Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Perspectives in vertebrate science ((PIVS,volume 6))

Synopsis

The idea already conceived by Lamarck, namely, that there are two kinds of evolution, which may be called ‘divergent’ and ‘progressive’ respectively, has been borne out by modern phylogenetic classification. With two kinds of evolution two different mechanisms are required. Basing the argument on the axiom of competitive exclusion it is concluded that the prerequisite for divergent evolution is isolation. Isolation may depend upon factors extrinsic to the organism themselves, in which case it is random; when it depends upon intrinsic factors it is non-random. Isolation may lead to taxonic divergence, that is, the origin of a new taxon, but it may also simply serve the purpose of taxonic survival, because it prevents the access of potential rivals. Taxonic divergence depends upon reproductive isolation. This may happen fortuitously when a few individuals become isolated spatially, in which case they may with the course of time form a new taxon. Non-random taxonic divergence may occur if reproductive isolation is established by chromosome re-arrangements and a variety of other factors. Random taxonic survival may occur as a consequence of comprehensive geological events, as exemplified by the marsupials in Australia. Non-random taxonic survival follows from ecological isolation, due to the possession of habits or properties which protect the organisms from competitors. It may be presumed that sooner or later taxonic survival leads to taxonic divergence. Progressive evolution is the result of the interspecific competition which takes place when two taxa happen to occupy the same niche. When this occurs, the axiom of competitive exclusion predicts that one of the taxa must succumb, and the other one, the dominant taxon, prevails. As this has occurred repeatedly in the course of time, the survival of ever more dominant forms has ensued, resulting in progressive evolution. It is shown that upon the adoption of certain simple criteria and a particular rule, the establishment of a phylogenetic classification may lead to the following three results: the polarity and the dominant phylogenetic lineage is established, and it becomes possible to test and to corroborate the ecological theory, which predicts that each nondominant taxon will be isolated, randomly or non-randomly, as the case may be. Since an unadapted organism cannot survive, the concept of ‘adaptation’ does not have the importance usually ascribed to it. Organisms do not survive because they are adapted, but because they are isolated.

Reprint requests should be sent to this address

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 259.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Atz, J.W. 1985. The use of phylogenetic trees in comparative endocrinology, pp. 1143–1148. In: B. Lofts & N.W. Holmes (ed.) Current Trends in Comparative Endocrinology, The University Press, Hong Kong.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ax, P. 1984. Das phylogenetische System Systematisierung der lebenden Natur auf Grund ihrer Phylogenese. Gustav Fischer, Stuttgart. 349 pp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. 1888. The life and letters of Charles Darwin, including an autobiographical chapter. F. Darwin (ed.), three volumes, John Murray, London. 395 pp., 393 pp., 418 pp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewar, D. & F. Finn. 1909. The making of species. John Lane, London. 400 pp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardiner, B.G. 1982. Tetrapod classification. Zool. J. Linn. Soc. 74: 207–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, G. 1960. The competitive exclusion principle. Science 131: 1292–1297.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Hardisty, M.W. 1982. Lampreys and hagfishes: Analysis of cyclostome relationships, pp. 165–260. In: M.W. Hardisty & I.C. Potter (ed.) The Biology of Lampreys, vol. 4B, Academic Press, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hennig, W. 1966. Phylogenetic systematics. University of Illinois Press, Urbana. 263 pp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchinson, G.E.D. 1975. Variations on a theme by Robert MacArthur. pp. 492–521. In: M.L. Cody & J.M. Diamond (ed.) Ecology and Evolution of Communities, Belknap Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huxley, J.S. 1942. Evolution. The modern synthesis. George Allen and Unwin, London. 645 pp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Janvier, P. 1981. The phylogeny of the Craniata, with particular reference to the significance of fossil ‘agnathans’. J. Vert. Palaeont. 1: 129–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lagios, M.D. 1979. The coelacanth and the Chondrichthyes as sister groups: a review of shared apomorph characters and a cladistic analysis and reinterpretation. Occasional Papers of the California Academy of Sciences 134: 25–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamarck, J.B. 1914. Zoological philosophy (transl. H. Elliot). Macmillan, London. 410 pp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R.C. 1974. The genetic basis of evolutionary change. Columbia University Press, New York. 364 pp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Løvtrup, S. 1977. The phylogeny of Vertebrata. John Wiley, London. 330 pp.

    Google Scholar 

  • LøVtrup, S. 1982. The four theories of evolution. Rivista di Biologia 75: 53–66, 231–272, 385–409.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Løvtrup, S. 1985. On the classification of the taxon Tetrapoda. Systematic Zoology 34: 463–470.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Løvtrup, S. 1987a. Darwinism — the refutation of a myth. Croom Helm, London. 469 pp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Løvtrup, S. 1987b. On species and other taxa. Cladistics 3: 171–191.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. 1963. Animal species and evolution. The Belknap Press, Cambridge. 797 pp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, G. 1987. Ontogeny, phylogeny, paleontology and the biogenetic law. Systematic Zoology 27: 324–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Patterson, C. 1982. Morphological characters and homology, pp. 21–74. In: K.A. Joysey & A.E. Friday (ed.) Problems of Phylogenetic Reconstruction, Academic Press, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riedl, R. 1975. Die Ordnung des Lebendigen: Systerribedingungen der Evolution. Paul Parey, Hamburg. 372 pp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokal, R.R. & P.H.A. Sneath. 1963. Principles of numerical taxonomy. W.H. Freeman, San Francisco. 359 pp.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, M.J.D. 1978. Modes of speciation. W.H. Freeman, San Francisco. 455 pp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodfield, A. 1973. Darwin, teleology and taxonomy. Philosophy 48: 35–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1989 Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Løvtrup, S. (1989). On divergent and progressive evolution. In: Bruton, M.N. (eds) Alternative Life-History Styles of Animals. Perspectives in vertebrate science, vol 6. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2605-9_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2605-9_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-7675-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-2605-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics