Skip to main content

Decision Making Under Interval Uncertainty (and Beyond)

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Human-Centric Decision-Making Models for Social Sciences

Part of the book series: Studies in Computational Intelligence ((SCI,volume 502))

Abstract

To make a decision, we must find out the user’s preference, and help the user select an alternative which is the best—according to these preferences. Traditional utility-based decision theory is based on a simplifying assumption that for each two alternatives, a user can always meaningfully decide which of them is preferable. In reality, often, when the alternatives are close, the user is often unable to select one of these alternatives. In this chapter, we show how we can extend the utility-based decision theory to such realistic (interval) cases.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

References

  1. Aliev, R., Huseynov, O., Kreinovich, V.: Decision making under interval and fuzzy uncertainty: towards an operational approach. In: Proceedings of the Tenth International Conference on Application of Fuzzy Systems and Soft Computing ICAFS’2012, Lisbon, Portugal, 29–30 August 2012

    Google Scholar 

  2. Aubinet, M., Vesala, T., Papale, D. (eds.): Eddy Covariance - A Practical Guide to Measurement and Data Analysis. Springer, Dordrecht (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Binder, A.B., Roberts, D. L.: Criteria for Lunar Site Selection, Report No. P-30, NASA Appollo Lunar Exploration Office and Illinois Institute of Technology Research Institute, Chicago, Illinois, January 1970

    Google Scholar 

  4. Cobb, C.W., Douglas, P.H.: A theory of production. Am. Econ. Rev. 18(Supplement), 139–165 (1928)

    Google Scholar 

  5. de Finetti, B.: Theory of Probability, Wiley, New York, Vol. 1, 1974; Vol. 2, 1975

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ehrgott, M., Gandibleux, X. (eds.): Multiple Criteria Optimization: State of the Art Annotated Bibliographic Surveys. Springer, New York (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ferson, S., Kreinovich, V., Hajagos, J., Oberkampf, W., Ginzburg, L.: Experimental Uncertainty Estimation and Statistics for Data Having Interval Uncertainty, Sandia National Laboratories (2007), Publ. 2007–0939

    Google Scholar 

  8. Fishburn, P.C.: Utility Theory for Decision Making. Wiley, New York (1969)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Fishburn, P.C.: Nonlinear Preference and Utility Theory. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore (1988)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  10. Fountoulis, I., Mariokalos, D., Spyridonos, E., Andreakis, E.: Geological criteria and methodology for landfill sites selection. In: Proceedings of the 8th International Conference on Environmental Science and Technology, Greece, 8–10 September 2003, pp. 200–207

    Google Scholar 

  11. Gardeñes, E., et al.: Modal intervals. Reliable Comput. 7, 77–111 (2001)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  12. Giang, P.H.: Decision with dempster-shafer belief functions: decision under ignorance and sequential consistency. Int. J. Approximate Reasoning 53, 38–53 (2012)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  13. Guo, P., Tanaka, H.: Decision making with interval probabilities. Eur. J. Oper. Res. 203, 444–454 (2010)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  14. Guo, P., Wang, Y.: Eliciting dual interval probabilities from interval comparison matrices. Inf. Sci. 190, 17–26 (2012)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  15. Helversen B.V., Mata R.: Losing a dime with a satisfied mind: positive affect predicts less search in sequential decision making, Psychology and Aging, 27, 825–839 (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Hurwicz, L.: Optimality Criteria for Decision Making Under Ignorance, Cowles Commission Discussion Paper, Statistics, No. 370, 1951

    Google Scholar 

  17. Jaimes A., Salayandia L., Gallegos I.: New cyber infrastructure for studying land-atmosphere interactions using eddy covariance techniques. In: Abstracts of the 2010 Fall Meeting American Geophysical Union AGU’2010, San Francisco, California, 12–18 December 2010

    Google Scholar 

  18. Jaimes, A., Herrera, J., GonzÍez, L., Ramìrez, G., Laney, C., Browning, D., Peters, D., Litvak, M., Tweedie, C.: Towards a multiscale approach to link climate, NEE and optical properties from a flux tower, robotic tram system that measures hyperspectral reflectance, phenocams, phenostations and a sensor network in desert a shrubland. In: Proceedings of the FLUXNET and Remote Sensing Open Workshop: Towards Upscaling Flux Information from Towers to the Globe FLUXNET-SpecNet’2011, Berkeley, California, 7–9 June 2011

    Google Scholar 

  19. Jaimes, A.: A cyber-Tool to Optimize Site Selection for Establishing an Eddy Covraince and Robotic Tram System at the Jornada Experimental Range. University of Texas, El Paso (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Jaimes, A., Tweedie, C., Kreinovich, V., Ceberio, M.: Scale-invariant approach to multi-criterion optimization under uncertainty, with applications to optimal sensor placement, in particular, to sensor placement in environmental research. Int. J. Reliab. Saf. 6(1–3), 188–203 (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  21. Kiekintveld, C., Kreinovich, V.: Efficient approximation for security games with interval uncertainty, In: Proceedings of the AAAI Spring Symposium on Game Theory for Security, Sustainability, and Health GTSSH’2012, Stanford, 26–28 March 2012

    Google Scholar 

  22. Kintisch, E.: Loss of carbon observatory highlights gaps in data. Science 323, 1276–1277 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Kreinovich, V.: Decision making under interval uncertainty, In: Abstracts of the 15th GAMM - IMACS International Symposium on Scientific Computing, Computer Arithmetic, and Verified Numerical Computation SCAN’2012. Novosibirsk, Russia, September 2012

    Google Scholar 

  24. Kreinovich, V., Starks, S.A., Iourinski, D., Kosheleva, O., Finkelstein, A.: Open-ended configurations of radio telescopes: a geometrical analysis. Geombinatorics 13(2), 79–85 (2003)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  25. Kyburg, H.E., Smokler, H.E. (eds.): Studies in Subjective Probability. Wiley, New York (1964)

    Google Scholar 

  26. Luce R.D., Krantz D.H., Suppes P., Tversky A.: Foundations of measurement, vol. 3, Representation, Axiomatization, and Invariance, Academic Press, California (1990)

    Google Scholar 

  27. Luce, R.D., Raiffa, R.: Games and Decisions: Introduction and Critical Survey. Dover, New York (1989)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  28. Moore, R.E., Kearfott, R.B., Cloud, M.J.: Introduction to Interval Analysis. SIAM, Pennsylvania (2009)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  29. Myerson, R.B.: Game theory. Analysis of conflict, Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1991)

    Google Scholar 

  30. Nash, J.F.: The bargaining problem. Econometrica 28, 155–162 (1950)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  31. Nash, J.: Two-person cooperative games. Econometrica 21, 128–140 (1953)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  32. Nguyen, H.T., Kreinovich, V., Wu, B., Xiang G.: Computing Statistics under Interval and Fuzzy Uncertainty, Springer, Berlin (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  33. Nguyen, H.T., Kreinovich, V.: Applications of Continuous Mathematics to Computer Science. Kluwer, Dordrecht (1997)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  34. Pfanzangl, J.: Theory of Measurement. Wiley, New York (1968)

    Google Scholar 

  35. Raiffa, H.: Decision Analysis. McGraw-Hill, Columbus (1997)

    Google Scholar 

  36. Roth, A.: Axiomatic Models of Bargaining. Springer, Berlin (1979)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  37. Savage, L.J.: The Foundations of Statistics. Wiley, New York (1954)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  38. Sawaragi, Y., Nakayama, H., Tanino, T.: Theory of Multiobjective Optimization. Academic Press, Orlando (1985)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  39. Shary, S.P.: A new technique in systems analysis under interval uncertainty and ambiguity. Reliable Comput. 8, 321–418 (2002)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  40. Steuer, R.E.: Multiple Criteria Optimization: Theory, Computations, and Application. Wiley, New York (1986)

    Google Scholar 

  41. Stevens, S.S.: On the theory of scales of measurement. Science 103, 677–680 (1946)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  42. Troffaes, M.C.M.: Decision making under uncertainty using imprecise probabilities. Int. J. Approximate Reasoning 45, 7–29 (2007)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  43. Walsh, C.: Monetary Theory and Policy. MIT Press, Cambridge (2003)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This work was supported in part by the National Science Foundation grants HRD-0734825 and HRD-1242122 (Cyber-ShARE Center of Excellence) and DUE-0926721, by Grant 1 T36 GM078000-01 from the National Institutes of Health, and by a grant on F-transforms from the Office of Naval Research. The authors is greatly thankful to the anonymous referees for valuable suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Vladik Kreinovich .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

A Proof of the Theorem

A Proof of the Theorem

\(1^\circ \). Due to scale-invariance (9), for every \(y_1\), ..., \(y_n\), \(y'_1\), ..., \(y'_n\), we can take \(\lambda _i=\displaystyle \frac{1}{y_i}\) and conclude that

$$\begin{aligned} (y'_1,\ldots ,y'_n)\sim (y_1,\ldots ,y_n)\Leftrightarrow \left( \frac{y'_1}{y_1},\ldots ,\frac{y'_n}{y_n}\right) \sim (1,\ldots ,1). \end{aligned}$$
(12)

Thus, to describe the equivalence relation \(\sim \), it is sufficient to describe the set of all the vectors \(z=(z_1,\ldots ,z_n)\) for which \(z\sim (1,\ldots ,1)\). Similarly,

$$\begin{aligned} (y'_1,\ldots ,y'_n)\succ (y_1,\ldots ,y_n)\Leftrightarrow \left( \frac{y'_1}{y_1},\ldots ,\frac{y'_n}{y_n}\right) \succ (1,\ldots ,1). \end{aligned}$$
(13)

So, to describe the ordering relation \(\succ \), it is sufficient to describe the set of all the vectors \(z=(z_1,\ldots ,z_n)\) for which \(z\succ (1,\ldots ,1)\).

Alternatively, we can take \(\lambda _i=\displaystyle \frac{1}{y'_i}\) and conclude that

$$\begin{aligned} (y'_1,\ldots ,y'_n)\succ (y_1,\ldots ,y_n)\Leftrightarrow (1,\ldots ,1)\succ \left( \frac{y_1}{y'_1},\ldots ,\frac{y_n}{y'_n}\right) . \end{aligned}$$
(14)

Thus, it is also sufficient to describe the set of all the vectors \(z=(z_1,\ldots ,z_n)\) for which \((1,\ldots ,1)\succ z\).

\(2^\circ \). The above equivalence involves division. To simplify the description, we can take into account that in the logarithmic space, division becomes a simple difference: \(\ln \left( \displaystyle \frac{y'_i}{y_i}\right) =\ln (y'_i)-\ln (y_i)\). To use this simplification, let us consider the logarithms \(Y_i\mathop {=}\limits ^{\mathrm{{def}}}\ln (y_i)\) of different values. In terms of these logarithms, the original values can be reconstructed as \(y_i=\exp (Y_i)\). In terms of these logarithms, we thus need to consider:

  • the set \(S_\sim \) of all the tuples \(Z=(Z_1,\ldots ,Z_n)\) for which

    $$\begin{aligned} z=(\exp (Z_1),\ldots ,\exp (Z_n))\sim (1,\ldots ,1), \end{aligned}$$
    (15)

    and

  • the set \(S_\succ \) of all the tuples \(Z=(Z_1,\ldots ,Z_n)\) for which

    $$\begin{aligned} z=(\exp (Z_1),\ldots ,\exp (Z_n))\succ (1,\ldots ,1). \end{aligned}$$
    (16)

We will also consider the set \(S_\prec \) of all the tuples \(Z=(Z_1,\ldots ,Z_n)\) for which

$$\begin{aligned} (1,\ldots ,1)\succ z=(\exp (Z_1),\ldots ,\exp (Z_n)). \end{aligned}$$
(17)

Since the pre-ordering relation is total, for every tuple \(z\),

  • either \(z\sim (1,\ldots ,1)\),

  • or \(z\succ (1,\ldots ,1)\),

  • or \((1,\ldots ,1)\succ z\).

In particular, this is true for \(z=(\exp (Z_1),\ldots ,\exp (Z_n))\). Thus, for every tuple \(Z\), either \(Z\in S_\sim \) or \(Z\in S_\succ \) or \(Z\in S_\prec \).

\(3^\circ \). Let us prove that the set \(S_\sim \) is closed under addition, i.e., that if the tuples \(Z=(Z_1,\ldots ,Z_n)\) and \(Z'=(Z'_1,\ldots ,Z'_n)\) belong to the set \(S_\sim \), then their component-wise sum

$$\begin{aligned} Z+Z'=(Z_1+Z'_1,\ldots ,Z_n+Z'_n) \end{aligned}$$
(18)

also belongs to the set \(S_\sim \).

Indeed, by definition (15) of the set \(S_\sim \), the condition \(Z\in S_\sim \) means that

$$\begin{aligned} (\exp (Z_1),\ldots ,\exp (Z_n))\sim (1,\ldots ,1). \end{aligned}$$
(19)

Using scale-invariance (9) with \(\lambda _i=\exp (Z'_i)\), we conclude that

$$\begin{aligned} (\exp (Z_1)\cdot \exp (Z'_1),\ldots ,\exp (Z_n)\cdot \exp (Z'_n))\sim (\exp (Z'_1),\ldots ,\exp (Z'_n)). \end{aligned}$$
(20)

On the other hand, the condition \(Z'\in S_\sim \) means that

$$\begin{aligned} (\exp (Z'_1),\ldots ,\exp (Z'_n))\sim (1,\ldots ,1). \end{aligned}$$
(21)

Thus, due to transitivity of the equivalence relation \(\sim \), we conclude that

$$\begin{aligned} (\exp (Z_1)\cdot \exp (Z'_1),\ldots ,\exp (Z_n)\cdot \exp (Z'_n))\sim (1,\ldots ,1). \end{aligned}$$
(22)

Since for every \(i\), we have \(\exp (Z_i)\cdot \exp (Z'_i)=\exp (Z_i+Z'_i)\), we thus conclude that

$$\begin{aligned} (\exp (Z_1+Z'_1),\ldots ,\exp (Z_n+Z'_n))\sim (1,\ldots ,1). \end{aligned}$$
(23)

By definition (15) of the set \(S_\sim \), this means that the tuple \(Z+Z'\) belongs to the set \(S_\sim \).

\(4^\circ \). Similarly, we can prove that the set \(S_\succ \) is closed under addition, i.e., that if the tuples \(Z=(Z_1,\ldots ,Z_n)\) and \(Z'=(Z'_1,\ldots ,Z'_n)\) belong to the set \(S_\succ \), then their component-wise sum

$$\begin{aligned} Z+Z'=(Z_1+Z'_1,\ldots ,Z_n+Z'_n) \end{aligned}$$
(24)

also belongs to the set \(S_\succ \).

Indeed, by definition (16) of the set \(S_\succ \), the condition \(Z\in S_\succ \) means that

$$\begin{aligned} (\exp (Z_1),\ldots ,\exp (Z_n))\succ (1,\ldots ,1). \end{aligned}$$
(25)

Using scale-invariance (8) with \(\lambda _i=\exp (Z'_i)\), we conclude that

$$\begin{aligned} (\exp (Z_1)\cdot \exp (Z'_1),\ldots ,\exp (Z_n)\cdot \exp (Z'_n))\succ (\exp (Z'_1),\ldots ,\exp (Z'_n)). \end{aligned}$$
(26)

On the other hand, the condition \(Z'\in S_\succ \) means that

$$\begin{aligned} (\exp (Z'_1),\ldots ,\exp (Z'_n))\succ (1,\ldots ,1). \end{aligned}$$
(27)

Thus, due to transitivity of the strict preference relation \(\succ \), we conclude that

$$\begin{aligned} (\exp (Z_1)\cdot \exp (Z'_1),\ldots ,\exp (Z_n)\cdot \exp (Z'_n))\succ (1,\ldots ,1). \end{aligned}$$
(28)

Since for every \(i\), we have \(\exp (Z_i)\cdot \exp (Z'_i)=\exp (Z_i+Z'_i)\), we thus conclude that

$$\begin{aligned} (\exp (Z_1+Z'_1),\ldots ,\exp (Z_n+Z'_n))\succ (1,\ldots ,1). \end{aligned}$$
(29)

By definition (16) of the set \(S_\succ \), this means that the tuple \(Z+Z'\) belongs to the set \(S_\succ \).

\(5^\circ \). A similar argument shows that the set \(S_\prec \) is closed under addition, i.e., that if the tuples \(Z=(Z_1,\ldots ,Z_n)\) and \(Z'=(Z'_1,\ldots ,Z'_n)\) belong to the set \(S_\prec \), then their component-wise sum

$$\begin{aligned} Z+Z'=(Z_1+Z'_1,\ldots ,Z_n+Z'_n) \end{aligned}$$
(30)

also belongs to the set \(S_\prec \).

\(6^\circ \). Let us now prove that the set \(S_\sim \) is closed under the “unary minus” operation, i.e., that if \(Z=(Z_1,\ldots ,Z_n)\in S_\sim \), then \(-Z\mathop {=}\limits ^{\mathrm{{def}}}(-Z_1,\ldots ,-Z_n)\) also belongs to \(S_\sim \).

Indeed, \(Z\in S_\sim \) means that

$$\begin{aligned} (\exp (Z_1),\ldots ,\exp (Z_n))\sim (1,\ldots ,1). \end{aligned}$$
(31)

Using scale-invariance (9) with \(\lambda _i=\exp (-Z_i)=\displaystyle \frac{1}{\exp (Z_i)}\), we conclude that

$$\begin{aligned} (1,\ldots ,1)\sim (\exp (-Z_1),\ldots ,\exp (-Z_n)), \end{aligned}$$
(32)

i.e., that \(-Z\in S_\sim \).

\(7^\circ \). Let us prove that if \(Z=(Z_1,\ldots ,Z_n)\in S_\succ \), then \(-Z\mathop {=}\limits ^{\mathrm{{def}}}(-Z_1,\ldots ,-Z_n)\) belongs to \(S_\prec \).

Indeed, \(Z\in S_\succ \) means that

$$\begin{aligned} (\exp (Z_1),\ldots ,\exp (Z_n))\succ (1,\ldots ,1). \end{aligned}$$
(33)

Using scale-invariance (8) with \(\lambda _i=\exp (-Z_i)=\displaystyle \frac{1}{\exp (Z_i)}\), we conclude that

$$\begin{aligned} (1,\ldots ,1)\succ (\exp (-Z_1),\ldots ,\exp (-Z_n)), \end{aligned}$$
(34)

i.e., that \(-Z\in S_\prec \).

Similarly, we can show that if \(Z\in S_\prec \), then \(-Z\in S_\succ \).

\(8^\circ \). From Part 3 of this proof, it now follows that if \(Z=(Z_1,\ldots ,Z_n)\in S_\sim \), then \(Z+Z\in S_\sim \), then that \(Z+(Z+Z)\in S_\sim \), etc., i.e., that for every positive integer \(p\), the tuple

$$\begin{aligned} p\cdot Z=(p\cdot Z_1,\ldots , p\cdot Z_n) \end{aligned}$$
(35)

also belongs to the set \(S_\sim \).

By using Part 6 of this proof, we can also conclude that this is true for negative integers \(p\) as well. Finally, by taking into account that the zero tuple \(0\mathop {=}\limits ^{\mathrm{{def}}}(0,\ldots ,0)\) can be represented as \(Z+(-Z)\), we conclude that \(0\cdot Z=0\) also belongs to the set \(S_\sim \).

Thus, if a tuple \(Z\) belongs to the set \(S_\sim \), then for every integer \(p\), the tuple \(p\cdot Z\) also belongs to the set \(S_\sim \).

\(9^\circ \). Similarly, from Parts 4 and 5 of this proof, it follows that

  • if \(Z=(Z_1,\ldots ,Z_n)\in S_\succ \), then for every positive integer \(p\), the tuple \(p\cdot Z\) also belongs to the set \(S_\succ \), and

  • if \(Z=(Z_1,\ldots ,Z_n)\in S_\prec \), then for every positive integer \(p\), the tuple \(p\cdot Z\) also belongs to the set \(S_\prec \).

\(10^\circ \). Let us prove that for every rational number \(r=\displaystyle \frac{p}{q}\), where \(p\) is an integer and \(q\) is a positive integer, if a tuple \(Z\) belongs to the set \(S_\sim \), then the tuple \(r\cdot Z\) also belongs to the set \(S_\sim \).

Indeed, according to Part 8, \(Z\in S_\sim \) implies that \(p\cdot Z\in S_\sim \).

According to Part 2, for the tuple \(r\cdot Z\), we have either \(r\cdot Z\in S_\sim \), or \(r\cdot Z\in S_\succ \), or \(r\cdot Z\in S_\prec \).

  • If \(r\cdot Z\in S_\succ \), then, by Part 9, we would get \(p\cdot Z=q\cdot (r\cdot Z)\in S_\succ \), which contradicts our result that \(p\cdot Z\in S_\sim \).

  • Similarly, if \(r\cdot Z\in S_\prec \), then, by Part 9, we would get \(p\cdot Z=q\cdot (r\cdot Z)\in S_\prec \), which contradicts our result that \(p\cdot Z\in S_\sim \).

Thus, the only remaining option is \(r\cdot Z\in S_\sim \). The statement is proven.

\(11^\circ \). Let us now use continuity to prove that for every real number \(x\), if a tuple \(Z\) belongs to the set \(S_\sim \), then the tuple \(x\cdot Z\) also belongs to the set \(S_\sim \).

Indeed, a real number \(x\) can be represented as a limit of rational numbers: \(r^{(k)}\rightarrow x\). According to Part 10, for every \(k\), we have \(r^{(k)}\cdot Z\in S_\sim \), i.e., the tuple

$$\begin{aligned} Z^{(k)}\mathop {=}\limits ^{\mathrm{{def}}}(\exp (r^{(k)}\cdot Z_1),\ldots ,\exp (r^{(k)}\cdot Z_n))\sim (1,\ldots ,1). \end{aligned}$$
(36)

In particular, this means that \(Z^{(k)}\succeq (1,\ldots ,1)\). In the limit,

$$\begin{aligned} Z^{(k)}\rightarrow (\exp (x\cdot Z_1),\ldots ,\exp (x\cdot Z_n))\succeq (1,\ldots ,1). \end{aligned}$$
(37)

By definition of the sets \(S_\sim \) and \(S_\succ \), this means that \(x\cdot Z\in S_\sim \) or \(x\cdot Z\in S_\succ \).

Similarly, for \(-(x\cdot Z)=(-x)\cdot Z\), we conclude that \(-x\cdot Z\in S_\sim \) or

$$\begin{aligned} (-x)\cdot Z\in S_\succ . \end{aligned}$$
(38)

If we had \(x\cdot Z\in S_\succ \), then by Part 7 we would get \((-x)\cdot Z\in S_\prec \), a contradiction. Thus, the case \(x\cdot Z\in S_\succ \) is impossible, and we have \(x\cdot Z\in S_\sim \). The statement is proven.

\(12^\circ \). According to Parts 3 and 11, the set \(S_\sim \) is closed under addition and under multiplication by an arbitrary real number. Thus, if tuples \(Z,\ldots ,Z'\) belong to the set \(S_\sim \), their arbitrary linear combination \(x\cdot Z+\ldots +x'\cdot Z'\) also belongs to the set \(S_\sim \). So, the set \(S_\sim \) is a linear subspace of the \(n\)-dimensional space of all the tuples.

\(13^\circ \). The subspace \(S_\sim \) cannot coincide with the entire \(n\)-dimensional space, because then the pre-ordering relation would be trivial. Thus, the dimension of this subspace must be less than or equal to \(n-1\). Let us show that the dimension of this subspace is \(n-1\).

Indeed, let us assume that the dimension is smaller than \(n-1\). Since the pre-ordering is non-trivial, there exist tuples \(y=(y_1,\ldots ,y_n)\) and \(y'=(y'_1,\ldots ,y'_n)\) for which \(y\succ y'\) and thus, \(Z=(Z_1,\ldots ,Z_n)\in S_\succ \), where \(Z_i=\ln \left( \displaystyle \frac{y_i}{y'_i}\right) \). From \(Z\in S_\succ \), we conclude that \(-Z\in S_\prec \).

Since the linear space \(S_\sim \) is a less than \((n-1)\)-dimensional subspace of an \(n\)-dimensional linear space, there is a path connecting \(Z\in S_\succ \) and \(-Z\in S_\prec \) which avoids \(S_\sim \). In mathematical terms, this path is a continuous mapping \(\gamma :[0,1]\rightarrow R^n\) for which \(\gamma (0)=Z\) and \(\gamma (1)=-Z\). Since this path avoids \(S_\sim \), every point \(\gamma (t)\) on this path belongs either to \(S_\succ \) or to \(S_\prec \).

Let \(\overline{t}\) denote the supremum (least upper bound) of the set of all the values \(t\) for which \(\gamma (t)\in S_\succ \). By definition of the supremum, there exists a sequence \(t^{(k)}\rightarrow \overline{t}\) for which \(\gamma \left( t^{(k)}\right) \in S_\succ \). Similarly to Part 11, we can use continuity to prove that in the limit, \(\gamma \left( \overline{t}\right) \in S_\succ \) or \(\gamma \left( \overline{t}\right) \in S_\sim \). Since the path avoids the set \(S_\sim \), we thus get \(\gamma \left( \overline{t}\right) \in S_\succ \).

Similarly, since \(\gamma (1)\not \in S_\succ \), there exists a sequence \(t^{(k)}\downarrow \overline{t}\) for which \(\gamma \left( t^{(k)}\right) \in S_\prec \). We can therefore conclude that in the limit, \(\gamma \left( \overline{t}\right) \in S_\succ \) or \(\gamma (\overline{t})\in S_\sim \)—a contradiction with our previous conclusion that \(\gamma \left( \overline{t}\right) \in S_\succ \).

This contradiction shows that the linear space \(S_\sim \) cannot have dimension smaller than \(n-1\) and thus, that this space have dimension \(n-1\).

\(14^\circ \). Every \((n-1)\)-dimensional linear subspace of an \(n\)-dimensional superspace separates the superspace into two half-spaces. Let us show that one of these half-spaces is \(S_\succ \) and the other is \(S_\prec \).

Indeed, if one of the subspaces contains two tuples \(Z\) and \(Z'\) for which \(Z\in S_\succ \) and \(Z'\in S_\prec \), then the line segment \(\gamma (t)=t\cdot Z+(1-t)\cdot Z'\) containing these two points also belongs to the same subspace, i.e., avoids the set \(S_\sim \). Thus, similarly to Part 13, we would get a contradiction.

So, if one point from a half-space belongs to \(S_\succ \), all other points from this subspace also belong to the set \(S_\succ \). Similarly, if one point from a half-space belongs to \(S_\prec \), all other points from this subspace also belong to the set \(S_\prec \).

\(15^\circ \). Every \((n-1)\)-dimensional linear subspace of an \(n\)-dimensional space has the form

$$\begin{aligned} \alpha _1\cdot Z_1+\ldots +\alpha _n\cdot Z_n=0 \end{aligned}$$
(39)

for some real values \(\alpha _i\), and the corresponding half-spaces have the form

$$\begin{aligned} \alpha _1\cdot Z_1+\ldots +\alpha _n\cdot Z_n>0 \end{aligned}$$
(40)

and

$$\begin{aligned} \alpha _1\cdot Z_1+\ldots +\alpha _n\cdot Z_n<0. \end{aligned}$$
(41)

The set \(S_\succ \) coincides with one of these subspaces. If it coincides with the set of all tuples \(Z\) for which \(\alpha _1\cdot Z_1+\ldots +\alpha _n\cdot Z_n<0\), then we can rewrite it as

$$\begin{aligned} (-\alpha _1)\cdot Z_1+\ldots +(-\alpha _n)\cdot Z_n>0, \end{aligned}$$
(42)

i.e., as \(\alpha '_1\cdot Z_1+\ldots +\alpha '_n\cdot Z_n>0\) for \(\alpha '_i=-\alpha _i\).

Thus, without losing generality, we can conclude that the set \(S_\succ \) coincides with the set of all the tuples \(Z\) for which \(\alpha _1\cdot Z_1+\ldots +\alpha _n\cdot Z_n>0\). We have mentioned that

$$\begin{aligned} y'=(y'_1,\ldots ,y'_n)\succ y=(y_1,\ldots ,y_n) \Leftrightarrow (Z_1,\ldots ,Z_n)\in S_\succ , \end{aligned}$$
(43)

where \(Z_i=\ln \left( \displaystyle \frac{y'_i}{y_i}\right) \). So,

$$\begin{aligned} y'\succ y\Leftrightarrow \end{aligned}$$
$$\begin{aligned} \alpha _1\cdot Z_1+\ldots +\alpha _n\cdot Z_n= \alpha _1\cdot \ln \left( \frac{y'_1}{y_1}\right) +\ldots +\alpha _n\cdot \ln \left( \frac{y'_n}{y_n}\right) >0. \end{aligned}$$
(44)

Since \(\ln \left( \displaystyle \frac{y'_i}{y_i}\right) =\ln (y'_i)-\ln (y_i)\), the last inequality in the formula (44) is equivalent to

$$\begin{aligned} \alpha _1\cdot \ln (y'_1)+\ldots +\alpha _n\cdot \ln (y'_n)>\alpha _1\cdot \ln (y_1)+\ldots +\alpha _n\cdot \ln (y_n). \end{aligned}$$
(45)

Let us take \(\exp \) of both sides of the formula (45); then, due to the monotonicity of the exponential function, we get an equivalent inequality

$$\begin{aligned} \exp (\alpha _1\cdot \ln (y'_1)+\ldots +\alpha _n\cdot \ln (y'_n))>\exp (\alpha _1\cdot \ln (y_1)+\ldots +\alpha _n\cdot \ln (y_n)). \end{aligned}$$
(46)

Here,

$$\begin{aligned} \exp (\alpha _1\cdot \ln (y'_1)+\ldots +\alpha _n\cdot \ln (y'_n))= \exp (\alpha _1\cdot \ln (y'_1))\cdot \ldots \cdot \exp (\alpha _n\cdot \ln (y'_n)), \end{aligned}$$

where for every \(i\), \(e^{\alpha _i\cdot z_i}=\left( e^{z_i}\right) ^{\alpha _i}\), with \(z_i\mathop {=}\limits ^{\mathrm{{def}}}\ln (y'_i)\), implies that

$$\begin{aligned} \exp (\alpha _i\cdot \ln (y'_i))=(\exp (\ln (y'_i)))^{\alpha _i}=(y'_i)^{\alpha _i}, \end{aligned}$$
(47)

so

$$\begin{aligned} \exp (\alpha _1\cdot \ln (y'_1)+\ldots +\alpha _n\cdot \ln (y'_n))= (y'_1)^{\alpha _1}\cdot \ldots \cdot (y'_n)^{\alpha _n} \end{aligned}$$
(48)

and similarly,

$$\begin{aligned} \exp (\alpha _1\cdot \ln (y_1)+\ldots +\alpha _n\cdot \ln (y_n))= y_1^{\alpha _1}\cdot \ldots \cdot y_n^{\alpha _n}. \end{aligned}$$
(49)

Thus, due to (44), (45), (46), (48) and (49), the condition \(y'\succ y\) is equivalent to:

$$\begin{aligned} \prod _{i=1}^n y_i^{\alpha _i}>\prod _{i=1}^n (y'_i)^{\alpha _i}. \end{aligned}$$
(50)

Similarly, we prove that

$$\begin{aligned} y_1,\ldots ,y_n)\sim y'=(y'_1,\ldots ,y'_n)\Leftrightarrow \prod _{i=1}^n y_i^{\alpha _i}=\prod _{i=1}^n (y'_i)^{\alpha _i}. \end{aligned}$$
(51)

The condition \(\alpha _i>0\) follows from our assumption that the pre-ordering is monotonic.

The theorem is proven.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kreinovich, V. (2014). Decision Making Under Interval Uncertainty (and Beyond). In: Guo, P., Pedrycz, W. (eds) Human-Centric Decision-Making Models for Social Sciences. Studies in Computational Intelligence, vol 502. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-39307-5_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-39307-5_8

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-642-39306-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-642-39307-5

  • eBook Packages: EngineeringEngineering (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics