Skip to main content

The Dynamic Logic of Stating and Asking: A Study of Inquisitive Dynamic Modalities

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Logic, Rationality, and Interaction (LORI 2017)

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Computer Science ((LNTCS,volume 10455))

Included in the following conference series:

Abstract

Inquisitive dynamic epistemic logic (IDEL) extends public announcement logic incorporating ideas from inquisitive semantics. In IDEL, the standard public announcement action can be extended to a more general public utterance action, which may involve a statement or a question. While uttering a statement has the effect of a standard announcement, uttering a question typically leads to new issues being raised. In this paper, we investigate the logic of this general public utterance action. We find striking commonalities, and some differences, with public announcement logic. We show that dynamic modalities admit a set of reduction axioms, which allow us to turn any formula of IDEL into an equivalent formula of static inquisitive epistemic logic. This leads us to establish several complete axiomatizations of IDEL, corresponding to known axiomatizations of public announcement logic.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Most previous presentations of IEL ([3, 8]) use a dichotomous language, in which formulas are divided into two syntactic categories: declaratives and interrogatives. The application of connectives is then subject to syntactic restrictions. Here we follow [4] in using a more general, non-dichotomous language; connectives apply without any restrictions, which leads to a more elegant logic. This difference is not an essential one; the results obtained here can be adapted to the dichotomous setting.

  2. 2.

    We use the neutral term utterance rather than announcement (used in [8]) because the latter suggests an informational interpretation. E.g., in IDEL, the utterance of a question such as ?p has the effect of raising the issue whether p. This should not be confused with the action of announcing whether p, i.e., announcing the true answer to the question ?p, which is a more standard action of providing information.

References

  1. Baltag, A., Moss, L., Solecki, S.: The logic of public announcements, common knowledge, and private suspicions. In: Proceedings of TARK 7, pp. 43–56. Morgan Kaufmann Publishers (1998)

    Google Scholar 

  2. van Benthem, J.: Logical dynamics of information and interaction. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2011)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  3. Ciardelli, I.: Modalities in the realm of questions: axiomatizing inquisitive epistemic logic. In: Goré, R., Kooi, B., Kurucz, A. (eds.) Advances in Modal Logic, pp. 94–113. College Publications, London (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Ciardelli, I.: Questions in logic. PhD thesis, University of Amsterdam (2016)

    Google Scholar 

  5. Ciardelli, I., Groenendijk, J., Roelofsen, F.: On the semantics and logic of declaratives and interrogatives. Synthese 192(6), 1689–1728 (2015)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  6. Ciardelli, I., Groenendijk, J., Roelofsen, F.: Inquisitive Semantics. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2017, To appear)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ciardelli, I., Roelofsen, F.: Inquisitive logic. J. Philos. Log. 40(1), 55–94 (2011)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  8. Ciardelli, I., Roelofsen, F.: Inquisitive dynamic epistemic logic. Synthese 192(6), 1643–1687 (2015)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  9. van Ditmarsch, H.: Knowledge Games. PhD thesis, Groningen University (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  10. van Ditmarsch, H., van der Hoek, W., Kooi, B.: Dynamic Epistemic Logic. Springer, Netherlands (2007)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  11. Gerbrandy, J., Groeneveld, W.: Reasoning about information change. J. log. Lang. Inf. 6(2), 147–169 (1997)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  12. Plaza, J.: Logics of public communications. In: Emrich, M.L., Pfeifer, M.S., Hadzikadic, M., Ras, Z.W. (eds) Proceedings of the Fourth International Symposium on Methodologies for Intelligent Systems, pp. 201–216. Oak Ridge National Laboratory (1989)

    Google Scholar 

  13. van Gessel, T.: Action models in inquisitive logic. MSc thesis, University of Amsterdam (2016)

    Google Scholar 

  14. Wang, Y., Cao, Q.: On axiomatizations of public announcement logic. Synthese 190(1), 103–134 (2013)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgment

Funding from the European Research Council (ERC, grant agreement number 680220) is gratefully acknowledged.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ivano Ciardelli .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendices

Appendix 1. Proof of the reduction law for E

To prove Proposition 7, we first need some lemmata. As a first step, we provide a characterization of the updated inquisitive state \(\varSigma _a^\varphi (w)\) in terms of resolutions.

Lemma 2

Let \(\varphi \in \mathcal {L}^\textsf {IDEL}\) and let \(\mathcal {R}(\varphi )=\{\alpha _1,\dots ,\alpha _n\}\). Given any M and w:

Proof

Theorem 1 ensures that . Given the support clause for this implies \([\varphi ]_M=[\alpha _1]_M\cup \dots \cup [\alpha _n]_M\). Thus, we have:

$$\begin{aligned} \varSigma _a^\varphi (w)= & {} \varSigma _a(w)\cap [\varphi ]_M=\varSigma _a(w)\,\cap \,([\alpha _1]_M\cup \dots \cup [\alpha _n]_M)\\= & {} \bigcup _{1\le i\le n}\!\!(\varSigma _a(w)\cap [\alpha _i]_M)=\varSigma _a^{\alpha _1}(w)\cup \dots \cup \varSigma _a^{\alpha _n}(w) \end{aligned}$$

Since resolutions are declaratives and thus truth-conditional, we have by Fact 3 that . Thus, we have .    \(\square \)

We will also make use of the next lemma, stating that whenever the antecedent of an implication is a truth-conditional formula \(\alpha \), the clause for implication can be simplified: \(\alpha \rightarrow \psi \) is supported at s iff \(\psi \) is supported at the state \(s\cap |\alpha |_M\).

Lemma 3

If \(\alpha \in \mathcal {L}^\textsf {IDEL}\) be truth-conditional. Then for any M, s, and \(\psi \):

\(M,s\,\models \,\alpha \rightarrow \psi \iff M,s\cap |\alpha |_M\,\models \,\psi \)

Proof

If \(\alpha \) is truth-conditional, then the subsets of s that support \(\alpha \) are all and only the subsets of \(s\cap |\alpha |_M\). Using this fact, the claim follows straightforwardly by the persistence of support.    \(\square \)

Finally, we will make use of the following equivalence, which can be established simply by spelling out the support conditions for the two formulas.

Lemma 4

For any \(\varphi ,\psi ,\chi \in \mathcal {L}^\textsf {IDEL}\),

Proof of Proposition 7. Let \(\mathcal {R}(\varphi )=\{\alpha _1,\dots ,\alpha _n\}\). First, notice that, by Lemma 2, the information states \(s\in \varSigma _a^\varphi (w)\) are all and only those of the form \(s=t\cap |\alpha _i|_M\) for some \(t\in \varSigma _a(w)\) and some \(\alpha _i\in \mathcal {R}(\varphi )\). Since \(\alpha _i\in \mathcal {R}(\varphi )\), it follows from Theorem 1 that \(|\alpha _i|_M\subseteq |\varphi |_M\), whence \(t\cap |\alpha _i|_M=t\cap |\alpha _i|_M\cap |\varphi |_M\).

Now suppose that \(M,w\,\models \,\varphi \), so that w survives in the updated model \(M^\varphi \). Making use of these facts, of Theorem 1, Lemmas 3 and 4, we have:

Finally, using this equivalence we get, for any model M and world w:

$$\begin{aligned} M,w\,\models \,[\varphi ]E_a\psi\iff & {} M,w\,\models \,\varphi \text { implies }M^\varphi ,w\,\models \,E_a\psi \\\iff & {} M,w\,\models \,\varphi \text { implies }M,w\,\models \,E_a(\varphi \rightarrow [\varphi ]\psi )\\\iff & {} M,w\,\models \,\varphi \rightarrow E_a(\varphi \rightarrow [\varphi ]\psi ) \end{aligned}$$

We have thus proved that \([\varphi ]E_a\psi \) and \(\varphi \rightarrow E_a(\varphi \rightarrow [\varphi ]\psi )\) have the same truth-conditions. Since both formulas are declaratives, and thus truth-conditional by Proposition 1, this ensures that these formulas are equivalent.   \(\square \)

Appendix 2. Proof of completeness via !Comp and !Mon

Proof of Theorem 4. The proof is analogous to the one in Sect. 7.4 of [10] for PAL. We only provide a proof sketch. We first define a complexity measure as follows:

  • \(c(p)=c(\bot )=1\)

  • \(c(K_a\varphi )=c(E_a\varphi )=1+c(\varphi )\)

  • \(c([\varphi ]\psi )=(4+c(\varphi ))\cdot c(\psi )\)

By recursion on this notion of complexity, we define a map \((\cdot )^*:\mathcal {L}^\textsf {IDEL}\rightarrow \mathcal {L}^\textsf {IEL}\):

figure a

We can then easily prove \(\varphi \dashv \vdash _{\textsf {IDEL}^{\textsf {!Comp}}}\varphi ^*\), using the reduction rules and !Comp. Completeness then follows since \(\vdash _{\textsf {IDEL}^{\textsf {!Comp}}}\) includes a complete system for IEL.   \(\square \)

Proof of Theorem 5. The proof is similar to the previous one, and to the proof of the analogous result for PAL in [14]. We modify the above definition of \((\cdot )^*\) by setting \(([\varphi ][\psi ]\chi )^*=([\varphi ]([\psi ]\chi )^*)^*\). By induction on the complexity of a formula (as defined above), we show that (i) \(\varphi ^*\) is well-defined; (ii) if \(\varphi \not \in \mathcal {L}^\textsf {IEL}\), then \(c(\varphi ^*)<c(\varphi )\); and (iii) \(\varphi \dashv \vdash _{\textsf {IDEL}^{\textsf {!Mon}}}\varphi ^*\). The only case which is not straightforward is the inductive step for a formula \([\varphi ][\psi ]\chi \), which I will spell out in detail.

For (i), notice that since \([\psi ]\chi \) is less complex than \([\varphi ][\psi ]\chi \), by induction hypothesis we have that \(([\psi ]\chi )^*\) is well-defined and less complex than \([\psi ]\chi \). It follows that \([\varphi ]([\psi ]\chi )^*\) is less complex than \([\varphi ][\psi ]\chi \). So, the induction hypothesis implies that \(([\varphi ]([\psi ]\chi )^*)^*\) is well-defined, i.e., that \(([\varphi ][\psi ]\chi )^*\) is well-defined.

For (ii), as both \([\psi ]\chi \) and \([\varphi ]([\psi ]\chi )^*\) are less complex than \([\varphi ][\psi ]\chi \), using the induction hypothesis we have \(c(([\varphi ][\psi ]\chi )^*)=c(([\varphi ]([\psi ]\chi )^*)^*)<c([\varphi ]([\psi ]\chi )^*)<c([\varphi ][\psi ]\chi )\). So, \(c(([\varphi ][\psi ]\chi )^*)<c([\varphi ][\psi ]\chi )\).

For (iii), as \([\psi ]\chi \) is less complex than \([\varphi ][\psi ]\chi \), the induction hypothesis gives \([\psi ]\chi \dashv \vdash _{\textsf {IDEL}^{\textsf {!Mon}}}([\psi ]\chi )^*\). By two applications of the rule !Mon we get \([\varphi ][\psi ]\chi \dashv \vdash _{\textsf {IDEL}^{\textsf {!Mon}}}[\varphi ]([\psi ]\chi )^*\). Now, since \([\varphi ]([\psi ]\chi )^*\) is less complex than \([\varphi ][\psi ]\chi \), the induction hypothesis applies, and gives \([\varphi ]([\psi ]\chi )^*\dashv \vdash _{\textsf {IDEL}^{\textsf {!Mon}}}([\varphi ]([\psi ]\chi )^*)^*\). Putting things together, we have obtained \([\varphi ][\psi ]\chi \dashv \vdash _{\textsf {IDEL}^{\textsf {!Mon}}}([\varphi ]([\psi ]\chi )^*)^*\) which is what we need, since by definition \(([\varphi ]([\psi ]\chi )^*)^*=([\varphi ][\psi ]\chi )^*\).   \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer-Verlag GmbH Germany

About this paper

Cite this paper

Ciardelli, I. (2017). The Dynamic Logic of Stating and Asking: A Study of Inquisitive Dynamic Modalities. In: Baltag, A., Seligman, J., Yamada, T. (eds) Logic, Rationality, and Interaction. LORI 2017. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 10455. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-55665-8_17

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-55665-8_17

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-662-55664-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-662-55665-8

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics