Skip to main content
Log in

Relevant deduction

From solving paradoxes towards a general theory

  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper presents an outline of a new theory of relevant deduction which arose from the purpose of solving paradoxes in various fields of analytic philosophy. In distinction to relevance logics, this approach does not replace classical logic by a new one, but distinguishes between relevance and validity. It is argued that irrelevant arguments are, although formally valid, nonsensical and even harmful in practical applications. The basic idea is this: a valid deduction is relevant iff no subformula of the conclusion is replaceable on some of its occurrences by any other formula salva validitate of the deduction. The paper first motivates the approach by showing that four paradoxes seemingly very distant from each other have a common source. Then the exact definition of relevant deduction is given and its logical properties are investigated. An extension to relevance of premises is discussed. Finally the paper presents an overview of its applications in philosophy of science, ethics, cognitive psychology and artificial intelligence.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Ackermann, W.: 1956, ‘Begründung einer strengen Implikation’, Journal of Symbolic Logic 21, 113–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, A. R. and Belnap, N. D.: 1975, Entailment. The Logic of Relevance and Necessity, Princeton University Press, Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Åqvist, L.: 1984, ‘Deontic Logic’, in D. Gabbay and F. Guenthner (eds.), pp. 605–714.

  • Barwise, J.: 1988, The Situation in Logic, Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratko, I.: 1986, Prolog Programming for Artificial Intelligence, Addison-Wesley Publ. Comp., Wokingham.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R.: 1936–37, ‘Testability and Meaning’, Philosophy of Science 3, 419–471 and 4, 1937, 1–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R.: 1956, ‘The Methodological Character of Theoretical Concepts’, in: H. Feigl, and M. Scriven (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. I, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp. 38–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cleave, J. P.: 1973–74, ‘An Account of Entailment Based on Classical Semantics’, Analysis 34, 118–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitting, M.: 1983, Proof Methods for Modal and Intuitionistic Logics, Reidel, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M.: 1974, ‘Explanation and Scientific Understanding’, Journal of Philosophy 71, 5–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glymour, C.: 1980, ‘Hypothetico-Deductivism is Hopeless’, Philosophy of Science 47, 322–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halldén, S. 1951: ‘On the Semantic Non-Completeness of Certain Lewis Calculi’, Journal of Symbolic Logic 16(2), 127–129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, J.: 1972, ‘Ethical Naturalism’, in: P. Edwards (ed.), The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol. 3–4, The Macmillan Company & The Free Press, New York, Reprint Edition, pp. 69–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G.: 1965, Aspects in Scientific Explanation and Other Essays, Free Press, New York, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, M.: 1970, ‘Theories and Transitivity of Confirmation’, Philosophy of Science 37, 50–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D.: 1739–40: A Treatise of Human Nature, (L. A. Selby-Bigge, ed., Oxford 1888, Reprint 1951), Orig. 1739/40.

  • Kitcher, P.: 1976, ‘Comments and Criticism: Explanation, Conjunction and Unification’, Journal of Philosophy 73, 207–212.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P.: 1981, ‘Explanatory Unification’, Philosophy of Science 48, 507–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kleene, S. C.: 1971, Introduction to Metamathematics, Wolters-Noordhoff Publishing, Groningen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Körner, S.: 1947, ‘On Entailment’, Proceedings of the Aristotelean Society 21, 143–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Körner, S.: 1959, Conceptual Thinking, Dover Publ., New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Körner, S.: 1979, ‘On Logical Validity and Informal Appropriateness’, Philosophy 54, 377–379.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuipers, T. A. (ed.): 1987, What Is Closer-To-The-Truth?, Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of Science and the Humanities, Vol. 10, Rodopi, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kutschera, F. v.: 1982, Grundlagen der Ethik, W. de Gruyter, Berlin-New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, J.: 1984, Foundations of Logic Programming, Springer, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D.: 1982, ‘Truth, Truthlikeness, Approximative Truth’, Fundamenta Scientiae, 3(1), 93–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morscher, E.: 1984, ‘Sein-Sollen-Schlüsse und wie Schlüsse sein sollen’, in W. u.a. Krawietz, (eds.), Theorie der Normen (Festgabe für Ota Weinberger), Duncker and Humblot, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parry, W.: 1933, ‘Ein Axiomensystem für eine neue Art von Implikation (Analytische Implikation)’, Ergebnisse eines mathematischen Kolloquiums, 4, 5–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K.: 1948, ‘What Can Logic Do For Philosophy?’, Artistotelian Society Proceedings, Suppl. 22, 141–154.

  • Popper, K.: 1963, Conjectures and Refutations, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K.: 1976, Logik der Forschung (6. Auflage). J. C. B. Mohr, Tübingen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. N.: 1954, ‘The Paradoxes of Derived Obligation’, Mind 63, 64–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. N.: 1960, ‘The Autonomy of Ethics’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 38, 199–206.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, A.: 1941, ‘Imperatives and Logic’, Theoria 7, 53–71; reprint in Philosophy of Science 11, 1944, pp. 30–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radnitzky, G.: 1980, ‘From Justifying a Theory to Comparing Theories and Selecting Questions’, Revue Internationale de Philosophie 131–132, 179–228.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rautenberg, W.: 1979, Klassische und Nichtklassische Aussagenlogik, Friedr. Vieweg & Sohn, Braunschweig, Wiesbaden.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G.: 1983, Wissenschaftliche Erklärung, Ansätze zu einer logisch-pragmatischen Wissenschaftstheorie, (dissertation), dbv-Verlag für die TU Graz.

  • Schurz, G.: 1983b, ‘Das deduktive Relevanzkriterium von Stephan Körner und seine wissenschaftstheoretischen Anwendungen’, Grazer Philosophische Studien 20, 149–177.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G.: 1987, ‘A New Definition of Verisimilitude and its Applications’, in P. Weingartner and G. Schurz (eds.), Logic, Philosophy of Science and Epistemology, Proceedings of the 11th International Wittgenstein-Symposium, Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, Vienna, pp. 177–184.

  • Schurz, G.: 1988, ‘Was ist wissenschaftliches Verstehen? Eine Theorie verstehensbewirkender Erklärungsepisoden’, in G. Schurz (ed.), pp. 235–298.

  • Schurz, G. (ed.): 1988, Erklären und Verstehen in der Wissenschaft. (With contributions by B. v. Fraassen, P. Gärdenfors, R. Tuomela, M. Friedman, P. Kitcher, G. Schurz and K. Lambert), R. Oldenbourg, München.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G.: 1989, Relevant Deduction in Science and Ethics. With a Case Study of the Is-Ought Problem, (habilitation), Salzburg 1989.

  • Schurz, G.: 1990, ‘Paradoxical Consequences of Balzer's and Gähde's Criteria of Theoreticity. Results of an Application to Ten Scientific Theories’, Erkenntnis 32, 161–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G.: 1991, ‘How Far Can Hume's Is-Ought Thesis be Generalized? An Investigation in Alethic-Deontic Modal Predicate Logic’, Journal of Philosophical Logic 20, 37–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. and Weingartner, P.: 1987, ‘Verisimilitude Defined by Relevant Consequence-Elements. A New Reconstruction of Popper's Idea’, in T. A. Kuipers (ed.), pp. 47–78.

  • Schurz, G. and Lambert, K.: 1991, ‘Outline of a Theory of Scientific Understanding’, submitted for publication.

  • Stegmüller, W.: 1970, Probleme und Resultate der Wissenschaftstheorie und Analytischen Philosophie, Band II, 1. Halbband, Springer, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stranzinger, R.: 1977, ‘Die Paradoxa der deontischen Logik’, in I. Tammelo and H. Schreiner (eds.), Grundzüge und Grundverfahren der Rechtslogik, Band 2, Verlag Dokumentation (UTB 685), München 1977.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weingartner, P. 1985, ‘A Simple Relevance Criterion for Natural Language and Its Semantics’, in G. Dorn and P. Weingartner (eds.), Foundations of Logic and Linguistic, Plenum Press, Salzburg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weingartner, P. and G. Schurz: 1986, ‘Paradoxes Solved by Simple Relevance Criteria’, Logique et Analyse 113, 3–40.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Additional information

This paper is based on the first part of my habilitation Schurz (1989). For various helps and comments I am indebted to Paul Weingartner. Andrzej Wrónski, Georg Kreisel, David Miller, Kit Fine, Terence Parsons and Peter Woodruff.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Schurz, G. Relevant deduction. Erkenntnis 35, 391–437 (1991). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00388295

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00388295

Keywords

Navigation