Skip to main content

Conceptual Change and the Rhetoric of Evolutionary Theory: ‘Force Talk’ as a Case Study and Challenge for Science Pedagogy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Philosophy of Biology

Part of the book series: History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences ((HPTL,volume 1))

Abstract

Darwinian theories vary. Some of the variation consists in differences in conceptual frames. These identify the entities and processes over which natural selection ranges. Different conceptual schemes are most easily identifiable by the different images, similes, analogies, and metaphors—in general, tropes—by which evolutionary theories are brought to bear on particulars. I show how Darwin’s metaphors balanced function, chance, and determinism in living things by seeing artificial selection in terms of natural forces and natural forces in terms of artificial selection. I then argue that the Modern Evolutionary Synthesis highlighted Darwin’s view of natural selection as a creative process, which earlier Darwinians had abandoned, by shifting to a conceptual framework and family of tropes that made images of force and design recessive. With the use of mathematical game theory to model gene frequency changes in the 1970s, however, design and force metaphors became dominant again, with the unintended result that images of Darwinism as promoting a god-abandoned, dog-eat-dog that had lodged deeply in popular culture long ago, were reawakened. Analysis of evolutionary discourse that hopes to reach students and the public must attend closely to the uses and abuses of conceptual tropes, ‘force’ and ‘design’ among them. This poses a question for pedagogy. How well can one teach evolutionary science without teaching some of its conceptual, and hence its rhetorical, history? Will students perceive this history as enhancing their knowledge of evolution, as an irrelevant waste of time, or, in its contentious diversity, as undermining its scientific status? Answering this question calls for empirical research.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Unless otherwise noted, references to letters to and from Darwin are to the Darwin Correspondence Database [DCD] http://www.darwinproject.ac.uk

  2. 2.

    One can see the over-reliance on chance on display in Steve Fuller’s inaccurate description of natural selection. “Chance mutations,” he writes, “are the driving force of evolution.” So natural selection consists of “compounded historical accidents” (Fuller 2007, pp. 31, 48). It is not surprising that Fuller testified on the side of intelligent design in Kitzmiller vs. Dover (Pa.) Area School Board (2005). If natural selection is anything as chancy as Bowen, Fuller, or the physicist Steven Weinberg imagine it to be, intelligent design can seem a sensible alternative (Weinberg 1992).

  3. 3.

    The passage also shows that neither did Darwin confuse selection for traits with selection of traits. The whiteness of arctic birds is (possibly) a “direct effect” of cold not of the protection it affords against prey. If we choose to call this selection at all, it is selection of whiteness, not for it. The philosopher Elliott Sober illustrates the distinction by imagining a sorting mechanism that allows balls of several sizes to fall through holes of various sizes. Balls of each size are painted a different color. There is selection for size, but only selection of color (Sober 1984, pp. 99–100).

  4. 4.

    The elimination of Darwin’s natural teleology is encoded in the stress Darwinians placed on natural selection as a mechanism. Spencer writes that “survival of the fittest” is Darwin’s ‘natural selection’ “express[ed] in mechanical terms” (Spencer 1864, I, p. 445). Wallace liked to compare natural selection to a steam engine fitted out with a Watt automatic governor. In contrasting Spencer with Darwin I take myself to be in agreement with, and reliant on, Gayon (1995). I do not mean to contravene Gayon’s claim that for Darwin natural selection is not metaphorical, but real (Gayon 1995, p. 269). I merely put his point otherwise. Darwin’s interactionist and explanatory sense of metaphor was itself a casualty of his caving in to allies who viewed metaphor as mere decoration. In acknowledging ‘survival of the fittest’ in the 3th and subsequent editions of the Origin Darwin says that natural selection falls on the metaphorical side of a distinction between literal and metaphorical senses. (For his variant ways of making this concession, see Peckham 1959, p. 165.) But this distinction severely disrupts the “one long argument” of the text.

  5. 5.

    Some philosophers of biology are not as insouciant as Fisher in believing that the many underlying context-dependent causes of fitness can be omitted from any definition of the concept of fitness that purports to understand its role in a theory of adaptive natural selection (Sober 1984; Brandon 1990, p. 13). To be sure, these philosophers are understandably as jumpy as Fisher about identifying fitness solely with the aggressive traits with which the popular mind still associates it. But they take fitness to be identical with relative adaptedness and so think it depends by definition on an array of underlying differences as its components. These do not have to be stated unless we are interested in analyzing one or another of them (for a recent discussion of fitness, see Ariew and Lewontin 2004).

  6. 6.

    The makers of the Modern Synthesis called mutation, selection, drift, and gene flow “factors” because they thought of themselves as contributing to the resolution of a long-running “factors of evolution debate” that had been unfolding ever since Spencer wrote a book with that title in 1886 (Pearce 2010).

  7. 7.

    On selectionist explanations of adaptation as naturally teleological, see Wright (1976) and Brandon (1981, 1990). On Darwin’s inclination to say this, see Gray (1963), p. 237, Darwin to Gray, June 5, 1874, DCD, entry 9483; see also Lennox (1993, 1994), Depew (2008), and Lennox and Kampourakis, this volume.

  8. 8.

    In contrast to E. O. Wilson, who has recanted his earlier embrace of genocentric kin-selection theory in favor of the trait-group selectionism of D. S. Wilson (Nowak et al. 2010).

  9. 9.

    To be fair, it should be noted that Dobzhansky, too, had a weakness for metaphysics, although more on the idealist than the materialist side. From the start, he argued that natural selection is creative because it evolves adaptations for adapting and evolving. It does so by preserving variation that may prove useful in changed and changing environments and by favoring the evolution of phenotypic plasticity (Dobzhansky 1937). But toward the end of his life Dobzhansky went further. He extended his conception of natural selection’s creativity to evolution’s creativity in a way that was only a whisker away from the religiously inspired, progress-oriented orthogenesis of Pierre Teilhard de Chardin (Dobzhansky 1970, pp. 430–431).

  10. 10.

    The origins of this analogy have little to do with the reason for its subsequent diffusion. The analogy was initially invoked by analytical philosophers of biology who were trying to decide whether the Hardy-Weinberg equilibrium formula is a law of nature. David Hull, in his pioneering Philosophy of Biological Science, evoked Newton’s laws as a model, but followed the founders of the Modern Synthesis in calling natural selection, mutation, drift, and gene flows agents and processes (Hull 1974, p. 58). It was the philosopher Elliott Sober who developed the Newtonian analogy further by talking about mutation, selection, drift, and gene flow as forces (Sober 1984). He should not be held too responsible for the rhetorical uses to which this idea has been put.

  11. 11.

    Ariew’s and Matthen’s critique of ‘force talk’ is aimed at knocking the causal wind out of population genetics in order to assign causal explanatory power (as opposed to the merely descriptive uses of population genetics) to the developmental process of individual organisms as the source of variation and the locus of adaptation. The rise of evolutionary developmentalism (“evo-devo”) might well be nurturing a paradigm shift from populations back to organisms (Walsh 2006; Pigliucci and Kaplan 2006; for “evo-devo” see Love, this volume). Still, it is worth noting that the population-genetical paradigm it wishes to displace is not as wedded to the force metaphor as these critics presume and so does not rise and fall with it. As I have shown, the metaphor has a recent origin, not an ancient pedigree.

  12. 12.

    Ironically, the introductory biology textbook that some of the same authors have written for non-majors does a better and more coherent job of inviting students to imaginatively project themselves into an evolutionary and ecological perspective. Because it does not have to teach all the concepts that majors and future health professionals will need it is not burdened with smoothing out the inherent heterogeneity of these concepts, which were developed at different stages in the history of biology and often contain in the way they are named and described traces of the conceptual frameworks in which they first arose.

References

  • Ariew, A., and R.C. Lewontin. 2004. The confusions of fitness. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55: 347–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, P. (Ed). 1987. Charles Darwin’s notebooks, ed. P. Barrett. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bateson, P., and P. Gluckman. 2011. Plasticity, robustness, and evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Beer, G. 2000. Darwin’s garden plots. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. X. 1st ed. 1985.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Behe, Michael. 1996. Darwin’s black box. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Black, M. 1962. Models and metaphors. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R. 1981. Biological teleology: Questions and explanations. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 12: 91–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R. 1990. Adaptation and environment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, N., J. Teece, M. Taylor, E. Simon, and J. Dickey. 2009. Biology: Concepts and connections, 6th ed. San Francisco: Pearson Benjamin Cummings.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, F. (ed.). 1959. Life and letters of Charles Darwin. New York: Basic Books. With introduction by George Gaylord Simpson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. 1966. On the origin of species. Facsimile of the 1st edition, 1859, London: J. Murray, ed. E Mayr. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. 1986. The blind watchmaker. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. 1989/1976. The selfish gene. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. 2006. The god delusion. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Depew, D. 2008. Consequence etiology and biological teleology in Aristotle and Darwin. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 38(4): 379–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Depew, D. 2009. The rhetoric of Darwin’s origin of species. In The Cambridge companion to the origin of species, ed. M. Ruse and R. Richards, 237–255. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Depew, D. 2011a. Adaptation as process: The future of Darwinism and the legacy of Theodosius Dobzhansky. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biology and the Biomedical Sciences 42: 89–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Depew, D. 2011b. Accident, adaptation, & teleology in Aristotle, Empedocles, and Darwinism. In Biological evolution: Facts and theories: A critical appraisal after 150 years after the origin of species, ed. G. Auletta, M. Leclerc, and R. Martinez, 461–478. Rome: Gregorian and Biblical Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Depew, D. 2012. The rhetoric of evolutionary theory. Biological Theory. doi:10.1007/s13752-012-0054-2.

  • Depew, D., and B. Weber. 1995. Darwinism evolving: Systems dynamics and the genealogy of natural selection. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky, T. 1937. Genetics and the origin of species. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky, T. 1970. Genetics of the evolutionary process. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky, T. 1973. Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution. The American Biology Teacher 35: 125–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eldredge, N. 1985. Unfinished synthesis. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eldredge, N., and S.J. Gould. 1972. Punctuated equilibria: An alternative to phyletic gradualism. In Models in paleobiology, ed. T.J.M. Schopf, 82–115. San Francisco: Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • England, R. 2001. Natural selection, teleology, and the logos: From Darwin to the Oxford Neo-Darwinists, 1859–1909. Osiris, 270–287, 2nd Series, vol. 16, Science in theistic contexts: Cognitive dimensions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, R.A. 1930. The genetical theory of natural selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, S. 2007. Science v. religion? Intelligent design and the problem of evolution. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gayon, J. 1995. Sélection naturelle ou survie des plus aptes? Éléments pour une histoire du concept de fitness dans la théorie évolutionniste. In Nature, histoire, société: Essais en hommage à Jacques Ro er, ed. C. Blanckaert, J.L. Fischer, and R. Rey, 263–287. Paris: Klincksieck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. (ed.). 1990. The empire of chance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S.J. 1980. Is a new and general theory of evolution emerging? Paleobiology 6: 119–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S.J. 1989. The wheel of fortune and the wedge of progress. Natural History 19: 14–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S.J., and R.C. Lewontin. 1979. The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London Series B 205(1161): 581–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gray, A. 1963. Darwiniana. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Originally published in 1876.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, W.D. 1964. Genetic evolution of social behavior. Journal of Theoretical Biology 7(1): 16–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, M. 1963. Models and analogies in science. London: Sheed and Ward.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodge, M. 1977. The structure and strategy of Darwin’s ‘long argument’. British Journal for the History of Science 10: 237–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodge, M. 1985. Darwin as lifelong generation theorist. In The Darwinian heritage, ed. D. Kohn, 207–243. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofstadter, R. 1944. Social Darwinism in American thought. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. 1974. Philosophy of biological science. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kampourakis, K. 2013. Teaching about adaptation: Why evolutionary history matters. Science & Education 22(2): 173–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kampourakis, K., and V. Zogza. 2007. Students’ preconceptions about evolution: How accurate is the characterization as “Lamarckian” when considering the history of evolutionary thought? Science & Education 16(3–5): 393–422.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kampourakis, K., and V. Zogza. 2008. Students’ intuitive explanations of the causes of homologies and adaptations. Science & Education 17(1): 27–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kampourakis, K., and V. Zogza. 2009. Preliminary evolutionary explanations: A basic framework for conceptual change and explanatory coherence in evolution. Science & Education 18(10): 1313–1340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kellogg, V. 1907. Darwinism today. New York: Holt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lack, D. 1947. Darwin’s finches. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., and M. Johnson. 1980. Metaphors we live by. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lennox, J.G. 1993. Darwin was a teleologist. Biology and Philosophy 8: 405–421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lennox, J.G. 1994. Teleology by another name: A reply to Ghiselin. Biology and Philosophy 9: 493–495.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewens, T. 2004. Organisms and artifacts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M., and A. Ariew. 2002. Two ways of thinking about fitness and natural selection. Journal of Philosophy 99: 55–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith, J. 1982. Evolution and the theory of games. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. 1942. Systematics and the origin of species. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. 1978. Evolution. In Evolution: A scientific American book, 2–11. San Francisco: Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. 1980. Prologue: Some thoughts on the history of the evolutionary synthesis. In The evolutionary synthesis, ed. E. Mayr and W. Provine, 1–48. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. 1988. Toward a new philosophy of biology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. 1991. One long argument: Charles Darwin and the genesis of modern evolutionary thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McComas, W.F. 1997. The discovery and nature of evolution by natural selection: Misconceptions and lessons from the history of science. The American Biology Teacher 59(8): 492–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nehm, R.H., and L. Reilly. 2007. Biology majors’ knowledge and misconceptions of natural selection. BioScience 57: 263–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nehm, R., M. Rector, and M. Huy. 2010. ‘Force talk’ in evolutionary explanation: Metaphors and misconceptions. Evolution Education and Outreach 3: 605–613.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nowak, M., C. Tarnita, and E.O. Wilson. 2010. The evolution of eusociality. Nature 466: 1057–1062.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee, J., K. Laland, and M. Feldman. 2003. Niche construction. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama, S., P. Grifftihs, and R. Gray (eds.). 2001. Cycles of contingency: Developmental systems and evolution. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearce, T. 2010. From ‘circumstances’ to ‘environment’: Herbert Spencer and the origins of the idea of organism–Environment interaction. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 41: 241–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peckham, M. (ed.). 1959. The origin of species: A variorum text. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M., and M. Boudry. 2011. Why machine-information metaphors are bad for science and science education. Science & Education 20(5–6): 453–471.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M., and J. Kaplan. 2006. Making sense of natural selection. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pink, R., K. Wicks, D.P. Caley, E.M. Punch, L. Jacobs, and D.R.F. Carter. 2011. Pseudogenes: Pseudo-functional or key regulators in health and disease. RNA 17: 792–798. doi:10.1261/rna.2658311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Provine, W. 1971. The origins of theoretical population genetics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. 1978. The rule of metaphor. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. 1975. Darwin’s debt to philosophy: An examination of the influence of the philosophical ideas of John F.W. Herschel and William Whewell on the development of Charles Darwin’s theory of evolution. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 6: 159–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. 1999. Mystery of mysteries: Is evolution a social construction? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. 2000. Darwin and the philosophers: Epistemological factors in the development and reception of the origin of species. In Biology and epistemology, ed. R. Creath and J. Maienschein, 3–26. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. 2010. Current status of research in teaching and learning evolution. II. Pedagogical issues. Science & Education 19: 539–571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. 1984. The nature of selection. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 2nd ed. 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E., and D. Wilson. 1998. Unto others. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spencer, H. 1864. Principles of biology. London: John Chapman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stauffer, R. (ed.). 1975. Charles Darwin’s natural selection. Second part of his ‘big species book’. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, D.L. 2011. Evolution, development, and the predictable genome. Greenwood Village: Roberts & Company Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trivers, R.L. 1971. The evolution of reciprocal altruism. The Quarterly Review of Biology 46(1): 35–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vosniadou, S. (ed.). 2008. International handbook of research on conceptual change. New York/London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D.M. 2006. Organisms as natural purposes: The contemporary evolutionary perspective. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37: 771–791.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, S. 1992. Dreams of a final theory. New York: Pantheon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, G.C. 1966. Adaptation and natural selection. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E.O. 1975. Sociobiology: The new synthesis. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, S. 1932. The roles of mutation, inbreeding, crossbreeding, and selection in evolution. Proceedings of the Sixth International Congress on Genetics 1: 355–366.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, L. 1976. Teleological explanations. Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I wish to thank André Ariew, Deirdre Egan, Kostas Kampourakis, and Jaime Sabel for substantial and collegially offered help in developing the ideas in this chapter. I developed its basic picture of Darwinism’s history in my long collaboration with Bruce Weber.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Depew .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Depew, D. (2013). Conceptual Change and the Rhetoric of Evolutionary Theory: ‘Force Talk’ as a Case Study and Challenge for Science Pedagogy. In: Kampourakis, K. (eds) The Philosophy of Biology. History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6537-5_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics