used Condition (RA) for \(u_A\) and \(u_B\) in the first inequality and Condition (N-IARA) in the second inequality, together with the fact that \(y_1^{\mathcal {P}}\le q_1-y_1^{\mathcal {P}},\) which holds by Corollary 1. As a consequence, the induction hypothesis ensures that

$$\begin{aligned} x_{N-1}^{\tilde{{\mathcal {P}}}} \le x_{N}^{\tilde{{\mathcal {P}}}'}. \end{aligned}$$

Together with Eqs. (28) and (29), this inequality, in turn, implies that

$$\begin{aligned} x_N^{{\mathcal {P}}} \le x_{N+1}^{{{\mathcal {P}}'}}, \end{aligned}$$

thereby completing the proof of the theorem. \(\square \)

1.3 Proof of Theorem 2

Consider the protocol \({\mathcal {P}}^{\varepsilon }=(q^\varepsilon _n)_{0\le n\le N}\) over the amount \(Q>0,\) where \(q^\varepsilon _0=0,\) \(q^\varepsilon _1=\varepsilon /2,\) \(q^\varepsilon _N=Q\) and \(q^\varepsilon _2, q^\varepsilon _3, \dots ,q^\varepsilon _{N-1}\) will be specified later. The proof is based on Taylor expansions around \(\sigma _{n-1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^{\varepsilon }}\) and \(q^\varepsilon _{n-1}-\sigma _{n-1}^{{\mathcal {P}}^{\varepsilon }},\) respectively, of the following four terms in Eq. (9) (to simplify notation, dependencies on \(\varepsilon \) and \({\mathcal {P}}^{{\varepsilon }}\) are henceforth suppressed):

$$\begin{aligned}&\overbrace{u'_A\left( y_{n}+\sigma _{n-1}\right) }^{(\text {I})} \cdot \left[ \overbrace{u_B\left( q_{n}-y_{n} -\sigma _{n-1}\right) -u_B\left( q_{n-1} -\sigma _{n-1}\right) }^{(\text {II})}\right] \nonumber \\&\quad =\left[ \overbrace{u_A\left( y_{n}+\sigma _{n-1}\right) -u_A\left( \sigma _{n-1}\right) }^{(\text {III})}\right] \cdot \overbrace{u'_B\left( q_{n}-y_{n} -\sigma _{n-1} \right) }^{(\text {IV})}. \end{aligned}$$
(30)

Using that \(u_A\) and \(u_B\) have two continuous derivatives on (0, Q],  we obtain the following Taylor expansions for any n,  with \(2\le n \le N\):

$$\begin{aligned} (\text {I})= & {} u'_A\left( \sigma _{n-1}\right) + \xi _\mathrm{{I}} \left( y_{n}\right) ,\end{aligned}$$
(31)
$$\begin{aligned} (\text {II})= & {} u'_B\left( q_{n-1}-\sigma _{n-1}\right) \cdot \left( q_n-q_{n-1}-y_{n}\right) + \xi _\text {II}\left( q_n-q_{n-1}-y_{n}\right) ,\end{aligned}$$
(32)
$$\begin{aligned} (\text {III})= & {} u'_A\left( \sigma _{n-1}\right) \cdot y_{n}+ \xi _\mathrm{{III}} \left( y_{n}\right) ,\end{aligned}$$
(33)
$$\begin{aligned} (\text {IV})= & {} u'_B\left( q_{n-1}-\sigma _{n-1}\right) + \xi _\mathrm{{IV}}\left( q_n-q_{n-1}-y_{n}\right) , \end{aligned}$$
(34)

where \(\xi _\mathrm{{I}},\) \(\xi _\mathrm{{I}},\) \(\xi _\mathrm{{III}}\) and \(\xi _\mathrm{{IV}}\) are the error terms. Since \( \sigma _{n-1} \ge \sigma _1>0\) and \( q_{n-1}-\sigma _{n-1} \ge q_1-\sigma _{1}>0,\) both the leading order and the error terms in Eqs. (31)–(34) can be estimated by using bounds on the first and second derivatives of the utility functions \(u_A\) and \(u_B,\) which are bounded on any compact subinterval of (0, Q] by the Extreme Value Theorem. More specifically, we define

$$\begin{aligned} M^{\#}_A:= & {} \sup _{x\in [\sigma _1,Q]}|u_A^\#(x)|<\infty ,\quad (\#=','') \\ \nonumber \end{aligned}$$
(35)
$$\begin{aligned} M^{\#}_B:= & {} \sup _{x \in [q_1-\sigma _1,Q]}|u_B^{\#}(x)|<\infty . \quad (\#=','') \end{aligned}$$
(36)

Note that since \(q_1=\frac{\varepsilon }{2},\) the outcome of the first bargaining round in accordance with protocol \({\mathcal {P}}^{\varepsilon ,N}\) is independent of N,  and hence so are the constants \(M_i^{\#}\) (\(i=A,B\)).Footnote 15 Using Taylor’s theorem, we can estimate the error terms as follows:

$$\begin{aligned}&|\xi _\mathrm{{I}}(y_n)|\le M^{\prime \prime }_A|y_n|, \\&|\xi _\mathrm{{II}}(q_n-q_{n-1}-y_{n})|\le \frac{1}{2} M^{\prime \prime }_B |q_n-q_{n-1}-y_{n}|^2, \\&|\xi _\mathrm{{III}}(y_n)|\le \frac{1}{2} M^{\prime \prime }_A |y_n|^2, \\&|\xi _\mathrm{{IV}}(q_n-q_{n-1}-y_{n})|\le M^{\prime \prime }_B |q_n-q_{n-1}-y_{n}|. \end{aligned}$$

Using the fact that for all \(1\le n \le N\) we have \(y_n \le q_n-q_{n-1}\) as well as \(q_n-q_{n-1}-y_n \le q_n-q_{n-1},\) Eq. (30) implies that for any n,  with \(2\le n \le N,\)

$$\begin{aligned}&\left| u'_A\left( \sigma _{n-1}\right) \cdot u'_B\left( q_{n-1}-\sigma _{n-1}\right) \cdot \left( q_n-q_{n-1}-2y_n \right) \right| \nonumber \\&\quad \le \frac{3}{2} \left( M_A^{\prime \prime }M_B^{\prime } +M_A^{\prime }M_B^{\prime \prime }\right) \left( q_n-q_{n-1}\right) ^2 + M_A^{\prime \prime }M_B^{\prime \prime } \left( q_n-q_{n-1}\right) ^3. \end{aligned}$$
(37)

Moreover, since \(u_i''\le 0\) (\(i=A,B\)),

$$\begin{aligned} |u'_A\left( \sigma _{n-1}\right) \cdot u'_B\left( q_{n-1}-\sigma _{n-1}\right) |\ge m_A' m_B', \end{aligned}$$

where

$$\begin{aligned} m_A':= & {} u_A'(Q-(q_1-y_1))>0, \\ m_B':= & {} u_B'(Q-y_1)>0. \end{aligned}$$

To see that \(m_A'\) and \(m_B'\) are indeed strictly positive, note that the derivatives of \(u_i\) are non-negative and non-increasing, since \(u_i\) itself is strictly increasing and concave (\(i=A,B\)). Thus, \(u'_i(x)=0\) can only occur at the boundary value \(x=Q,\) if at all. The positivity of \(m_A'\) and \(m_B'\) then follows from the fact that \(0<y_1<q_1\le Q.\)Footnote 16 In conclusion, we obtain that for any n with \(2\le n \le N,\)

$$\begin{aligned}&\left| y_n-\frac{q_n-q_{n-1}}{2}\right| \nonumber \\&\quad \le \frac{3\left( M_A^{\prime \prime }M_B^{\prime } +M_A^{\prime }M_B^{\prime \prime }\right) }{4m_A'm_B'} \left( q_n-q_{n-1}\right) ^2+ \frac{M_A^{\prime \prime }M_B^{\prime \prime }}{2m_A'm_B'} \left( q_n-q_{n-1}\right) ^3.\nonumber \\&\quad =: C_1 (q_n-q_{n-1})^2+C_2(q_n-q_{n-1})^3 \nonumber \\&\quad \le \left( C_1 { \cdot } \mathop {\hbox {max}}\limits _{2\le { l}\le N}|q_{{ l}}-q_{{ l}-1}| + C_2 { \cdot } \mathop {\hbox {max}}\limits _{2\le { l} \le N}|q_{{l}}-q_{{ l}-1}|^2 \right) (q_n-q_{n-1}), \end{aligned}$$
(38)

where \(C_1,\) \(C_2\) are independent of N by definition.

We can now estimate the difference between the outcome \(x_N=\sum _{n=1}^N y_n\) for player A in accordance with protocol \({\mathcal {P}}^{\varepsilon ,N}\) and half the total amount Q,  namely,

$$\begin{aligned}&\left| x_N-\frac{Q}{2} \right| = \left| \sum _{n=1}^N y_n - \frac{Q}{2} \right| \nonumber \\&\quad \le y_1 +\left| \sum _{n=2}^N \left( y_n-\frac{q_n-q_{n-1}}{2}\right) \right| + \left| \sum _{n=2}^N \frac{q_n-q_{n-1}}{2}-\frac{Q}{2}\right| \end{aligned}$$
(39)
$$\begin{aligned}&\quad \le y_1+ \left( C_1 \cdot \mathop {\hbox {max}}\limits _{2\le l \le N}|q_l-q_{l-1}| + C_2 \cdot \mathop {\hbox {max}}\limits _{2\le l \le N}|q_{l}-q_{l-1}|^2 \right) \cdot \,\left| \sum _{n=2}^N (q_n-q_{n-1}) \right| + \frac{q_1}{2}\nonumber \\&\quad \le \frac{\varepsilon }{2} + \left( C_1 \cdot \mathop {\hbox {max}}\limits _{2\le l \le N}|q_{l}-q_{ l-1}| + C_2 \cdot \mathop {\hbox {max}}\limits _{2\le {l} \le N}|q_{l}-q_{ l-1}|^2 \right) \cdot \,(Q -q_1)+\frac{\varepsilon }{4}, \end{aligned}$$
(40)

where we have used (38) and the fact that \(y_1=\varepsilon /2.\) Choosing N and \(q_2, \dots , q_N,\) with \(q_2\le \dots \le q_N,\) such that

$$\begin{aligned} \left( C_1 \cdot \mathop {\hbox {max}}\limits _{2\le {l} \le N}|q_{l}-q_{l-1}| + C_2 \cdot \mathop {\hbox {max}}\limits _{2\le {l} \le N}|q_{l}-q_{l-1}|^2 \right) \cdot Q< \frac{\varepsilon }{4} \end{aligned}$$

concludes the proof of the theorem. \(\square \)

Remark 1

In the proof of Theorem 2, the fact that the derivatives of \(u_i\) (\(i=A,B\)) at zero might be singular required us to treat the first bargaining round separately, by imposing \(q_1=\varepsilon /2,\) which is independent of N. If, however, we assume that \(u_i\in C^2([0,Q])\) and \(u'_i(Q)>0\) (\(i=A,B\)), this is no longer necessary. Indeed, in this case, the suprema in Eqs. (35) and (36) remain finite when evaluated over the entire interval [0, Q],  thereby enabling us to replace (38) by

$$\begin{aligned}&\left| y_n-\frac{q_n-q_{n-1}}{2}\right| \\&\quad \le \left( C_1 \cdot \mathop {\hbox {max}}\limits _{1\le l \le N}|q_{ l}-q_{l-1}| + C_2 \cdot \mathop {\hbox {max}}\limits _{1\le l \le N}|q_{l}-q_{l-1}|^2 \right) \cdot \,(q_n-q_{n-1}). \end{aligned}$$

We stress that this inequality is now valid for all \(1\le n \le N,\) with constants \(C_1\) and \(C_2\) independent of \(\varepsilon .\) This leads to the following estimate of the difference between the outcome \(x_N\) and half the total amount Q:

$$\begin{aligned} \left| x_N-\frac{Q}{2} \right| \le \left( C_1 \cdot \mathop {\hbox {max}}\limits _{1\le l \le N}|q_{l}-q_{l-1}| + C_2 \cdot \mathop {\hbox {max}}\limits _{1\le l \le N}|q_{l}-q_{l-1}|^2 \right) \cdot Q. \end{aligned}$$
(41)

As a consequence, the assertion of Corollary 2 follows for \(u_i'(Q)>0\) and extends to all \(u_i \in C^2([0,Q])\) by a simple approximation argument at Q (\(i=A,B\)).Footnote 17

Remark 2

Assume again that \(u_i'(Q)>0\) (\(i=A,B\)). Then (41) can be used to determine the required granularity of a particular protocol more explicitly than (40), given any error margin \(\varepsilon >0.\) This is possible because \(C_1\) and \(C_2\) in (41) are now independent of \(\varepsilon .\) As an example, consider the case of equidistant \(q_n,\) i.e., \(q_n:= n\cdot Q/N\) for \(1\le n\le N.\) Then, using (41), we obtain that \(| x_N-\frac{Q}{2} |<\varepsilon \) if

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{C_1Q^2}{N} + \frac{C_2Q^3}{N^2} <\varepsilon . \end{aligned}$$

It then follows that the number of required rounds \(N^\varepsilon \) grows at most inversely proportional to the error margin \(\varepsilon >0.\) Namely,

$$\begin{aligned} N^\varepsilon := {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} \lceil C_1 Q^2 / \varepsilon \rceil &{}\text {if } C_2=0, \\ \left\lceil \frac{1}{\sqrt{\frac{\varepsilon }{C_2Q^3}+\frac{C_1^2}{(4C_2^2Q^2)}}-\frac{C_1}{2C_2Q}} \right\rceil &{}\text {if } C_2>0. \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$

We note that \(C_2=0\) if one player has linear utility.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Grech, P., Tejada, O. Divide the dollar and conquer more: sequential bargaining and risk aversion. Int J Game Theory 47, 1261–1286 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-018-0618-x

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-018-0618-x

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation