Skip to main content
Log in

The gene in search of an identity

  • Review Articles
  • Published:
Human Genetics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Summary

The concept of the difference between the potential for a trait and the trait proper, i.e., between the genotype and the phenotype, became clear only during the first decade of the century, mainly through the work of Johannsen. Although Johannsen insisted on that the terms he coined were only helpful devices to organize data about heredity, it is obvious that they were bound from the beginning to the hypothesis that there was “something” in the gametes that could be rendered to analysis as discrete units. These units were the genes.

This reductionist yet materially non-committed attitude has been developed into what I called instrumental-reductionism: the genes were hypothetical constructs that were accepted “as if” they were real entities. The research program developed on such a concept was very successful, not least because this instrumental approach allowed maximum flexibility in the attachment of meaning of the genes. While most geneticists accepted one or another position of this flexible concept, others took more extreme positions. At the one extreme end of the conceptual continuum was the realist approach that argued that genes were discrete, measurable, material particles, and on the other end, the claim that the attempts to identify discrete units only led to hyperatomism of a holistic view appropriate to heredity.

The acceptance of the gene as a material and discrete unit, in the beginning of 1950s, opened the way to a deeper level of conceptualizing both its structure (“cistron-recon-muton”) and function (“one gene—one enzyme”). The discovery of the structure of DNA finally offered a chemical-physical explanation to the geneticist's requirements of a material gene. Thus, within less than 20 years the gene has been established as a “sharply limited segment of the linear structure” that is involved in the structrue of a product or its regulation.

However, with turning of much of the attention to the eucaryotic DNA, it was necessary to accommodate the gene to an increasing flood of findings that did not tally with its concept as a discrete material unit. Without much heart-seeking among geneticists, the gene regained its role as an instrumental unit, or even as just an intervening variable, “a quantity obtained by specified manipulation of the values of empirical variables”. Though this flexibility demonstrated again that “the most fruitful concepts are those to which it is impossible to attach a well defined meaning”, it brought us also into a situation in which the same term has a different meaning for each group of scientists. In order to avoid the danger “to be scattered over the face of all the earth” because of lack of communicable language, it might be advisable to halt a little and reflect on the meaning of our concepts and their function.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Beadle GW, Tatum EL (1941a) Experimental control of development and differentiation. Genetic control of developmental reactions. Am Nat 75:107–116

    Google Scholar 

  • Beadle GW, Tatum EL (1941b) Genetic control of biochemical reactions in Neurospora. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 27:499–506

    Google Scholar 

  • Benzer S (1957) The elementary units of heredity. In: McElroy WD, Glass B (eds) The chemical basis of heredity. Johns Hopkins Press, Baltimore, pp 70–93

    Google Scholar 

  • Benzer S (1959) On the topology of the genetic fine structure. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 45:1607–1620

    Google Scholar 

  • Britten RJ, Davidson EH (1969) Gene regulation for higher cells: a theory. Science 165:349–357

    Google Scholar 

  • Britten RJ, Kohne DE (1968) Repeated sequences in DNA. Science 161:529–540

    Google Scholar 

  • Carlson EA (1966) The gene: a critical history. Saunders, Philadelphia London

    Google Scholar 

  • Castle WE (1915). Mr. Muller on the constancy of Mendelian factors. Am Nat 49:37–42

    Google Scholar 

  • Castle WE (1919) Piebald rats and the theory of genes. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 5:126–130

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1976) The selfish gene. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • East EM (1912) Mendelian notation as a description of physiological facts. Am Nat 46:633–655

    Google Scholar 

  • Elkana Y (1974) The discovery of conservation of energy. Hutchinson Educational, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher RA (1918) The correlation between relatives on the supposition of Mendelian inheritance. Trans R Soc Edinburgh 52:399–433

    Google Scholar 

  • Galton F (1872) On blood relationships. In: Olby RC (1966) The origins of Mendelism. Constable, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldschmidt RB (1938) The theory of the gene. Sci Month 46:268–273

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldschmidt RB (1950) Fifty years of genetics. Am Nat 84:313–340

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldschmidt RB (1954) Different philosophies of genetics. Science 119:703–710

    Google Scholar 

  • Grivell LA (1983) Mitochondrial DNA. Sci Am 248(3):60–73

    Google Scholar 

  • Jenkin F (1867) The origin of species. In: Hall DL (1973) Darwin and his critics. Harvard University Press, Cambridge Mass, pp 303–350

    Google Scholar 

  • Johannsen W (1909) Elemente der Exakten Erblichkeitslehre, 2nd edn. Gustav Fischer, Jena

    Google Scholar 

  • Johannsen W (1926) Elemente der Exakten Erblichkeitslehre, 3rd edn. Gustav Fischer, Jena

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCorquodale K, Meehl PE (1948) On a distinction between hypothetical constructs and intervening variables. Psychol Rev 55:95–107

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell G (1962) The ontological status of theoretical entities. In: Feigl H, Maxwell G (eds) Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science 3:3–27

  • Mendel G (1866) Versuche über Pflanzen-Hybriden. Verh Naturf Ver. Im Verlage des Vereines, Brünn

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan TH (1933) The relation of genetics to physiology and medicine. In: Nobel Lectures in Physiology and Medicine 1922–1941. (1965) Elsevier, Amsterdam New York, pp 313–328

    Google Scholar 

  • Morton NE, Yee S, Elston RC, Lew R (1970) Discontinuity and quasi-continuity: alternative hypotheses of multifactorial inheritance. Clin Genet 1:81–93

    Google Scholar 

  • Motulsky AG (1982) Genetic approaches to common diseases. In: Bonne B (ed) Human genetics, Part B: Medical genetics. Proceedings 6th International Congress of Human Genetics. Alan R Liss, New York, pp 89–95

    Google Scholar 

  • Muller HJ (1914) The bearing of the selection experiments of Castle and Phillips on the variability of genes. Am Nat 48:567–576

    Google Scholar 

  • Muller HJ (1916) The mechanism of crossing over. Am Nat 30:193–221

    Google Scholar 

  • Muller HJ (1922) Variation due to change in the individual gene. Am Nat 56:32–50

    Google Scholar 

  • Muller HJ (1926) The gene as the basis of life. International Congress of Plant Sciences 1. Ithaca 1929, pp 897–921

  • Muller HJ (1947) Pilgrim Trust Lecture: the gene. Proc R Soc Lond [Biol] 134:1–37

    Google Scholar 

  • Muller HJ (1956) On the relation between chromosome changes and gene mutations. Brookhaven Symp Biol 8:126–147

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel E (1968) The structure of science. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Olby RC (1966) Origins of mendelism. Constable, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Olby RC (1974) The path to the double helix. Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Plomin R, Kuse AR (1979) Genetic differences between humans and chimps and among humans. Am Psychol 34:188–190

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandler I (1983) Pier Louis Moreande Maupertuis, a precursor of Mendel? J Hist Biol 16:101–136

    Google Scholar 

  • Stent GS (1968) That was the molecular biology that was. Science 160:390–395

    Google Scholar 

  • Stent GS (1970) DNA. Daedalus 99:909–937

    Google Scholar 

  • Timofeeff-Ressovsky NW, Zimmer EG, Delbrück M (1935) Über die Natur der Genmutation und der Genstruktur. Nachr Ges Wissen Göttingen. Math-physik Klasse, Fachgruppe VI 1:189–245

    Google Scholar 

  • Vogel F (1970) The genetic basis of the normal human electroencephalogram (EEG). Humangenetik 10:91–114

    Google Scholar 

  • Vogel F, Motulsky AG (1982) Human genetics, problems and approaches. Springer, Berlin Heidelberg New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson JD, Crick FHC (1953) Genetical implications on the structure of deoxyribose nucleic acid. Nature 171:964–967

    Google Scholar 

  • Weismann A (1885) The continuity of the germ-plasm as the foundation of the theory of heredity. In: Poulton EB, Schonland S, Shipley AE (eds) Essays upon heredity and kindred biological problems by Dr. August Weismann. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodger JH (1967) Biological principles, a critical study. Routledge and Kegan Paul, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Falk, R. The gene in search of an identity. Hum Genet 68, 195–204 (1984). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00418388

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00418388

Keywords

Navigation