Skip to main content

On the Interpretation of Common Nouns: Types Versus Predicates

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Modern Perspectives in Type-Theoretical Semantics

Part of the book series: Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy ((SLAP,volume 98))

Abstract

When type theories are used for formal semantics, different approaches to the interpretation of common nouns (CNs) become available w.r.t whether a CN is interpreted as a predicate or a type. In this paper, we shall first summarise and analyse several approaches as found in the literature and then study a particularly interesting and potentially challenging issue in a semantics where some CNs are interpreted as types – how to deal with some of the negated sentences and conditionals. When some CNs are interpreted as types (e.g., \(Man :Type\)), a sentence like John is a man can be given a judgemental interpretation \(j:Man\), rather than the traditional Montagovian interpretation man(j). In such a setting, the question is then how to interpret negated sentences like John is not a man (or more complicated sentences like conditionals). A theory for predicational forms of judgemental interpretations is introduced and is shown to be able to deal with negated sentences and conditionals appropriately. A number of examples are considered to show that the theory provides an adequate treatment in various situations. Furthermore, experiments in the proof assistant Coq are performed in order to provide more supporting evidence for this adequacy. Besides the above, we also briefly study the use of indexed types in order to deal with CNs exhibiting temporal sensitivity and gradability.

S. Chatzikyriakidis—Supported by the Centre of Linguistic Theory and Studies in Probability in Gothenburg.

Z. Luo—Partially supported by the research grants from Royal Academy of Engineering, EU COST Action CA15123, and the CAS/SAFEA International Partnership Program for Creative Research Teams.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Please note that this is not just an issue for MTT-semantics; it is a general problem whenever one has many types to interpret (even some) CNs in formal semantics. Several people have raised this issue of how to interpret negated sentences in MTT-semantics to the second author including, to name a few, G. Morrill (during ESSLLI 2011), N. Asher (in email communications about a paper in LACL 2014) and K. Mineshima (in ESSLLI 2014). We are grateful for their interesting discussions and comments.

  2. 2.

    A predicate in a higher-order logic may be seen as different from a predicate in first-order logic. Here, for those who are interested, it is instructive to mention Quine’s view on this difference (Quine 1986) (although the authors should not be regarded as agreeing with it).

  3. 3.

    Decidability of type checking means that of the judgement \(a:A\). In Church’s simple type theory (as used in Montague semantics), it means that, for example, it is decidable to check whether \(j :e\), \(p:t\), \(f:e\rightarrow t\), etc. This obviously has to be decidable for, otherwise, the embedded logic (HOL in Montague’s semantics) could not be used in a feasible way (for example, we would not be able to apply its rules).

  4. 4.

    We cannot explain this in details. See, for example, Beeson (1985) among others.

  5. 5.

    DTS as described in Bekki (2014) does not seem to contain the other logical type constructors such as disjoint union or the empty type. It is unclear how to define some of the logical operators such as negation without the empty type. We might assume that DTS be extended with such types and type constructors, since a logic in DTS is needed for doing formal semantics. (Bekki and Mineshima, in a private communication with the authors after seeing this footnote, have clarified that DTS is intended to contain these type constructors; this is further clarified by adding a new paragraph in Sect. 1.3 of their paper in the current collection Bekki and Mineshima 2016).

  6. 6.

    Formally, the type of a predicate is the function type \(\mathbf e \rightarrow U\), where U is either a type universe or a totality of propositions. We assume that DTS be extended with such a type.

  7. 7.

    This proposal was started by considering a predicational form for a non-hypothetical judgement, proposed in an email communication by the second author with Koji Mineshima during ESSLLI 2014. It was further developed to consider the logical operator not, first proposed in Chatzikyriakidis and Luo (2014) and further developed here, for negated judgements \(\nvdash a:A\) to interpret negated VPs and hypothetical judgements (e.g. conditionals).

  8. 8.

    not was first proposed in Chatzikyriakidis and Luo (2014) to deal with negated VPs. We develop the idea further in this paper.

  9. 9.

    This is the case, for example, when we do not know the type of John in the NL context.

  10. 10.

    To get such genericity would require the so-called bounded quantification which is usually not available in a type theory of any sophistication.

  11. 11.

    In order to do this in Coq, we need to introduce a classical axiom (say, the double negation axiom).

  12. 12.

    In general, dependent types are useful in describing dependent event types, giving a fine-grained treatment of Davidsonian event semantics (Davidson 1967; Parsons 1990). In this respect, an initial study of how event semantics can be considered in dependent type theories has been carried out (Luo and Soloviev 2016) and further work is at the moment in progress.

  13. 13.

    A similar idea has been used by de Groote (2007) in discussing type-theoretic extensions of abstract categorial grammars. However, indices there are used on the (linguistic) syntactic level, trying to capture morphological considerations (e.g. gender, number etc.); in effect those indices correspond to elements that are morphologically realized. In our case, the approach deals with things that are not morphologically realized (e.g. grades) and is purely on the (linguistic) semantic level.

  14. 14.

    The calculus pCIC is very similar to UTT (Luo 1994), the MTT we have used in MTT-semantics. This is the case especially after the universe Set became predicative in the version 8 of Coq in 2004 (The Coq Team 2007).

References

  • Asher, N. (2012). Lexical meaning in context: A web of words. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N., Abrusan, M., & van de Cruys, T. (2016). Types, meanings and co-composition in lexical semantics. In this volume.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N., & Luo, Z. (2012). In Formalisation of coercions in lexical semantics, Sinn und Bedeutung 17, Paris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beeson, M. J. (1985). Foundations of constructive mathematics. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bekki, D. (2014). Representing anaphora with dependent types. Logical aspects of computational linguistics (Vol. 8535), LNCS Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bekki, D., & Mineshima, K. (2016). Context-passing and underspecification in dependent type semantics. In this volume.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chatzikyriakidis, S., & Luo, Z. (2013). Adjectives in a modern type-theoretical setting. In G. Morrill & J. M. Nederhof (Eds.), Proceedings of Formal Grammar 2013. LNCS 8036 (pp. 159–174).

    Google Scholar 

  • Chatzikyriakidis, S., & Luo, Z. (2014). Natural language reasoning in Coq. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 23, 441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chatzikyriakidis, S., & Luo, Z. (2015). Individuation criteria, dot-types and copredication: A view from modern type theories. Proceedings of the 14th International Conference on Mathematics of Language, Chicago, (Vol. 23).

    Google Scholar 

  • Chatzikyriakidis, S., & Luo, Z. (2016). Adjectival and adverbial modification in modern type theories. Manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  • Church, A. (1940). A formulation of the simple theory of types. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 5(1), 56–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Constantinescu, C. (2013). In Big eaters and real idiots: evidence for adnominal degree modification? Sinn und Bedeutung, (Vol. 17, pp. 183–200).

    Google Scholar 

  • Curry, H. B., & Feys, R. (1958). Combinatory logic (Vol. 1). Amsterdam: North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1967). The logical form of action sentences. In S. Rothstein (Ed.), The logic of decision and action. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Groote, P., & Maarek, S. (2007). Type-theoretic extensions of abstract categorial grammars. In Proceedings of Workshop on New Directions in Type-theoretic Grammars.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geach, P. (1962). Reference and generality. New York: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, W. A. (1980). The formulae-as-types notion of construction. In J. Hindley & J. Seldin (Eds.), To H. B. Curry: Essays on combinatory logic. Cambridge: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krahmer, E., & Piwek, P. (1999). Presupposition projection as proof construction. In H. Bunt & R. Muskens (Eds.), Computing meaning, Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy Netherlands: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luo, Z. (1994). Computation and reasoning: A type theory for computer science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luo, Z. (1999). Coercive subtyping. Journal of Logic and Computation, 9(1), 105–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luo, Z. (2010). Type-theoretical semantics with coercive subtyping. In Semantics and Linguistic Theory 20 (SALT20), Vancouver.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luo, Z. (2011). Contextual analysis of word meanings in type-theoretical semantics. Logical aspects of computational linguistics (LACL’2011) (Vol. 6736), LNAI New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luo, Z. (2012). Common nouns as types. In D. Bechet & A. Dikovsky (Eds.), Logical aspects of computational linguistics (LACL’2012) (Vol. 7351), LNCS Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luo, Z. (2012a). Formal semantics in modern type theories with coercive subtyping. Linguistics and Philosophy, 35(6), 491–513.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luo, Z., & Soloviev, S. (2016) Dependent event types. Manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luo, Z., Soloviev, S., & Xue, T. (2012). Coercive subtyping: Theory and implementation. Information and Computation, 223, 18–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin-Löf, P. (1984). Intuitionistic type theory. Italy: Bibliopolis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moltmann, F. (2003). Nominalizing quantifiers. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 32(5), 445–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moltmann, F. (2007). Events, tropes, and truthmaking. Philosophical Studies, 134(3), 363–403.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R. (1973). The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English. In J. Hintikka, J. Moravcsik, & P. Suppes (Eds.), Approaches to natural languages. Netherlands: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R. (1974). In R. Thomason (Ed.), Formal philosophy. Connecticut: Yale University Press. Collected papers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morzycki, M. (2009). Degree modification of gradable nouns: Size adjectives and adnominal degree morphemes. Natural Language Semantics, 17(2), 175–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nordström, B., Petersson, K., & Smith, J. (1990). Programming in Martin-Löf’s type theory: An Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, T. (1990). Events in the semantics of english. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1986). Philosophy of logic (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ranta, A. (1994). Type-theoretical grammar. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Retoré, C. (2013). The montagovian generative lexicon Tyn: A type theoretical framework for natural language semantics. In R. Matthes & A. Schubert (Eds.), Proceedings of TYPES2013.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solt, S. (2009). The semantics of adjectives of quantity. Ph.D. Thesis, The City University of New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tanaka, R., Mineshima, K., & Bekki, D. (2015). Factivity and presupposition in dependent type semantics. In Type Theories and Lexical Semantics Workshop.

    Google Scholar 

  • The Coq Team. (2007). The Coq Proof Assistant Reference Manual (Version 8.1), INRIA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tonhauser, J. (2002). A dynamic semantic account of the temporal interpretation of noun phrases. Semantics and linguistic theory (pp. 286–305). New York: Cornell University.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks go to Koji Mineshima for very helpful email communications with the second author, often with thought provoking questions and examples.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stergios Chatzikyriakidis .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendices

A. Coq: A Gentle Introduction

Coq is an interactive theorem prover, i.e. a proof-assistant, that implements the Calculus of Inductive Constructions (pCIC, see The Coq Team 2007), in effect an MTT.Footnote 14 The basic idea behind Coq is as follows: it helps one to see whether propositions based on statements previously pre-defined or user defined (definitions, parameters, variables) can be proven or not. To give a very short example on how Coq operates, imagine that we want to prove the following propositional tautology:

  1. (73)

    \(((P \vee Q) \wedge (P \rightarrow R) \wedge (Q \rightarrow R)) \rightarrow R\)

Given Coq’s typed nature we have to introduce the variables PQR as being of type Prop (PQR : Prop). Using the command Theorem, we put Coq into proof mode:

  1. (74)

    Theorem A :  \(((P \vee Q) \wedge (P \rightarrow R) \wedge (Q \rightarrow R)) \rightarrow R\)

figure o

The idea from this point onwards is to guide the prover into the completion of the proof using proof tactics that are either already predefined or can be defined by the user using the tactical language Ltac. For the case interested, we first introduce the antecedent as an assumption using intro:

figure p

We split the hypothesis into individual hypotheses using destruct

figure q

Now, we can apply the elimination rule for disjunction (elim) which will basically result in two subgoals:

figure r

The two subgoals are already hypotheses. We can use the assumption tactic that matches the goal with an identical hypothesis and the proof is completed:

figure s

Now, what we need to do in order to reason about NL is to implement our theoretical accounts we have provided in Coq. For example, one must introduce the universe \(\textsc {cn}\) and further declare the types of the universe. For the moment, since universe construction is not an option in Coq, we define \(\textsc {cn}\) to be Coq’s predefined Set universe. We show these, plus the introduction of individuals John and Mary and quantifier some. We also introduce the subtyping relations \(Man<Human<Animal<Object\):

figure t

With the above definitions one can perform reasoning tasks, for example one might want to check whether some man walks follows from John walks. We formulate this as a theorem named EX:

figure u

The next step here is to unfold the definition for the quantifier. This is done using the cbv command, which basically performs any reduction possible. Then, we move the antecedent as a hypothesis using intro:

figure v

At this point, we use the exists tactic to substitute John for x. Using assumption the theorem is proven.

B. Coq Data and Assumptions

The following gives all of the data and assumptions made in Coq in order to deal with all the examples discussed in this paper.

figure w

We further assume that all the types in the universe D are totally ordered and dense; i.e., they respect the following axioms:

$$\begin{aligned} (reflexivity)&\forall A:D.\ \forall d:A.\ d\le d \\ (anti\texttt {-}symmetry)&\forall A:D.\ \forall d, d_1:A.\ d\le d_1\wedge d_1 \le d \rightarrow d = d_1 \\ (transitivity)&\forall A:D.\ \forall d, d_1,d_2:A.\ d\le d_1\wedge d_1 \le d_2 \rightarrow d \le d_2 \\ (density)&\forall A:D.\ \forall d, d_1:A.\ d\le d_1\rightarrow \exists d_2:A. d \le d_2 \le d_1 \end{aligned}$$

Remark

There is a pending question w.r.t the formal properties of grades. One of the common assumptions in the literature is that grades are dense, total, transitive, anti-symmetric and reflexive. The question is whether these assumptions are enough or different weaking might be needed depending on the grade in each case. What is rather difficult to tackle is the formal properties of abstract grades like idiocy.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Chatzikyriakidis, S., Luo, Z. (2017). On the Interpretation of Common Nouns: Types Versus Predicates. In: Chatzikyriakidis, S., Luo, Z. (eds) Modern Perspectives in Type-Theoretical Semantics. Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy, vol 98. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-50422-3_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-50422-3_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-50420-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-50422-3

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics