Skip to main content

General Formal Ontology (GFO): A Foundational Ontology for Conceptual Modelling

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Theory and Applications of Ontology: Computer Applications

Abstract

The current chapter presents an overview about the current stage of the foundational ontology GFO. GFO (General Formal Ontology). GFO is a foundational ontology integrating objects and processes. It is being developed by the research group Onto-Med (Ontologies in Medicine) at the University of Leipzig. Unique selling properties of GFO are the following: it includes categories of objects (3D objects) as well as of processes (4D entities) and both are integrated into one coherent framework. GFO presents a multi-categorial approach by admitting universals, concepts, and symbol structures and their interrelations. GFO adopts categories pertaining to levels of reality, and it is designed to support interoperability by principles of ontological mapping and reduction. GFO contains several novel ontological modules, in particular, a module for functions and a module for roles. GFO is designed for applications, firstly in medical, biological, and biomedical areas, but also in the fields of economics and sociology.

Contribution for the TAO-Volume

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    A more detailed exposition of GFO is presented in Herre et al. (2006b).

  2. 2.

    http://www.onto-med.de

  3. 3.

    The development of axiomatic systems for GFO is work in progress and will be published as Part II of the General Formal Ontology.

  4. 4.

    These axiomatized ontologies of a domain are influenced by the assumed views and the classification principles from which different conceptualizations can be derived. Furthermore, there is no sufficiently founded criterion to establish the equivalence of two ontologies. Hence, the orthogonality criterion, as expounded in Smith et al. (2007), must be rejected.

  5. 5.

    One of these ontologies, called BFO (Basic Formal Ontology) (Grenon, 2003), has its source in the GOL- project which started in 1999 as a common project of the department of formal concepts (Institute for Computer Science) and the Institute for Medical Informatics of the University of Leipzig. GOL was the scientific basis for a research programme related to a Wolfgang-Paul Prize advertised in 2001. Since June 2002 GFO and BFO were independently developed.

  6. 6.

    Our approach to categories is inspired by the ideas of Jorge Gracia (1999). We consider Gracia’s approach as an important contribution to the philosophical foundation of conceptual modelling.

  7. 7.

    The mental representation of a concept allows us to understand a linguistic expression. Concepts are outside of individual minds, but they are anchored, on the one hand, in individual minds by the concepts’ mental representation, and on the other hand, in society as a result of communication and usage of language.

  8. 8.

    The ability to generate and use symbol structures seems to be the most basic assumption for complex communication. Here, an important aspect of the ability of humans to construct symbolic structures and to identify tokens as instances of symbols. The ultimate transmission of information must use spatio-temporal tokens as bearers.

  9. 9.

    If the theory is sufficiently expressive then an absolute consistency proof, based on finitary methods, is impossible. Hence, consistency proofs have a relative character; they are based on the method of formally reducing the considered theory to another already established theory whose consistency has a higher degree of evidence.

  10. 10.

    One must distinguish between symbols and tokens. Only tokens, being physical instances of symbols, can be perceived and transmitted through space and time.

  11. 11.

    The study of mental representations of concepts is an important topic of cognitive psychology and cognitive linguistics. The theory of prototypes is an influential approach in this area of research (Rosch, 1975).

  12. 12.

    There is the general problem where the cut is made and defined between the subject and the independent real world. Several options are possible. Our approach can be justified by interpreting the phenomena as realization of dispositions of the objective independent world. These dispositions need a subject to come to appearance, more precisely, these appearances are realizations of dispositions within a subject. Hence, the phenomenal world is, on the one hand, anchored and founded in the objective reality, on the other hand it is realized in the subjective world. This connection is the basis for GFO’s integrative realism.

  13. 13.

    The GFO approach to time is related to what P. Hayes calls the glass continuum (Hayes, 1995). Furthermore, we advance and refine the theory of Brentano (1976).

  14. 14.

    Again, we use ideas of Brentano (1976) and Chisholm (1983) for our theory.

  15. 15.

    A perpetuant has - similar as a primitive universal - an implicit relation to time. The persistence of this kind of individual derives from its cognitive character. Persistence seems to be reasonable only for items that are invariant through a time-interval and at the same time are related at time-points of its duration to individuals which are immediately related to time and which may have different properties at different time-points. Such items are either special primitive universals or particular cognitive individuals. We do not apply the notion of persistance to abstract individuals, as to the number 100.

  16. 16.

    GFO presents a solution to a problem which arises in Smith and Varzi (2000). GFO gives a new interpretation of bona-fide boundaries in terms of natural boundaries. The claim stated in Smith and Varzi (2000) that bona fide boundaries cannot touch is counter-intuitive and ontologically false. A similar critics is sated in Ridder (2002).

  17. 17.

    We assume an eternal view on processes. If we are speaking about the future or the past then these are relative notions that are related to an observer.

  18. 18.

    The representation of a change could additionally mention also two sub-processes p(1), p(2), where both processes meet, and e(1) is the right boundary of p(1), and e(2) is the left boundary of p(2).

  19. 19.

    Recall that “coincident process boundaries” refers to the fact that the respective time-boundaries coincide. It does not mean that the presentials themselves should coincide.

  20. 20.

    The categories of situations and situoids as discussed in this paper are a first attempt to account for this in a systematic manner.

  21. 21.

    This resembles the idea of “indirect qualities” in Masolo et al. (2002).

  22. 22.

    In earlier texts these were referred to as “properties” and “qualities”.

  23. 23.

    Note that the term “property value ” here resembles Gärdenfors’ notion of “property”, our “property” his “quality dimension”

  24. 24.

    A quality space consists of all “quales” (our property values) of some “quality” (our property).

  25. 25.

    Note that “context” here is just an auxiliary notion for introducing roles, instead of being presented in a profound ontological analysis.

  26. 26.

    The literature provides fills and hasRole as other common terms for the plays relation.

  27. 27.

    Other terms in the literature are natural type (Guarino, 1992), natural kind (Wilkerson, 1995), phenomenon (Sowa, 1984), base classifier in UML (Rumbaugh et al., 1999), and basic concept in Sunagawa (2005).

  28. 28.

    Processes, as other individuals, are not completely free of cognition. To clarify this situation we introduced in Section 14.2.4 layers between the subject and reality. The layer of perception connects the subject with reality and we stipulate that the phenomenal world, though cognitively biased, belongs to the reality outside the subject.

  29. 29.

    Persistants apply to every process, whereas the construction of perpetuants is restricted to a particular class of material processes.

  30. 30.

    A full elaboration of our approach to personal identity is much more complicated. It must consider the underlying process, the place of consciousness and will, and the dynamic interrelations between the persistant, the perpetuant, the presentials, and the process.

  31. 31.

    This vagueness cannot be avoided because we assume that the specification of OntMod(P) exhibits a decidable set of conditions. By Gödel’s incompleteness theorems a complete specification of P cannot be, in general, achieved.

  32. 32.

    The term “an execution of α approximates p” needs further explanation. This can be made precise by using the approaches of computable and constructive analysis (Weihrauch, 2000; Geuvers et al., 2007). The development of an ontological theory of computational simulation of natural processes is in progress and will be published elsewhere.

  33. 33.

    It is an open problem whether every reasonable natural process is computable (Kreisel, 1974).

References

  • Allen, J.F., and P.J. Hayes. 1990. Moments and points in an interval-based temporal logic. Computational Intelligence 5(4):225–238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D.M. 1997. A world of states of affairs. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashburner, M., C.A. Ball, J.A. Blake, D. Botstein, H. Butler, J.M. Cherry, A.P. Davis, K. Dolinski, S.S. Dwight, J.T. Eppig, M.A. Harris, D.P. Hill, L. Issel-Tarver, A. Kasarskis, S. Lewis. et al. 2000. Gene ontology: Tool for the unification of biology. Nature Genetics 25(1):25–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baader, F., D. Calvanese, D. McGuinness, D. Nardi, and P. Patel-Schneider, eds. 2003. The description logic handbook: Theory, implementation and applications. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bachman, C.W., and M. Daya. 1977. The role concept in data models. In Proceedings of the 3rd International Conference on Very Large Databases, 464–476. IEEE Computer Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bard, J., S.Y. Rhee, and M. Ashburner. 2005. An ontology for cell types. Genome Biology 6(2):R21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J., and J. Perry. 1983. Situations and Attitudes. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Book/MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloch, E. 1985. Subject-Objekt. Frankfurt/M: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boella, G, J. Odell, L. van der Torre, and H. Verhagen. eds. 2005. Proceedings of the 2005 AAAI Fall Symposium ’Roles, an Interdisciplinary Perspective: Ontologies, Languages, and Multiagent Systems’, Nov 3–6, Arlington, Virginia, number FS-05-08 in Fall Symposium Series Technical Reports, Menlo Park, CA: AAAI Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Booch, G., J. Rumbaugh, and I. Jacobson. 1999. The unified modeling language user guide. Object Technology Series. Reading, MA: Addison Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braunwald, E., K.J. Isselbacher, R.G. Petersdorf, J.D. Wilson, J.B. Martin, and A.S. Fauci. eds. 1987. Harrison’s principles of internal medicine, 11th edition. New York, NY: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. 1976. Philosophische Untersuchungen zu Raum, Zeit und Kontinuum, eds. S. Körner, and R.M. Chisholm, Hamburg: Felix- Meiner Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooksbank, C., G. Cameron, and J. Thornton. 2005. The european bioinformatics institute’s data resources: Towards systems biology. Nucleic Acids Research 33(Database issue):D46–D53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burek, P. 2007. Ontology of functions: A domain-independent framework for modeling functions, PhD thesis. University of Leipzig, Institute of Informatics (IfI).

    Google Scholar 

  • Burek, P., R. Hoehndorf, F. Loebe, J. Visagie, H. Herre, and J. Kelso. 2006. A top-level ontology of functions and its application in the open biomedical ontologies. Bioinformatics 22(14):e66–e73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casati, R., and A. Varzi. 1994. Holes and other superficialities. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chandrasekaran, B., and J.R. Josephson. 1997. Representing functions as effect. In Proceedings of the Functional Modeling Workshop, Paris, France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R.M. 1983. Boundaries as dependent particulars. Grazer Philosophische Studien 20:87–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang, C.C., and H.J. Keisler. 1977. Model theory. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Keizer, N.F., A. Abu-Hanna, and J.H.M. Zwetsloot-Schonk. 2000. Understanding terminological systems I: Terminology and typology. Methods of Information in Medicine 39(1):16–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dori, D. 2002. Object-process methodology: A holistic systems paradigm. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. 2000. Conceptual spaces: The geometry of thought, A Bradford Book. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Genesereth, M.R., and R.E. Fikes. 1992. Knowledge interchange format. Technical Report Logic-92-1, Stanford Logic Group, Stanford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geuvers, H., M. Nigqui, B. Spitters, and F. Wiedijk. 2007. Constructive analysis, types and exact real numbers. Mathematical Structures in Computer Science 17:3–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gracia, J.J.E. 1999. Metaphysics and its tasks: The search for the categorial foundation of knowledge. SUNY series in Philosophy. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grenon, P. 2003. Spatio-temporality in basic formal ontology: SNAP and SPAN. http://www.ifomis.org/Research/IFOMISReports/IFOMIS%20Report%2005_2003.pdf

  • Gruber, T.R. 1993. A translation approach to portable ontology specifications. Knowledge Acquisition 5(2):199–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guarino, N. 1992. Concepts, attributes and arbitrary relations: Some linguistic and ontological criteria for structuring knowledge bases. Data & Knowledge Engineering 8(3):249–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guarino, N., and C.A. Welty. 2000. A formal ontology of properties. In Knowledge engineering and knowledge management: methods, models, and tools, eds. R. Dieng and O. Corby. Proceedings of the 12th International Conference on Knowledge Engineering and Knowledge Management (EKAW2000), Juan-les-Pins, France, Oct 2–6, LNCS 1937, 97–112. Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Guarino, N., and C.A. Welty. 2001. Supporting ontological analysis of taxonomic relationships. Data & Knowledge Engineering 39(1):51–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guarino, N., and C. Welty. 2004. An overview of ontoclean. In Handbook on ontologies, International Handbooks on Information Systems, Chapter 8, eds. S. Staab, and R. Studer, 151–159. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guizzardi, G., and G. Wagner. 2004a. Towards ontological foundations for agent modelling concepts using the unified foundational ontology (UFO), LNCS 3508, June 2004, 110–124. doi:http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/1147248

  • Guizzardi, G., and G. Wagner. 2004b. A unified foundational ontology and some applications of it in business modelling. Proceedings of the CAiSE’04 Workshops. Faculty of Computer Science ands Information Technology, Riga Technical University, Riga, June 2004, vol. 3, 129–143, Riga, Latvia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, N. 1964. Der Aufbau der realen Welt. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter and Co.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hayes, P.J. 1995. A catalogue of temporal theories. Technical Report UIUC-BI-AI-96-01, University of Illinois.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heller, B., H. Herre, K. Lippoldt, M. Löffler. 2004. Standardized terminology for clinical trial protocols based on ontological top-level categories. In Computer-based support for clinical guidelines and protocols, eds. K. Kaiser, S. Miksch, S.W. Tu. Proceedings of the Symposium on Computerized Guidelines and Protocols. (CGP 2004), 13–14 Apr 2004. Prague. 46–60. Studies in Health Technology and Informatics, vol. 101. Amsterdam: IOS-Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herre, H., and B. Heller. 2006a. Semantic foundations of medical information systems based on top-level ontologies. Journal of Knowledge-Based Systems 19(2):107–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herre, H., B. Heller, P. Burek, F. Loebe, R. Hoehndorf, and H. Michalek. 2006b. General formal ontology (GFO) – A foundational ontology integrating objects and processes, Report Nr. 8, Onto-Med, IMISE.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herre, H. 2010. Ontology of mereological systems – A logical approach, this volume.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hermes, H. 1959. Zur Axiomatisierung der Mechanik. In The axiomatic method, eds. L. Henkin, P. Suppes, and A. Tarski, 282–290. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ingarden, R. 1964. Der Streit um die Existenz der Welt I (Existentialontologie). Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johansson, I. 1989. Ontological investigations: An inquiry into the categories of nature, man and society. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M., and G. Forbes. 1987. Is there a problem about persistence? Aristotelian Society 61:107–135.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kreisel, G. 1974. A notion of mechanistic theory. Synthese 29:16–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • J. Lehmann, S. Borgo, A. Gangemi, and C. Masolo. 2004. Causality and causation in DOLCE. In Formal Ontology in Information Systems: Proceedings of the International Conference FOIS 2004, vol 114 of Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence And Applications, eds. A.C. Varzi, and L. Vieu, 273–284, Amsterdam: IOS Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • D.B. Lenat, and R.V. Guha. 1990. Building large knowledge-based systems: Representation and inference in the cyc project. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1986. On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Basil blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loebe, F. 2003. An analysis of roles: Towards ontology-based modelling. Onto-Med Report 6, Onto-Med Research Group, University of Leipzig.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loebe, F. 2003. Abstract vs. social roles: A refined top-level ontological analysis. In Boella et al. [8], 93–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loebe, F. 2007. Abstract vs social roles_ Towards a general theoretical account or roles. Applied Ontology 2(2):127–158.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loux, M. 1998. Metaphysics: A contemporary introduction. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Masolo, C., S. Borgo, A. Gangemi, N. Guarino, and A. Oltramari. 2003. Wonderweb deliverable D18: Ontology library (final). Technical Report, Laboratory for Applied Ontology – ISTC-CNR, Trento.

    Google Scholar 

  • Masolo, C., S. Borgo, A. Gangemi, N. Guarino, A. Oltramari, and L.Schneider. 2002. Wonderweb deliverable D17. Preliminary Report Version 2.0, Laboratory for Applied Ontology – ISTC-CNR, Padova, IT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Masolo, C., L. Vieu, E. Bottazzi, C. Catenacci, R. Ferrario, A. Gangemi, and N. Guarino. 2004. Social roles and their descriptions. In Principles of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning: Proceedings of the 9th International Conference (KR2004.), eds. D. Dubois, C. Welty, and M.-A. Williams, Whistler, Canada, June 2–5, 267–277, Menlo Park, CA: AAAI Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MC Cray, A.T. 2006. Conceptualizing the world: Lessons from history. Journal of Biomedical Informatics 39:267–273.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niles, I., and A. Pease. 2001. Towards a standard upper ontology. In Formal Ontology in Information Systems: Collected Papers from the 2nd International Conference, Oct 2001, eds. C. Welty, and B. Smith, 2–9, New York, NY: ACM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pease, A., and I. Niles. 2002. IEEE standard upper ontology: A progress report. Knowledge Engineering Review 17(1):65–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poli, R. 2001. The basic problem of the theory of levels of reality. Axiomathes 12(3–4):261–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poli, R. 2002. Ontological methodology. International Journal of Human-Computer Studies 56(6):639–664.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pschyrembel, W., and O. Dornblüth. 2002. In Pschyrembel Klinisches Wörterbuch. 259th edition, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ridder, L. 2002. Mereologie. Frankfurt a. Main: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Roeder, I., and M. Loeffler. 2002. Anoval dynamic model of hematopoietic stem cell organizations based on the concept of within-tissue plasticity. Experimental Hematology 30:853–861.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosch, E. 1975. Cognitive representations of semantic categories. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 104:192–233.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosse, C., and J.L. Mejno. 2003. A reference ontology for biomedical informatics. The foundational model of anatomy. Journal of biomedical informatics 36:478–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rumbaugh, J., I. Jacobson, and G. Booch. 1999. The unified modeling. language reference manual. Object Technology Series. Reading, MA: Addison Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, S., and P. Norvig. 1995. Artificial intelligence: A modern approach. Prentice hall series in artificial intelligence. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sasajima, M., Y. Kitamura, M. Ikeda, and R. Mizoguchi. 1995. FBRL: A function and behavior representation language. In Proceedings of the 14th International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence, IJCAI 95, Montreal, Quebec, Canada, Aug 20–25, 1830–1836. San Francisco, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J.R. 1995. The construction of social reality. New York, NY: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seibt, J. 2003. Free process theory: towards a typology of processes. Axiomathes. 14(1):23–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shahar, Y. 1994. A knowledge-based method for temporal abstraction of clinical data. PhD thesis, Stanford, CA: Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. 2001. Four-dimensionalism: an ontology of persistences and time. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, B., and A. Varzi. 2000. Fiat and bona fide boundaries. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60(2):401–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, B. 2004. Beyond concepts: Ontology as reality representation. In FOIS, International conference on formal ontology and information systems,73–84, Turin: IOS Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, B., W.Ceusters, and R. Temmermann. 2005. Wüsteria. In Proceedings Medical Informatics Europe 2005, Geneva; Studies in Health Technology and Informatics 116:647–652.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, B. 2006. From concepts to clinical reality: An essay on the benchmarking of biomedical terminologies. Journal of Biomedical Informatics 39:288–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, B., and W. Ceusters. 2006. Ontology as the core discipline of biomedical informatics. In Computing, philosophy, and cognitive science. eds. C.D. Crnkovic, and S. Stuart. Cambridge, MA: Scholars Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, B. et. al. 2007. The OBO foundry: coordinated evolution of ontologies to support biomedical data integration. Nature biotechnology 25(11):1251–1255, Nov 2007.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sowa, J.F. 1984. Conceptual structures: Information processing in mind and machine. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sowa, J.F. 2000. Knowledge representation: logical, philosophical and computational foundations. Pacific Grove, CA: Brooks/Cole.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steimann, F. 2000. On the representation of roles in object-oriented and conceptual modelling. Data & Knowledge Engineering 35(1):83–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sunagawa, E., K. Kozaki, Y. Kitamura, and R. Mizoguchi. 2005. A framework for organizing role concepts in ontology development tool: Hozo. In Boella et al. [8], 136–143.

    Google Scholar 

  • SUO. 2004. IEEE P1600.1 Standard upper ontology working group (SUO WG). http://suo.ieee.org.

  • Szczerba, L.W. 1977. Interpretability of elementary theories. In eds. R.E. Butts, and J. Hintikka, Logic, foundations of mathematics and computability theory, volume 9 of The Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, 129–145. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, A. 1944. The semantic conception of truth and the foundation of semantics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 4:341–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, A. 1983. Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics: Papers from 1923 to 1938, 2nd edition,. eds. J. Corcoran, Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • W3C. 2004. Web Ontology Language (OWL) Specifications. W3C Recommendations, World WideWebConsortium (W3C), Cambridge, MA. http://www.w3.org/2004/OWL/.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weihrauch, K. 2000. Computable analysis. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, M. 1912. Experimentelle Studien über das Sehen von Bewegung. Zeitschrift für Psychologie 161–265.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, M. 1922. Untersuchungen zur Lehre von der Gestalt. I. Prinizpielle Bemerkungen.

    Google Scholar 

  • West, M., J. Sullivan, and H. Teijgeler. 2003. ISO/FDIS 15926-2: Lifecycle integration of process plant data including oil and gas production facilities. ISO TC184/SC4/WG3N1328, July 2003. http://www.tc184-sc4.org/wg3ndocs/wg3n1328/lifecycle_integration_schema.html.

  • Wilkerson, T.E. 1995. Natural kinds. Avebury Series in Philosophy. Aldershot, UK: Avebury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. 1922. Tractatus logico-philosophicus. (transl: C.K. Ogden) London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Many thanks to P. Burek, R. Hoehndorf, F. Loebe, H.Michalek who contributed significantly to the development of GFO. I am grateful to R. Poli and anonymous reviewers for their critical remarks that contribute to the quality of the paper. Thanks to M. West for fruitful discussions which lead to deeper insight into 4-dimensionalism. Finally, thanks to J. Gracia for inspiring discussions on the relations between different kinds of categories, and the proper interpretation of the notion of realism.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Heinrich Herre .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Herre, H. (2010). General Formal Ontology (GFO): A Foundational Ontology for Conceptual Modelling. In: Poli, R., Healy, M., Kameas, A. (eds) Theory and Applications of Ontology: Computer Applications. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-8847-5_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics