Skip to main content

Husserl’s Concept of Intentionality

  • Chapter
Analecta Husserliana

Part of the book series: Analecta Husserliana ((ANHU,volume 1))

Abstract

It may not be an overstatement to say that the development of Husserl’s thought can be adequately grasped if only we followed the development of his concept of intentionality. The same could also be said of the development of phenomenology after Husserl. There are no doubt some excellent studies on Husserl’s concept of intentionality1, but what is still lacking is a comprehensive account which would take into account the total Husserliana which are only now coming to be made available to scholars. Furthermore, we also do not have a study which undertakes to assess Husserl’s concept of intentionality from the point of view of the criticisms and challenges emerging out of the writings of the post-Husserlian phenomenologists. This paper will make an attempt to fulfil these two needs but only within the brief compass permissible here. There will be first an attempt to explore the philosophical relationship of Husserl’s concept of intentionality to Brentano’s. An exposition will next be given of Husserl’s concept through the various phases of its development. This will be followed by a reference to the criticisms and challenges made by the later phenomenologists like Sartre and Merleau-Ponty, and the concluding part of the paper will seek to evaluate the points made by the critics and in that connection take a fresh look at Husserl’s thought against the new perspective gained thereby.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. Special references may be made to: H. Spiegelberg, ‘Der Begriff’ der Intentionalität in der Scholastik, bei Brentano und bei Husserl’, Philosophische Hefte 5 (1936), 75–91;

    Google Scholar 

  2. L. Landgrebe, Phänomenologie und Metaphysik, Schröder, Hamburg, 1949, pp. 59–69;

    Google Scholar 

  3. A. Gurwitsch, ‘On the Intentionality of Consciousness’ in Philosophical Essays in Memory of Edmund Husserl (ed. by M. Färber, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1940;

    Google Scholar 

  4. A. De Waelhens, ‘L’idée phénoménologique d’intentionnalité’, in Husserl et la Pensée Moderne (ed. by H. L. Van Breda and J. Taminiaux ), Martinus Nühoflf, The Hague, 1959.

    Google Scholar 

  5. In fact, Chisholm regards this as the ontological part of the Brentano thesis. Cf. Chisholm’s essay on #x2018;sIntentionality#x2019;s in the Encyclopedia of Philosophy (ed. by P. Edwards ), Colliers & Macmillan, New York, 1967.

    Google Scholar 

  6. F. Brentano, The True and the Evident (English translation by R. M. Chisholm et al.). Rout ledge & Kegan Paul, London, p. 78.

    Google Scholar 

  7. F. Brentano, Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt, Vol. II, Leipzig, 1911, pp. 133–138.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  9. E. Husserl, Logische Untersuchungen, 4th ed., Max Niemeyer, Halle, 1928 (to be henceforth referred to as LU), ILL, pp. 370ff.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Ibid, p. 369.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Cf. E. Husserl, Phänomenologische Psychologie, Husserliana, Vol. IX, Martinus Nijhoff.The Hague, 1962 (to be henceforth referred to as P. Ps.), p. 268; Erste Philosophie, I, Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, 1956 (to be henceforth referred to as EP), pp. 349; Die Krisis der Europäischen Wissenschaften und die Transzendentale Phänomenologie, Martinus Nühoff, The Hague, 1954 (to be henceforth referred to as Krisis), p. 236.

    Google Scholar 

  12. P.Ps., pp. 314, pp. 260–266.

    Google Scholar 

  13. According to G. Berger, the category of noema is more fundamental than that of being or of non-being. Cf. G. Berger, Le cogito dans la philosophic de Husserl, Paris 1941. p. 54.

    Google Scholar 

  14. A. Gurwitsch, Studies in Phenomenology and Psychology, Northwestern University Press, 1966.

    Google Scholar 

  15. R. M. Chisholm, ‘Sentences about Believing’ in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Vol. LVI, 1955–56, pp. 125–147; ‘On some Psychological Concepts and the “Logic” of Intentionality’ in Intentionality, Minds, and Perception (ed. by H.N. Castañeda), Wayne State University, 1966, pp. 11–35; also his Encyclopedia article.

    Google Scholar 

  16. L. Landgrebe, loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  17. H. Spiegelberg, loc. cit., p. 86.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Contrast Quinton, ‘Mind and Matter’ in Brain and Mind, Modern Concepts of the Nature of Mind (ed. by J. R. Smythies), Humanities Press, New York, 1965. Quinton argues (p. 224) that the Brentano thesis rules out behaviourism. It surely does, if intentionally is regarded as was done by Brentano himself as a criterion of the mental, and if behaviour is understood in a mechanistic way, not otherwise.

    Google Scholar 

  19. A. Diemer, Edmund Husserl, Versuch einer systematischen Darstellung seiner Phänomenologie, Meisenheim, 1956.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Cf. J. N. Mohanty, Edmund Husserl’s Theory of Meaning, Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, 1964, pp. 80–86.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Cf. P. Ricccur, Freedom and Nature. The Voluntary and the Involuntary (transl. by E. V. Kohak), Northwestern University Press, 1966, pp. 205ff.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Cf. P. Ricceur, Husserl, An Analysis of his Phenomenology (transl. by E. G. Ballard and L. E. Embrce ), Northwestern University Press, 1967, p. 192.

    Google Scholar 

  23. T. W. Adorno, Zur Metakritik der Erkenntnistheorie, Studien über Husserl und die phänomenologische Antinomien, Kohlhammer, Stuttgart, 1956, p. 171.

    Google Scholar 

  24. E. Husserl, Ideas I (references will be made to the Boyce Gibson translation in the paperback edition which will be henceforth referred to as Ideas I ), p. 250.

    Google Scholar 

  25. A. Gurwitsch, Studies, pp. 138–139.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Ideas I, p. 267.

    Google Scholar 

  27. For elaboration of this point, see J. N. Mohanty, ‘Notas a las lecciones de Husserl sobre laconcienciadel tiempo’, Dianoia, Anuario de Filosofia, Mexico, 1968, pp. 82–95.

    Google Scholar 

  28. R. Sokolowski, The Formation of Husserl’s Concept of Constitution, Martinus Nühoff, The Hague, 1964, pp. 92–93, 100, 114–115.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ideas I, p. 226.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Gaston Berger, bearing witness to Husserl’s later thought in this matter, refers to “how much the word ‘construction’ could irritate Husserl” (Gurwitsch, Studies, p. 160). For an account of the different stages of Husserl’s attitude towards the notion of productive synthesis, see Iso Kern, Husserl und Kant, Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, 1964, pp. 249ff.

    Google Scholar 

  31. P. Ricoeur, Husserl, p. 41.

    Google Scholar 

  32. E. Husserl, Ideen, I (Husserliana edition), p. 100. (This edition will be referred to as Ideen I.)

    Google Scholar 

  33. Ideen I, § 82.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Ideen I, § 95.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Ideen I, § 117.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Ideen II (Husserliana, Vol. IV), Martinus Nühoff, The Hague, 1952, § 4.

    Google Scholar 

  37. E. Husserl, Analysen zur Passiven Synthesis (1918–1926), Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, p. 196.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Cartesian Meditations, translated by D. Cairns, Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, 1960, § 38 (to be henceforth referred to as CM).

    Google Scholar 

  39. P.Ps., pp. 98–99.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Formale und Transzendentale Logik (to be henceforth referred to as FuTL), Max Niemeyer. Halle 1929, p. 184.

    Google Scholar 

  41. R. Sokolowski, loc. cit., p. 172.

    Google Scholar 

  42. G. Funke, Zur transzendentalen Phänomenologie, Bonn 1957, pp. 12–13; CM § 32.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Thus T. Seebohm, ‘Die Bedingungen der Möglichkeit der Transzendental-Philosophie’. Bouvier, Bonn, 1962:“… ist die genetische Intcntionalanalysc auf die Zusammenhänge dieser Typen in der Einheit des Bewußtseinsstromes selbst gerichtet.” This surely is not eo ipso a historically oriented programme.

    Google Scholar 

  44. For example, in P.Ps., p. 431.

    Google Scholar 

  45. CM, § 19.

    Google Scholar 

  46. CM,§ 64.

    Google Scholar 

  47. CM, p. 47.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Krisis, p. 240.

    Google Scholar 

  49. EP, II, pp. 318–319.

    Google Scholar 

  50. P.Ps., p. 428.

    Google Scholar 

  51. FuTL, p. 208; § 94.

    Google Scholar 

  52. G. Brand, Welt, Ich und Zeit, nach unveröffentliehen Manuskripten E. Husserls, Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, 1955, p. 23.

    Google Scholar 

  53. E. Fink, Studien zur Phänomenologie, Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, 1966, p. 219.

    Google Scholar 

  54. M. Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, London, 1962, Introduction.

    Google Scholar 

  55. J. J. Kockelmans, Phenomenology and Physical Science. An Introduction to the Philosophy of Physical Science, Duquesne University Press, 1966, pp. 53ff.

    Google Scholar 

  56. J.-P. Sartre, The Transcendence of the Ego. An Existentialist Theory of Consciousness, translated by F. Williams and R. Kirkpatrick, Noonday, New York, 1957.

    Google Scholar 

  57. J.-P. Sartre, Being and Nothingness. An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology, Translated by H. E. Barnes (to be henceforth referred to as BN), Methucn, London, 1957, p. Ixi.

    Google Scholar 

  58. BN, p. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  59. BN, p. Ixiii.

    Google Scholar 

  60. BN, p. 109.

    Google Scholar 

  61. BN, p. lix.

    Google Scholar 

  62. L. Landgrebe, ‘Prinzipien der Lehre vom Empfinden’ in Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung, 8 (1954) 193–209.

    Google Scholar 

  63. H. U. Asemissen, Strukturanalytische Probleme der Wahrnehmung in der Phänomenologie Husserls, Kant-Studien Ergänzungshefte 73,26–34, Kölner Universitätsvcrlag, 1957.

    Google Scholar 

  64. M. Merleau-Ponty, loc. cit., 243. Also sec the same work, pp. 213, 267, 405.

    Google Scholar 

  65. This is so according to Diemer.

    Google Scholar 

  66. BN, p. lx.

    Google Scholar 

  67. BN, p. Ixi.

    Google Scholar 

  68. T. Langan, Merleau-Ponty’s Critique of Reason, Yale University Press, 1966, p. 23f.

    Google Scholar 

  69. M. Merleau-Ponty, loc. cit., p. xvii.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Cf. ibid., pp. 124–125.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Cf. ibid., pp. 57, 58–59.Also, Merleau-Ponty, M., Signs (transl. by McCleary), Northwestern University Press, 1964, p. 173.

    Google Scholar 

  72. M. Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, p. 137.

    Google Scholar 

  73. M. Heidegger, Vom Wesen des Grundes, Klostermann, Frankfurt, 1949, pp. 15, 44.

    Google Scholar 

  74. BN, p. 85.

    Google Scholar 

  75. P. Ricoeur, Freedom and Nature, 61.

    Google Scholar 

  76. This is the argument of Natanson in his ‘The Empirical and Transcendental Ego’ in For Roman Ingarden. Nine Essays in Phenomenology (ed. by A. T. Tymieniecka), Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, 1959.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Ideen II, § 28; but the doctrine of the autogenesis of the ego is surely suggested in the same work, p. 102.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Ibid, p. 310f.

    Google Scholar 

  79. P.Ps., pp. 207–208.

    Google Scholar 

  80. CM, § 32. On ‘habitualities’, see P. Ricoeur, Husserl, pp. 54–55.

    Google Scholar 

  81. G. Funke, loc. cit., pp. 22–23.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Seebohm, e.g., holds that the concept of hyle may be non-sensualistically interpreted within the framework of the intentionality thesis. See loc. cit. p. 97 fn. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  83. P. Ricoeur, Freedom and Nature, pp. 373–409.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Ideas I, § 53.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Ibid., § 53.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Section 2, Chapter 3.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Ideen II, pp. 56, 158f.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Ibid., p. 151.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Ibid., p. 151f.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Ibid., p. 153.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Ideen III, p. 118.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Ibid., p. 124. From this point of view, Ricocur’s statement (in his Husserl, p. 61) that the distinction between existence and objectivity is not known to Husserl may only be conditionally accepted.

    Google Scholar 

  93. CM, § 28.

    Google Scholar 

  94. P.Ps., p. 197.

    Google Scholar 

  95. Ideen I, § 38.

    Google Scholar 

  96. P. Ricceur, Freedom and Nature, pp. 387–389. 04

    Google Scholar 

  97. CM, esp. § 9.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Krisis, p. 474.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1970 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht-Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mohanty, J.N. (1970). Husserl’s Concept of Intentionality. In: Tymieniecka, AT. (eds) Analecta Husserliana. Analecta Husserliana, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-3326-8_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-3326-8_6

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-3328-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-3326-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics