Skip to main content

Body and Movement: Basic Dynamic Principles

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Handbook of Phenomenology and Cognitive Science

Abstrct

Embodiment is to the body as enaction is to movement.1 In each instance, the primary term of the analogy attempts to embrace an animate reality in a way compatible with the science or strand of philosophy being practiced. In each instance, however, the primary term is uncongenial to the basic reality it aims to capture and describe. The lack of fit is indirectly but substantively attested to by indices of books on embodiment and enaction: either no entry exists for the tactile-kinesthetic/affective body and kinesthesia or paltry entries exist. In effect, the foundational ontological and epistemological reality of life is missing: animation is nowhere on the map.2 The lack of fit and missing reality are furthermore attested to by the terms in which proprioception is discussed and the fact that a clear-cut distinction and substantive understanding of the difference between proprioception and kinesthesia is nowhere in evidence (see Sheets-Johnstone 1999 for more on this topic). Proprioception is, properly speaking, not a “matter of debate among philosophers” - seemingly, a matter of determining the correct answer to a multiple-choice question.3 Properly speaking, proprioception is a matter of all manner of bodily organs that sense movement and deformations, a primordial form of animate awareness that began its evolutionary career in surface recognition sensitivity - tactility in the service of movement - that evolved into different external sensors registering movement - chordotonal organs, hair plates, sensilla, cilia, and so on - and that, with the advent of internal bodily organs sensing movement through muscular effort, evolved into kinesthesia (Mill 1976; Laverack 1976; Wright 1976; Dorsett 1976; see Sheets-Johnstone 1999 for a close examination and study of the data). As is evident, proprioception is the broader term with respect to kinesthesia. It refers to a sense of movement and position that includes tactility and gravitational orientation through vestibular sensory organs as well as kinesthesia. As its etymology indicates, kinesthesia in its primary, that is, experiential, sense denotes an awareness of movement, hence an awareness of dynamics, hence an awareness of a qualitatively felt kinetic flow. The flow may be felt as smooth, expansive, abrupt, attenuated, jagged, linear, curved, constricted, slow, and so on, including any and all possible combinations as the flow unfolds. Given the inherent qualitative spatio-temporal-energic character of kinesthesia, it is hardly surprising that discussions of body and of movement that omit kinesthesia from their register omit the very stuff of life and the qualitative nature of that stuff. They omit animation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 259.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This essay concentrates attention on embodiment. An essay titled “Animation: An Essential, Fundamental, and Properly Descriptive Concept” concentrates attention on enaction and is forthcoming 2009 in Continental Philosophy Review.

  2. 2.

    Opportunities for putting it squarely on the map clearly exist. Consider, for example, Hanna and Thompson’s “animalist” solution to what they term “the mind-body-body problem,” the latter referring to the tripartite sectioning of what they describe as “something” that is “at once a conscious subject, a living and lived body, and an objective material thing” (Hanna and Thompson 2003b, p. 24). In particular, Hanna and Thompson propose that mind and physical body are simply “dual aspects of one’s lived body” (ibid.), and that lived bodies are animal bodies. Their appeal to “dual aspect animalism” (ibid., p. 30) is oddly devoid of any reference to animation, precisely that which would ground their solution in the empirical realities of animate life through reference to proprioception and kinesthesia, the tactile-kinesthetic body and coordination dynamics, and that would flesh out their reliance on “cognitive ethology” (ibid., pp. 31-32) as an academically reputable support for their animalist solution.

  3. 3.

    See Thompson 2007, p. 464, n.3. Thompson cites José Bermúdez’s, Dorothée Legrand’s, and Shaun Gallagher’s “arguments” (as Thompson puts it) as to what proprioception is, that is, whether it is equivalent to prereflective self-consciousness or not and whether the latter consciousness is a perceptual or non-perceptual experience, encapsulating one’s body as object or as subject.

  4. 4.

     An editorial concern that the word animation “does not express the bodily nature of cognition” is thus answered; no ‘embodiment’ needed.

  5. 5.

     “We have chosen to take as a guideline the idea… that a successful scientific theory of cognition must account for phenomenality, that is, … for the fact that for a whole set of cognitive systems, and for the human one in particular, things have appearances. We will argue that on the basis of its past achievements in describing such phenomenality, Husserlian phenomenology can play a key role in helping to meet this requirement, provided that it can be naturalized, and even though Husserl himself strongly opposed naturalism. By ‘naturalized’ we mean integrated into an explanatory framework where every acceptable property is made continuous with the properties admitted by the natural sciences” (Roy, Petitot, Pachoud, and Varela 1999, pp. 1-2; second italics added).

  6. 6.

    To my knowledge, neither cognitive scientists nor phenomenologists have written of “embodied” emotion, an odd omission in their conjoint program of ‘embodiment’ since emotions are commonly labelled ‘mental states’. Social psychologists and anthropologists have, on the contrary, embodied emotion. See, for example, Lyon and Barbalet 1994; Niedenthal et al. 2005, the latter only in terms of showing how “embodiment is critically involved in information processing about emotion” (p. 192).

  7. 7.

     The qualities of movement do not change according to where one lives or in which culture one is brought up. What does change are the appurtenances that are or are not part of one’s everyday life: toothpaste, water from a faucet, a car, and so on.

  8. 8.

    It should perhaps be noted in this context that Mark Johnson’s anchorage of ‘the body in the mind’ (Johnson 1987) shows how meaning is generated in and through bodily experience. His analyses are thus in a sense compatible with the basic dynamic principles outlined in this chapter. The compatibility is limited because foundational aspects of animation - kinesthesia, the tactile-kinesthetic body, the developing coordination dynamics of infancy, and the coherency of Leib and Körper - do not enter into the picture. Johnson’s primary concern is language and in fact basic elements in his analyses - ”image schemata” and “imagination” - are “embodied.” In his most recent book with George Lakoff (Lakoff and Johnson 1999), “embodiment” figures even more strongly.

  9. 9.

    Sensations, however, may in some instances coalesce. A throbbing sensation, for example, may develop into a kinetic form. See Sheets-Johnstone 2006.

  10. 10.

    We might note that agency is empirically linked not to an ontological entity called a self but to an epistemological subject in the form of animation and kinesthesia.

  11. 11.

    Indeed, to speak of proprioception in terms of “proprioceptive feedback” is, to begin with, to speak in terms of a motorology, not of a living and lived-through dynamics as it unfolds and of that living and lived-through dynamics as a kinetic melody at the level of neurophysiological innervations and denervations (with respect to the latter, see Luria 1966, 1973).

References

  • Baron-Cohen S (1995) Mindblindness: an essay on autism and theory of mind. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruner J (1990) Acts of meaning. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin C. 1981 [1871]. The descent of man and selection in relation to sex. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher H, Di Paolo E (2007) Participatory sense-making: an enactive approach to social cognition. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 6(4) (forthcoming)

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorsett DA (1976) The structure and function of proprioceptors in soft-bodied invertebrates. In: Mill PJ (ed) Structure and function of proprioceptors in the invertebrates. Chapman & Hall, London, pp 443-483

    Google Scholar 

  • Furuhjelm M, Ingelman-Sundbert A, Wirsén C (1976) A child is born, revth edn. Delacourte Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S, Meltzoff AN (1996) The earliest sense of self and others: Merleau-Ponty and recent developmental studies. Philos Psychol 9(2):211-233

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S, Varela FJ (2003) Redrawing the map and resetting the time: phenomenology and the cognitive sciences. In: Thompson E (ed) The problem of consciousness: new essays in phenomenological philosophy of mind. Calgary University Press, Calgary, Canada, pp 93-132

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese V (2001) The ‘shared manifold’ hypothesis: from mirror neurons to empathy. J Conscious Stud 8(5-7):33-50

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese V (2007) Intentional attunement. the mirror neuron system and its role in interpersonal relations. Interdisciplines. “What do mirror neurons mean?” http://www.interdisciplines.org/mirror/papers/1, Last accessed May 19, 2007

  • Gibbs R (2006) Embodiment and cognitive science. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanna R, Thompson E (2003a) Neurophenomenology and the spontaneity of consciousness. In: Thompson E (ed) The problem of consciousness: new essays in the phenomenological philosophy of mind. University of Calgary Press, Calgary, Canada, pp 133-161

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanna R, Thompson E (2003b) The mind-body-body problem. Theoria et Historia Scientiarum VII(1):23-42

    Google Scholar 

  • Howells W (1959) Mankind in the making. Doubleday & Co., New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley SL (1998) Consciousness in action. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson M (1987) The body in the mind. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl E (1989) Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy: Book 2 (Ideas II) (trans: Rojcewicz R, Schuwer A). Kluwer, Boston, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelso, J. A. Scott (1995) Dynamic patterns: the self-organization of brain and behavior. Bradford Book/MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacan J (1977) The mirror stage as formative of the function of the I as revealed in psychoanalytic experience. In: Sheridan A (trans) Écrits: a selection. W. W. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff G, Johnson M (1999) Philosophy in the flesh. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Laverack MS (1976) External proprioceptors. In: Mill PJ (ed) Structure and function of proprioceptors in the invertebrates. Chapman & Hall, London, pp 1-63

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawrence DH (1932) Apocalypse. Viking Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Luria AR (1966) Human brain and psychological processes (trans: Haigh B). Harper & Row, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Luria AR (1973) The working brain (trans: Haigh B). Penguin Books: Harmondsworth, Middlesex, England

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyon ML, Barbalet JM (1994) Society’s body: emotion and the ‘Somatization’ of social theory. In: Csordas TJ (ed) Embodiment and experience: the existential ground of culture and self. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 48-66

    Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff AN (1990) Foundations for developing a concept of self: the role of imitation in relating self to other and the value of social mirroring, social modeling, and self practice in infancy. In: Cicchetti D, M Beeghly (eds) The self in transition: infancy to childhood. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL, pp 139-164

    Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff AN, M Keith Moore (1977) Imitation of facial and manual gestures by human neonates. Science 198:75-78

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff AN, Keith Moore M (1994) Imitation, memory, and the representation of persons. Infant Behav Dev 17:83-99

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty M (1963). In praise of philosophy and other essays (trans: Wild J, James E). Northwestern University Press, Evanston, IL

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty M (1968) The visible and the invisible (ed: Lefort C, trans: Lingis A). Northwestern University Press, Evanston, IL

    Google Scholar 

  • Niedenthal PM, Barsalou LW, Winkielman P, Krauth-Gruber S, Ric F. (2005). Embodiment in attitudes, social perception, and emotion. Pers Soc Psychol Rev 9(3):184-211

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nöe A (2004) Action in perception. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget J (1962) Play, dreams and imitation in childhood. W.W. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Petitot, Jean, Francisco J. Varela, Bernard Pachoud, Jean-Michel Roy (1999) Naturalizing pheno­menology. Stanford, CA, Stanford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. Statesman. In: The dialogues of Plato, vol. 2 (trans: Lowett B). Random House, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Roy J-M, Petitot J, Pachoud B, Varela FJ (1999) Beyond the gap: an introduction to naturalizing phenomenology. In: Petitot J, Varela FJ, Pachoud B, Roy J-M (eds)Naturalizing phenomenology: issues in contemporary phenomenology and cognitive science. Stanford University Press, Stanford, CA, pp 1-80

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone M 1966 [1979, 1980]. The phenomenology of dance. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, WI. Second editions: Dance Books, Ltd., London; Arno Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone M (1986) Existential fit and evolutionary continuities. Synthese 66:219-248

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone M (1999) The primacy of movement. John Benjamins, Amsterdam/Philadelphia

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone M (2003) Kinesthetic memory. Theoria et Historia Scientiarum VII(1):69-92

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone M (2006) Essential clarifications of ‘self-affection’ and Husserl’s ‘sphere of ownness’: first steps toward a pure phenomenology of (human) nature. Cont Philos Rev 39:361-391

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone M (2007) Schizophrenia and the ‘Comet’s tail of nature’: a case study in phenomenology and human psycho-pathology. Philoctetes J (in conjunction with NY Psychoanalytic Institute) 1(2):5-45. This article is a target article with commentaries by Jaak Panksepp and Luc Ciompi, and Louis Sass, and a response by the author

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone M (2008) The roots of morality. Pennsylvania State University Press, University Park, PA

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone M (2009) Animation: an essential, fundamental, and properly descriptive concept. Continental Philos Rev (forthcoming)

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone M (2009) The corporeal turn: an interdisciplinary reader (Chapter 3). Imprint Academic, Exeter, UK

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokolowski R (1972) Discussion. In: Tymieniecka A-T (ed) Analecta Husserliana, vol. 2: The later Husserl and the idea of phenomenology. D. Reidel Publishing, Dordrecht, pp 64-77

    Google Scholar 

  • Spitz R (1983) Dialogues from infancy In: Emde RN (ed). International Universities Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Stawarska B (2003) Facial embodiment in ‘invisible’ imitation. Theoria et Historia Scientiarum VII(1):139-161

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson E (2007) Mind in life: biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Toombs SK (2001) The role of empathy in clinical practice. J Conscious Stud 8(5-7):247-258

    Google Scholar 

  • Umtilà C (2007) Consciousness and control of action. In: Zelazo PD, Moscovitch M, Thompson E (eds) The Cambridge handbook of consciousness. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 327-351

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela FJ (1996) Neurophenomenology: a methodological remedy for the hard problem. J Conscious Stud 3(4):330-350

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela FJ (1999) The specious present: a neurophenomenology of time consciousness. In: Petitot J, Varela FJ, Pachoud B, Roy J-M (eds) Naturalizing phenomenology: issues in contemporary phenomenology and cognitive science. Stanford University Press, Stanford, CA, pp 266-314

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright BR (1976) Limb and wing receptors in insects, chelicerates and myriapods. In: Mill PJ (ed) Structure and function of proprioceptors in the invertebrates. Chapman & Hall, London, pp 323-386

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill PJ (ed) (1976) Structure and function of proprioceptors in the invertebrates. Chapman & Hall, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2002) First-person thoughts and embodied self-awareness: some reflections on the relation between recent analytical philosophy and phenomenology. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 1:7-26

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2005) Subjectivity and selfhood. Bradford Book/MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Zelazo P, Gao H, Todd R (2007) The development of consciousness. In: Zelazo PD, Moscovitch M, Thompson E (eds) The Cambridge handbook of consciousness. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 405-432

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Sheets-Johnstone, M. (2010). Body and Movement: Basic Dynamic Principles. In: Schmicking, D., Gallagher, S. (eds) Handbook of Phenomenology and Cognitive Science. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-2646-0_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics