Skip to main content
Log in

Good to the last drop? Millikan stories as “canned” pedagogy

  • Published:
Science and Engineering Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In recent literature, the famous Millikan oil-drop experiment appears as a case of “good scientific judgment” on the one hand, and scientific misconduct on the other. This article discusses different interpretations of the fact that Nobel laureate Robert Millikan’s notebooks show that he eliminated a number of oildrops in his published 1913 paper on the charge of the electron, while reporting that he had included all the drops. Starting with the common source of all Millikan stories, historian of physics Gerald Holton’s 1978 paper, I discuss recent “canned” versions of Millikan-as-misbehaver in books on scientific fraud. Then I examine some versions of Millikan-as-good-scientist, particularly the reconstruction by historian of physics Allan Franklin, and the views of some practicing physicists. Finally, we have an instructive head-on collision between the two standard treatments of Millikan. The problem with canned stories is not only insufficient information; we also lack a realistic evaluation of the role of ethics in science. As a fundamentally knowledge-seeking enterprise, science may harbor an inherent, perhaps irresolvable, conflict between scientific and ethical concerns.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes and References

  1. Broad Wm. and Wade N. (1983)Betrayers of the Truth, Simon and Schuster, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Kohn A. (1986)False Prophets: Fraud and Error in Science and Medicine, Basil Blackwell, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See e.g., Brush S. (1974) Should the History of Science Be Rated X?,Science 183: 1164–1172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Babbage C. (1830)Reflections on the Decline of Science in England, August M. Kelley, New York (1970).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Holton G. (1978) Subelectrons, presuppositions and the Millikan-Ehrenhaft dispute, In: Holton G., ed.,The Scientific Imagination, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Broad and Wade (1983).

    Google Scholar 

  7. Kohn (1986).

    Google Scholar 

  8. Franklin A. (1984) Forging, Cooking, Trimming, and Riding on the Bandwagon,American Journal of Physics,52 (9): 786–793.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Holton G. (1986) Thematic Presuppositions and the Direction of Scientific Advance, In: Holton G.,The Advancement of Science and Its Burdens, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.

    Google Scholar 

  10. National Academy of Sciences (NAS) (1990),On Being A Scientist, Washington, D.C., National Academy Press. (The reader should note that there is a new edition published in 1995 that is greatly modified).

    Google Scholar 

  11. Goodstein D. (1991) Scientific Fraud,The American Scholar,60 (4), Autumn 1991: 505–515.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Gert B. (1993), Moral Theory and Scientific Research, in: Sigma Xi,Ethics, Values and the Promise of Science (Proceedings of Sigma Xi Forum, San Francisco 1993), Sigma Xi Publications Office, Research Triangle, N.C., pp. 157–171.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Holton (1978), p. 28.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Holton (1978), pp. 70–71.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Millikan R. A. (1913) On the Elementary Electrical Charge and the Avogadro Constant,Physical Review,2: 109–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Millikan R.A. (1917),The Electron: Its Isolation and Measurement and the Determination of Some of Its Properties, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, USA.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Millikan quoted in Holton (1986), p. 9

    Google Scholar 

  18. Broad and Wade (1983), p. 227.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Holton (1978), quoted in Broad and Wade (1983), p. 35.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Kohn (1986).

    Google Scholar 

  22. Kohn (1986). p. 60.

    Google Scholar 

  23. For Fletcher’s own reflection on this case, see Fletcher H. (1982) My Work with Millikan on the Oil-Drop Experiment,Physics Today, June, 43–47.

  24. Kohn (1986), p. 62.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Luria S. (1975), What Makes a Scientist Cheat?,Prism, May, pp. 16,18.

  26. Kohn (1986), loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Franklin (1984).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Franklin (1984), p. 788.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Ibid. Franklin (1984)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Ibid. Franklin (1984),

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Ibid. Franklin (1984),

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Franklin (1984), p. 789.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Franklin (1984), p. 792.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Fairbank W. M. and Franklin A. (1982)American Journal of Physics 50, 394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Westfall R. S. (1973) Newton and the Fudge Factor,Science 179: 751–758. This and some other cases are included in Brush S. (1974), Should the History of Science Be Rated X?,Science 183: 1164–1172. Broad and Wade (1983) have collected historical cases in their Chapter 2 and Appendix, and provide references to the original articles.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Dickman S. (1993) Could Coulomb’s Experiments Result in Coulomb’s Law?,Science 262(22 October): 500–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Franklin (1984), p. 789.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Ibid. Franklin (1984), p. 789.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Franklin (1984), p. 792.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Holton (1986), pp. 9–10.

    Google Scholar 

  41. De Voto B. (1947)Across the Wide Missouri, Houghton Mifflin, Boston, quoted in Holton (1986), p. 7.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Holton (1986), p. 9. The theme of suspension of disbelief as exemplified by Millikan already appears in Holton’s 1978 article, pp. 71–72.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Holton, 1986, p. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  44. eg, Holton (1978), p. 72; Holton (1986), p. 307.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Scientists often suggests that when judging acceptable and unacceptable behavior of scientists in historical cases, one would have to take into account the prevailing standards at the time regarding data presentation and the like. This has also been applied to Millikan. The 1990 National Academy of Sciences pamphletOn Being A Scientist discusses the fact that Millikan “glossed over [his] exclusions in some of his published papers and by present standards this is not acceptable” (NAS, 1990, p. 3). This statement seems to imply that such conduct was, at some earlier time, acceptable in science. Assuming one could indeed find out what was accepted scientific conduct at a particular time, one might, again, discuss in what way that might affect the ethical judgment of the case. The problem of changing standards for “good science” is briefly discussed in Schmaus W., Segerstråle U. and Jesseph D. (1992) The Hard Program in the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge: A Manifesto,Social Epistemology,6 (3): 243–265. The question of changing standards for acceptable scientific conduct remains a difficult one.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  46. Goodstein (1991).

    Google Scholar 

  47. Goodstein (1991), pp. 511–512.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Goodstein (1991), p. 512.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Gert (1993), p. 167.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Gert (1993), p. 170.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Ibid. Gert (1993),

    Google Scholar 

  52. Ibid. Gert (1993),

    Google Scholar 

  53. Gert (1993), p. 167.

    Google Scholar 

  54. This assumption can easily lead to problems, however, in cases with conflicting views of “good science.” For an illustration, see Segerstråle U. (1992) Reductionism, ‘Bad Science’ and Politics: A Critique of Anti-Reductionist Reasoning,Politics and the Life Sciences,11(2): 199–214.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Bernard Davis, personal communication.

  56. John Edsall, personal communication.

  57. For a more detailed analysis of this and related problems, see Segerstråle, U. (1993), The Importance of Being Right vs. the Importance of Being Earnest: Public Accountability of Science in the ‘Baltimore Case’,Science Studies 6 (2): 4–22. In this case there seems to be a contrast in reasoning style particularly between junior scientist Margot O’Toole and senior scientist David Baltimore.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Franks F. (1981)Polywater, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, USA.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Langmuir I. (1989) Pathological science,Physics Today 42: 36–48. Reprinted from the original inGeneral Electric Research and Development Center Report 86-C-035, April 1968.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  60. Cf. Segerstråle U. (1990a), The Murky Borderland between Scientific Intuition and Fraud,International Journal of Applied Ethics 5 (1): 11–20. Reprinted in: Erwin E., Gendin S. and Kleiman L., eds. (1993)Ethical Issues in Research, Garland Publishing, Hamden, CT, USA.

    Google Scholar 

  61. See eg, Segerstråle U. (1992, 1990a) and Segerstråle, U. (1990b), Negotiating ‘Sound Science’: Expert Disagreement about Release of Genetically Engineered Organisms,Politics and the Life Sciences,8 (2): 221–231.

    Google Scholar 

  62. NAS (1990), p. 3.

  63. NAS (1990), pp. 3–4, italics added.

  64. Gert (1993), p. 168.

    Google Scholar 

  65. The report defines these terms as follows: “Fabrication is making up data or results, falsification is changing data or results, and plagiarism is using the ideas or words of another person without giving appropriate credit.” National Academy of Sciences (NAS), Panel on Scientific Responsibility and the Conduct of Research (1992),Responsible Science: Ensuring the Integrity of the Research Process, Volume 1, National Academy Press, Washington, D.C., p. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  66. NAS (1992), p. 5.

  67. NAS (1992), p. 6.

  68. Stone R. (1995) Federal Panel Recommends Universities Play Bigger Role,Science 267: 449.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  69. I cannot here go into the interesting reasoning that this open-ended exercise inspires. For instance, as some students correctly point out, if everyone plagiarized, it would undermine science as we know it. While I am here primarily interested in making an analytical distinction between knowledge concerns and moral concerns, a future class exercise might well involve discussing Gert’s fundamental challenge, that is, his question whether “acts of honesty under great temptation to deceive” might not have influence the scientific tradition so as to make science evenmore successful than it is (Gert p. 167, this paper p. 207).

    Google Scholar 

  70. Leon Lederman, personal communication. For more statements by scientists about the importance of careful measurement and reporting, see the special issue ofPerspectives on the Professions (1991),10 (2): What is Good Science? What is Good Engineering? (Guest editor: Segerstråle, U.).

  71. Fairbank and Franklin (1982).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  72. Gert’s suggestion that the correct result may have been produced even more quickly had Newton and Millikan freely disclosed all their results (Gert, 1993, p. 168, this paper p. 207), could indeed be characterized as a knowledge-oriented rather than ethical concern. But Gert is not interested in loss of information of the type discussed here. Rather, he is worried about the amount of possible “futile research” that may result when experienced scientists suppress disconfirming evidence for hypotheses they strongly believe in. He is concerned about scientists’ potentially diminished trust in one another’s results (Gert (1993) p. 170 and this paper p. 206).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Additional information

The author’s special interests include standards for “good science”, science and values, and social psychology.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Segerstråle, U. Good to the last drop? Millikan stories as “canned” pedagogy. Sci Eng Ethics 1, 197–214 (1995). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02628797

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02628797

Keywords

Navigation