Skip to main content

Social Creation of Pro-social Preferences for Collective Action

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Theory of Externalities and Public Goods

Abstract

Pro-social preferences are thought to play a significant role in solving society’s collective action problems of providing public goods and reducing public bads. Societies can benefit by deliberately instilling and sustaining such preferences in their members. We construct a theoretical model to examine an intergenerational education process for this. We consider both a one-time action of this kind and a constitution that establishes a steady state, and compare the two.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Induction in this context is a mild form of discipline technique. Hoffman defines and explains it as follows: “When children harm or are about to harm someone—the parent, a sibling, a friend— indicate[s] implicitly or explicitly that the act is wrong and that the child has committed an infraction. This creates the condition for feeling empathy-based guilt. Hoffman (2000, pp. 150–151).

  2. 2.

    The need for collective action for preference formation is the crucial respect in which our model differs from other models where individual parents shape their children’s preferences, for example Bisin and Verdier (2001), Tabellini (2008).

  3. 3.

    The problem of the commons, where the issue is how to dissuade individuals from creating a public bad, is the mirror image of this, and can be analyzed by similar methods. In other contexts, sufficiently pro-social preferences may lead to a coordination or “assurance” game. Such more complex interaction topologies are subject of our ongoing work.

  4. 4.

    See Friedman (1962, p. 191) for an early argument along these lines in favor of government action to alleviate poverty.

References

  • Akcay, E., Van Cleve, J., Feldman, M. W., & Roughgarden, J. (2009). A theory for the evolution of other-regard integrating proximate and ultimate perspectives. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 106, 19061–19066.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K. J., & Levin, S. A. (2009). Intergenerational resource transfers with random offspring numbers. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 106, 13702–13706.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bisin, A., & Verdier, T. (2001). The economics of cultural transmission and the dynamics of preferences. Journal of Economic Theory, 97(2), 298–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boocock, S. S., & Scott, K. A. (2005). Kids in context: The sociological study of children and childhoods. Lanham, MD: Rowan and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cornes, R., Itaya, J.-I., & Tanaka, A. (2012). Private provision of public goods between families. Journal of Population Economics, 25(4), 1451–1480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cornes, R., & Sandler, T. (1996). The theory of externalities, public goods, and club goods (2nd ed.). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cornes, R., & Silva, E. C. D. (1999). Rotten kids, purity, and perfection. Journal of Political Economy, 107(5), 1034–1040

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dixit, A. (2009). Governance institutions and economic activity. American Economic Review, 99(1), 5–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, E., & Gintis, H. (2007). Human motivation and social cooperation: Experimental and analytical foundations. Annual Review of Sociology, 33, 43–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1962). Capitalism and freedom. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gintis, H. (2003). Solving the puzzle of pro-sociality. Rationality and Society, 15, 155–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, G. (1968). The tragedy of the commons. Science, 162, 1243–1248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henrich, J., Boyd, R., Bowles, S., Camerer, C., Fehr, E., Gintis, H., et al. (2001). In search of Homo economicus: Behavioral experiments in 15 small-scale societies. American Economic Review, 91, 73–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henrich, J., Heine, S. J., & Norenzayan, A. (2010). The weirdest people in the world? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33, 61–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, M. L. (2000). Empathy and moral development. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levin, S. A. (1999). Fragile dominion: Complexity and the commons. Reading, MA: Perseus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom, E. (1990). Governing the commons: The evolution of institutions for collective action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rabin, M. (1993). Incorporating fairness into game-theory and economics. American Economic Review, 83, 1281–1302.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, D. L., Levin, S. A., & Laxminarayan, R. (2005). Strategic interactions in multi-institutional epidemics of antibiotic resistance. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 102, 3153–3158.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tabellini, G. (2008). The scope of cooperation: Values and incentives. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 123(3), 905–950.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Funding was provided by the National Science Foundation grants GEO-1211972 and OCE-1426746, and by the Nordforsk-funded project Green Growth Based on Marine Resources: Ecological and Socio-Economic Constraints (GreenMAR) to Simon A. Levin.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Avinash Dixit .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix: Mathematical Derivations

Appendix: Mathematical Derivations

1.1 Nash Equilibrium with Pro-sociality

Begin with the purely selfish case, set out in Sect. 2, Eqs. (1)–(3). The Kuhn-Tucker conditions for individual i’s choice of (x i , z i ) to maximize u i are

$$ \displaystyle\begin{array}{rcl} \frac{\partial u_{i}} {\partial x_{i}}& =& 1 + \overline{z} -{ 2 \over 3}\,(x_{i} + z_{i}) \leq 0,\quad x_{i} \geq 0\,,{}\end{array}$$
(20)
$$\displaystyle\begin{array}{rcl} \frac{\partial u_{i}} {\partial z_{i}}& =&{ 1 \over n}\ x_{i} -{ 2 \over 3}\,(x_{i} + z_{i}) \leq 0,\quad z_{i} \geq 0\,,{}\end{array}$$
(21)

with complementary slackness in each equation. Note that in (21) we have used \(\partial \overline{z}/\partial z_{i} = 1/n\). The matrix of second-order partials is

$$\displaystyle{\left (\begin{array}{cc} -{ 2 \over 3} & -{ 2 \over 3} +{ 1 \over n} \\ -{ 2 \over 3} +{ 1 \over n} & -{ 2 \over 3} \end{array} \right )\,.}$$

The diagonal elements of this are negative, and the determinant is

$$\displaystyle{\left ({2 \over 3}\right )^{2} -\left ({2 \over 3} -{ 1 \over n}\right )^{2}> 0\,.}$$

Therefore the matrix is negative definite, so the second-order sufficient conditions are met and the Kuhn-Tucker conditions yield the global maximum of u i . (This will continue to be so in all the variants of the model considered here, and will not be mentioned further.)

First try the purely selfish solution where x i  > 0 and z i  = 0 for all i. Then \(\overline{z} = 0\) also, and the conditions (20) and (21) are

$$\displaystyle{1 -{ 2 \over 3}\,x_{i} = 0,\qquad \left ({ 1 \over n} -{ 2 \over 3}\right )\,x_{i} \leq 0\,,}$$

or

$$\displaystyle{x_{i} ={ 3 \over 2},\qquad { 1 \over n} \leq { 2 \over 3}\,.}$$

The inequality is true for n ≥ 2. Therefore the solution x i  = 3∕2, z i  = 0 in (4) is verified. The y i and u i are easily computed.

Next consider the symmetric social optimum. Recall that the common private and public effort levels x i  = x and z i  = z for all i, are chosen to maximize the common utility level

$$\displaystyle{u = x\,(1 + z) -{ 1 \over 3}\ (x + z)^{2}\,.}$$

The first-order conditions are

$$\displaystyle\begin{array}{rcl} \frac{\partial u} {\partial x}& =& 1 + z -{ 2 \over 3}\,(x + z) = 0\,, {}\\ \frac{\partial u} {\partial z}& =& x -{ 2 \over 3}\,(x + z) = 0\,. {}\\ \end{array}$$

These yield the solution x = 2, z = 1 in (6). The resulting y and u are easily found.

Next consider equilibria where people have the pro-social utility (7), with the same γ for all. The Kuhn-Tucker conditions for person 1 are:

$$\displaystyle\begin{array}{rcl} \frac{\partial v_{1}} {\partial x_{1}}& =& 1 + \overline{z} -{ 2 \over 3}\,(x_{1} + z_{1}) \leq 0,\quad x_{1} \geq 0\,,{}\end{array}$$
(22)
$$\displaystyle\begin{array}{rcl} \frac{\partial v_{1}} {\partial z_{1}}& =&{ 1 \over n}\ x_{1} -{ 2 \over 3}\,(x_{1} + z_{1}) +\gamma \ \sum _{ j=2}^{n}\,{ 1 \over n}\,x_{j} \leq 0,\quad z_{i} \geq 0\,,{}\end{array}$$
(23)

with complementary slackness in each. Similar conditions obtain for the other individuals.

See if the selfish solution with x i  > 0, z i  = 0 still works. The conditions (22) and (23) become

$$\displaystyle{1 -{ 2 \over 3}\,x_{i} = 0,\qquad { 1 \over n}\ x_{1} -{ 2 \over 3}\,x_{1} +\gamma \ \sum _{ j=2}^{n}\,{ 1 \over n}\,x_{j} \leq 0\,,}$$

or

$$\displaystyle{x_{i} ={ 3 \over 2},\qquad {3 \over 2}\,\left ({ 1 \over n} -{ 2 \over 3} +\gamma { n-1 \over n} \right ) \leq 0\,.}$$

The inequality becomes

$$\displaystyle{\phi = \frac{1 + (n - 1)\,\gamma } {n} \leq \frac{2} {3}\,,}$$

which is equivalent to (8) in the text.

When this condition is not met, look for a symmetric Nash equilibrium with x i  = x > 0 and z i  = z > 0 for all i. The conditions (22) and (23) become

$$\displaystyle\begin{array}{rcl} 1 + z& =&{ 2 \over 3}\,(x + z)\,, {}\\ \phi \,x& =&{ 2 \over 3}\,(x + z)\,. {}\\ \end{array}$$

These yield the solution (10) in the text.

Writing u for the common level of selfish utility, it is then mechanical to verify

$$\displaystyle{\frac{du} {d\phi } = \frac{8\,(1-\phi )} {(2-\phi )^{2}} \,.}$$

Therefore u is an increasing function of ϕ over the range \(({2 \over 3},1)\). Thus more pro-socialness achieves higher selfish utilities all round.

1.2 One-Time Education for Pro-socialness

In the range 0 ≤ ϕ ≤ 2∕3, it is obviously best to set ϕ = 0 and get U a = 0. 75 (1 +δ). In the range 2∕3 ≤ ϕ ≤ 1, use θ = (kδ)1∕3, to substitute k = δθ 3, and write the formula defining the function for \(\phi \geq { 2 \over 3}\) as

$$\displaystyle{ f(\phi ) = 0.75 +\delta \ \left [\,\frac{\phi \,(4 - 3\phi )} {(2-\phi )^{2}} - \frac{\theta ^{3}} {1-\phi }\,\right ]\,. }$$
(24)

It is then mechanical to verify

$$\displaystyle{f^{{\prime}}(\phi ) = \frac{\delta } {(1-\phi )^{2}}\ \left [\ 8\,\left (\frac{1-\phi } {2-\phi }\right )^{3} -\theta ^{3}\ \right ]\,.}$$

Therefore

$$\displaystyle{ f^{{\prime}}(\phi )> 0\quad \mbox{ iff}\quad 2\,\frac{1-\phi } {2-\phi }>\theta,\quad \mbox{ i.e.}\quad \phi <\phi ^{{\ast}} = \frac{2\,(1-\theta )} {2-\theta } \,. }$$
(25)

Therefore f(ϕ) is single-peaked, and its maximum occurs where f (ϕ) = 0, that is, at ϕ = ϕ . Substituting and simplifying, the maximum value is

$$\displaystyle{f(\phi ^{{\ast}}) = 0.75 +\delta \, \left (\ \theta ^{3} - 3\,\theta ^{2} + 1\ \right )\,.}$$

If this exceeds 0. 75 (1 +δ), then ϕ maximizes f(ϕ) in (14); otherwise ϕ = 0 yields the maximum of f(ϕ).

We also need to restrict ϕ  > 2∕3 to have an equilibrium that results in the utilities that enter the construction of f(ϕ). From the definition in (7), we see that 1 ≥ ϕ  > 2∕3 corresponds to 0 ≤ θ < 1∕2. Now define

$$\displaystyle{h(\theta ) =\theta ^{3} - 3\,\theta ^{2} + 1 - 0.75 =\theta ^{3} - 3\,\theta ^{2} + 0.25\,.}$$

We have

$$\displaystyle{h^{{\prime}}(\theta ) = 3\ \theta ^{2} - 6\,\theta = 3\,\theta \,(\theta -2)\,,}$$

which is negative over the interval \((0,{ 1 \over 2})\). Therefore h(θ) is a decreasing function throughout this range. Also h(0) = 1∕4 > 0 and \(h({1 \over 2}) = -3/8 <0\). Therefore there is a unique θ in the interval such that h(θ) > 0 for θ < θ and h(θ) < 0 for θ > θ . Numerical calculation shows that θ  ≈ 0. 305. This completes the proof of the statements in the text leading to (15).

1.3 Education for Pro-socialness in Steady State

Write the objective function in (26) as v = ng(ϕ) where

$$\displaystyle{ g(\phi ) = \left \{\begin{array}{ll} 0.75\ \phi - \frac{k\,\phi } {1-\phi } &\mbox{ for }\phi <2/3 \\ \frac{\phi ^{2}\,(4-3\phi )} {(2-\phi )^{2}} - \frac{k\,\phi } {1-\phi }&\mbox{ for }2/3 <\phi <1 \end{array} \right. }$$
(26)

For 0 ≤ ϕ < 2∕3 we have

$$\displaystyle{g^{{\prime}}(\phi ) = 0.75 - \frac{k} {(1-\phi )^{2}}}$$

and

$$\displaystyle{g^{{\prime\prime}}(\phi ) = \frac{-2\,k} {(1-\phi )^{3}} <0}$$

Therefore g(ϕ) is concave in this range. Also

$$\displaystyle{g^{{\prime}}(0) = 0.75 - k> 0\quad \mbox{ if }k <0.75}$$

and

$$\displaystyle{g^{{\prime}}(2/3) = 0.75 - 9\,k <0\quad \mbox{ if }k> 1/12}$$

For 2∕3 < ϕ < 1 we have, after some tedious algebra,

$$\displaystyle{g^{{\prime}}(\phi ) = \frac{\phi \,(16 - 18\ \phi + 3\ \phi ^{2})} {(2-\phi )^{3}} - \frac{k} {(1-\phi )^{2}}}$$

Then

$$\displaystyle{g^{{\prime}}(2/3) = 3/2 - 9\,k> 0\quad \mbox{ if }k <1/6}$$

and

$$\displaystyle{g^{{\prime}}(\phi ) \rightarrow -\infty \quad \mbox{ as}\quad \phi \rightarrow 1}$$

In general, g(ϕ) is not concave throughout the range 2∕3 < ϕ < 1. (Specifically, the first term on the right hand side of (26) is convex for 2∕3 < ϕ < 4∕5 and concave for 4∕5 < ϕ < 1, so g(ϕ) can be convex for a sub-range to the right of 2/3 if k is small.) But numerical calculation shows that

$$\displaystyle{(1-\phi )^{2}\ g^{{\prime}}(\phi ) = \frac{\phi \,(1-\phi )^{2}\,(16 - 18\ \phi + 3\ \phi ^{2})} {(2-\phi )^{3}} - k}$$

is a decreasing function of ϕ. It equals 1∕6 − k for ϕ = 2∕3 and − k for ϕ = 1. Therefore, if k < 1∕6, g (ϕ) is positive for ϕ < a critical value ϕ (which is uniquely defined for each k and of course depends on k), and negative for ϕ > ϕ . Then g(ϕ) is increasing for 2∕3 < ϕ < ϕ and decreasing for ϕ  < ϕ < 1, i.e. g(ϕ) has a unique interior maximum at ϕ in the range 2∕3 < ϕ < 1.

Putting all this information together gives the statements in the text.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Dixit, A., Levin, S. (2017). Social Creation of Pro-social Preferences for Collective Action. In: Buchholz, W., Rübbelke, D. (eds) The Theory of Externalities and Public Goods. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-49442-5_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics