Skip to main content

Epistemic Reductionism and the Moral-Epistemic Disparity

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Metaepistemology

Part of the book series: Palgrave Innovations in Philosophy ((PIIP))

Abstract

In previous work, I defend the following disparity between moral and epistemic facts: whereas moral facts are irreducibly normative, epistemic facts—facts such as that someone is epistemically justified in believing something—are reducible to facts from some other domain (such as facts about probabilities). This moral-epistemic disparity is significant because it undercuts an important kind of argument for robust moral realism. My defense of epistemic reductionism and of the moral-epistemic disparity has been criticized by Richard Rowland (2013) and Terence Cuneo and Christos Kyriacou (2018). This paper aims to rebut these criticisms and, more generally, to clarify and strengthen the case for epistemic reductionism and the moral-epistemic disparity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For brief explanations of these advantages, see Heathwood (2013).

  2. 2.

    Another interesting defense of moral-epistemic parity can be found in Greco (2015). I lack the space to discuss Greco’s arguments here, but see Côte-Bouchard (2017).

  3. 3.

    Furthermore, they are not themselves natural properties. This addition is required to distinguish non-naturalism from non-reductive naturalism.

  4. 4.

    More exactly, they should hold that the property of basic intrinsic goodness is necessarily coextensive with the property of being a state of pleasure (see Harman 1967 and Feldman 2000). I ignore this complication in what follows.

  5. 5.

    A terminological note: in what follows, since it won’t matter, I won’t fuss over the differences between natural and descriptive properties, and I will also sometimes use the expression “non-moral property” for the same thing. I also won’t fuss over the difference between reductionism and naturalism.

  6. 6.

    This phrase is due to Milo (1995, 182, 190–93). See Shafer-Landau (2003, 15–17) for the same sort of definition of moral realism.

  7. 7.

    Provided that pleasure is stance-independent, which is in fact a controversial view. See Bramble (2013) for a stance-independent account of pleasure and Heathwood (2007) for a stance-dependent theory.

  8. 8.

    The Open Question Argument is due to Moore (1903). For a helpful interpretation, see Feldman (2005).

  9. 9.

    Incidentally, I believe that synthetic reductionism fails for other reasons: moral terms don’t function the way that synthetic reductionism requires them to function. See Barnett (2002) and Gampel (1996).

  10. 10.

    To emphasise again: it is not my claim that this biconditional in fact has no counterexamples. Nor am I claiming that it is in no need of clarification or refinement. For example, does “likely to be true” here mean merely a likelihood of greater than 0.5, or does it mean something greater than that, or perhaps something both greater than that and vague? For another example, might we want to include something to the effect that the belief must be based on the evidence? Or perhaps we are talking here about propositional rather than doxastic justification, so that appeals to the basing relation are not needed? Also, what is it for something to be a part of a person’s evidence (this will we discuss briefly below (Sect. 4.2)). These are all important issues, but since my project is the metaepistemological one, I don’t want to—and don’t much need to—get bogged down in the controversies of first-order epistemology.

  11. 11.

    The main one discussed in my (2009) paper is the same analysis that is on display in Sect. 3 above. In that paper, I do allude in passing to the closely related analysis that Rowland focuses on (Heathwood 2009, 89–90).

  12. 12.

    I don’t respond to every one of Cuneo and Kyriacou’s concerns in the main text. One of these concerns is that even if I am right that epistemic reasonability is reducible, this does not show that all epistemic notions are reducible. This is a fair point. My reductive analysis of reasonable belief is only a first step towards showing that the entire epistemic realm can be explained naturalistically. But epistemic reasonability (in other words, epistemic justification) is, it is fair to say, the central normative notion in epistemology. Cuneo and Kyriacou also object that my positon commits non-naturalists in metaethics to the view “that there are not one but two types of reason properties: one that is wholly descriptive and one that is not” (Cuneo and Kyriacou 2018). This is true. But I just think that it is a straightforward consequence of the fact that epistemic facts are naturalistically reducible while moral facts are not, a position that, I have been arguing, we have good reason to accept.

  13. 13.

    And if it really is some epistemologist’s view that, in the example, you have, as a part of your evidence, the information that you are looking at a trumpe l’oeil mural, then I take it that the epistemologist should say that it is in fact not reasonable for you to believe that there is a table before you. After all, you had decisive evidence to the contrary.

  14. 14.

    Cf. Thomas Kelly’s remarks about “theoriz[ing] in the opposite direction”: “to the extent that one has independent intuitions about what an individual would be justified in believing in a given scenario, such intuitions will shape one’s views about what evidence must be available to an individual so situated—and therefore, one’s views about the more general theoretical issue about what evidence is, or what sorts of things can and cannot qualify as evidence” (Kelly 2014, sec. 1).

  15. 15.

    This argument assumes that the “ought” in evidence that a subject ought to take into account is an epistemic “ought.” If this were some other kind of “ought,” such as a moral “ought,” the strategy described above would not succeed (at least given, what I believe, that moral notions are not reducible to descriptive notions). In general, if the moral and the epistemic are in this way entangled, in that whether a belief is reasonable depends on moral factors, my argument for moral-epistemic disparity would fail. For a recent argument for this kind of moral-epistemic entanglement, see Case (forthcoming).

  16. 16.

    The idea that an ideal observer analysis will fall prey to the Open Question Argument if and only if it is understood reductively is recognised by advocates of the Open Question Argument in ethics, such as, for example, Michael Huemer: “I think that there are two ways of understanding this sort of theory [the ideal observer theory], one that makes it non-reductionist and immune to the Open Question Argument, and another that makes it reductionist but vulnerable to the Open Question Argument” (Huemer 2005, 68).

  17. 17.

    I should emphasise that Cuneo and Kyriacou don’t mean the argument that I discuss in this section to stand on its own. It is part of a larger line of argument, which includes the part that I address in the next section.

References

  • Barnett, David. 2002. Against a Posteriori Moral Naturalism. Philosophical Studies 107 (3): 239–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bramble, Ben. 2013. The Distinctive Feeling Theory of Pleasure. Philosophical Studies 162 (2): 201–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Case, Spencer. forthcoming. From Epistemic to Moral Realism. Journal of Moral Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • CĂ´te-Bouchard, Charles. 2017. Epistemological Closed Questions: A Reply to Greco. Manuscrito 40 (4): 97–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cuneo, Terence, and Christos Kyriacou. 2018. Defending the Moral/Epistemic Parity. In Metaepistemology, ed. Conor McHugh, Jonathan Way, and Daniel Whiting. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, Fred. 2000. Basic Intrinsic Value. Philosophical Studies 99 (3): 319–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. The Open Question Argument: What It Isn’t; and What It Is. Philosophical Issues 15 (1): 22–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, Richard. 1988. Having Evidence. In Philosophical Analysis, ed. D.F. Austin, 83–104. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Firth, Roderick. 1952. Ethical Absolutism and the Ideal Observer. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 12 (3): 317–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gampel, Eric H. 1996. A Defense of the Autonomy of Ethics: Why Value is Not like Water. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 26 (2): 191–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greco, Daniel. 2015. Epistemological Open Questions. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 93 (3): 509–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, Gilbert. 1967. Toward a Theory of Intrinsic Value. Journal of Philosophy 64 (23): 792–804.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heathwood, Chris. 2007. The Reduction of Sensory Pleasure to Desire. Philosophical Studies 133 (1): 23–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. Moral and Epistemic Open-Question Arguments. Philosophical Books 50 (2): 83–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Reductionism in Ethics. In International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, Michael. 2005. Ethical Intuitionism. 2005 ed. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. (1738) 1975. A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by L.A. Selby-Bigge and P.H. Nidditch. 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, Thomas. 2014. Evidence. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2014 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/evidence/.

  • Milo, Ronald. 1995. Contractarian Constructivism. The Journal of Philosophy 92 (4): 181–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G.E. 1903. Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowland, Richard. 2013. Moral Error Theory and the Argument from Epistemic Reasons. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 7 (1): 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau, Russ. 2003. Moral Realism: A Defence. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, Timothy. 2000. Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Chris Heathwood .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Heathwood, C. (2018). Epistemic Reductionism and the Moral-Epistemic Disparity. In: Kyriacou, C., McKenna, R. (eds) Metaepistemology. Palgrave Innovations in Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-93369-6_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics