Keywords

JEL Classification

1 Introduction

How should we treat future generations? From a normative point of view, what are the present generation’s obligations towards the future? What ethical criterion for intergenerational justice should be adopted if one seeks to respect the interests of future generations? Answering such questions is essential when faced with the task of managing the global environment, e.g., in the context of climate change.Footnote 1

These questions can be approached and answered in at least two ways:

  1. 1.

    Through an axiomatic analysis one can investigate on what ethical conditions various criteria for intergenerational justice are based, and then proceed to evaluate the normative appeal of these conditions.

  2. 2.

    By considering different technological environments, one can explore the consequences of various criteria for intergenerational justice, and compare the properties of the intergenerational well-being streams that are generated.

It is consistent with Rawls (1971) reflective equilibrium to do both: criteria for intergenerational justice should be judged both by the ethical conditions on which they build and by their consequences in specific technological environments. In particular, we may question the appropriateness of a criterion for intergenerational justice if it produces unacceptable outcomes in relevant technological environments. This view has been supported by many scholars, including Koopmans (1967), [Dasgupta and Heal 1979, p. 311], and [Atkinson 2001, p. 206].

When evaluating long-term policies, economists usually suggest to maximize the sum of discounted utilities. On the one hand, such discounted utilitarianism has been given a solid axiomatic foundation by Koopmans (1960).Footnote 2 On the other hand, this criterion has ethically questionable implications when applied to economic models with resource constraints. This is demonstrated by Dasgupta and Heal (1974) in the so-called Dasgupta-Heal-Solow (DHS) model of capital accumulation and resource depletion (Dasgupta and Heal 1974, 1979; Solow 1974), where discounted utilitarianism for any positive discount rate undermines the well-being of generations in far future, even if sustainable streams with non-decreasing well-being are feasible.

In this paper we revisit Koopmans (1960) framework, with numerical representability, sensitivity and stationarity as its key features. In Sect. 2 we consider conditions that are sufficient to numerically represent the social welfare relation by means of a recursive social welfare function satisfying sensitivity, stationarity and a condition requiring that the evaluation of two streams with the same present well-being not depend on what that level of well-being is, thereby echoing the analysis of [Koopmans 1960, Sects. 3–7]. In this framework we introduce an equity condition we call “Hammond Equity for the Future”, capturing the following ethical intuition: A sacrifice by the present generation leading to a uniform gain for all future generations cannot lead to a less desirable stream of well-being if the present remains better-off than the future even after the sacrifice.Footnote 3

In Sect. 3 we point out that “Hammond Equity for the Future” is weak, as it is implied by all the standard consequentialist equity conditions suggested in the literature. We show that adding this condition leads to a class of sustainable recursive social welfare functions, where the well-being of the present generation is taken into account if and only if the future is better-off. Furthermore, we establish general existence by means of an algorithmic construction. Finally, we show that any member of this class of sustainable recursive social welfare functions satisfies the key axioms of Chichilnisky’s (1996) “sustainable preferences”, namely “No Dictatorship of the Present” and “No Dictatorship of the Future”.Footnote 4

In Sect. 4 we offer results that identify which of the conditions used by Koopmans (1960) to axiomatize discounted utilitarianism is particularly questionable from an ethical perspective. The condition in question, referred to as “Independent Present” by us and listed as Postulate \(3'\)a by [Koopmans 1960, Sect. 14], requires that the evaluation of two streams which differ during only the first two periods not depend on what the common continuation stream is. It is only by means of “Independent Present” that [Koopmans 1960, Sect. 14] moves beyond the recursive form to arrive at discounted utilitarianism, since this condition allows for additively separable representations when combined with stationarity and the requirement that the evaluation of two streams with the same present well-being not depend on what that level of well-being is (Debreu 1960; Gorman 1968a; Koopmans 1986a).

We suggest in Sect. 4 that “Independent Present”—which in the words of Heal (2005) is “restrictive” and “surely not innocent”—may not be supported by ethical intuition, as it is not obvious that the resolution of a conflict between the first two generations should be independent of how their well-being compares to the well-being of later generations. In our formal analysis we single out “Independent Present” as the culprit by showing that the addition of this condition contradicts both “Hammond Equity for the Future” and the Chichilnisky’s (1996) conditions.

In Sect. 5 we apply sustainable recursive social welfare functions for studying optimal harvesting of a renewable resource that yields amenities. In a companion paper (Asheim and Mitra 2010) it is demonstrated how such functions can be used to solve the distributional conflicts in the DHS model. In both settings, our new criterion yields consequences that differ from those of discounted utilitarianism.

Koopmans (1960) has often been interpreted as presenting the definitive case for discounted utilitarianism. In Sect. 6 we discuss how our results contribute to a weakening of this impression, by exploring other avenues within the general setting of his approach. We also investigate the scope for our new equity condition “Hammond Equity for the Future” outside the Koopmans (1960) framework by not imposing that the social welfare relation is numerically representable.

All lemmas and proofs are relegated to an appendix.

2 Formal Setting and Basic Result

Let \(\mathbb {R}\) denote the set of real numbers and \(\mathbb {Z}_+\) the set of non-negative integers. Denote by \({}_0\mathbf {x} = (x_0, x_1, \dots , x_t, \dots , )\) an infinite stream, where \(x_t \in Y\) is a one-dimensional indicator of the well-being of generation t, and \(Y \subseteq \mathbb {R}\) is a non-degenerate interval of admissible well-beings.Footnote 5 We will consider the set \(\mathbf {X}\) of infinite streams bounded in well-being (see Koopmans 1986b, p. 89); i.e., \(\mathbf {X}\) is given by

$$\mathbf {X} = \{ {}_0\mathbf {x} \in \mathbb {R}^{\mathbb {Z}_+} \mid [{\inf }_t x_t, \, {\sup }_t x_t] \subseteq Y \} \, .$$

By setting \(Y = [0,1]\), this includes the important special case where \(\mathbf {X} = [0,1]^{\mathbb {Z}_+}\). However, the formulation allows for cases where Y is not compact.

Denote by \({}_0\mathbf {x}_{T-1} = (x_0, x_1, \dots , x_{T-1})\) and \(_T\mathbf {x} = (x_T, x_{T+1}, \dots , x_{T+t}, \dots , )\) the T-head and the T-tail of \({}_0\mathbf {x}\). Write \(_{\text {con}}z = (z, z, \dots )\) for the stream of a constant level of well-being equal to \(z \in Y\). Throughout this paper we assume that the indicator of well-being is at least ordinally measurable and level comparable across generations; Blackorby et al. (1984) call this “level-plus comparability”.

For all \({}_0\mathbf {x}\), \({}_0\mathbf {y} \in \mathbf {X}\), we write \({}_0\mathbf {x} \, \ge \, {}_0\mathbf {y}\) if and only if \(x_t \ge y_t\) for all \(t \in \mathbb {Z}_+\), \({}_0\mathbf {x} \, > \, {}_0\mathbf {y}\) if and only if \({}_0\mathbf {x} \, \ge \, {}_0\mathbf {y}\) and \({}_0\mathbf {x} \, \ne \, {}_0\mathbf {y}\), and \({}_0\mathbf {x} \, \gg \, {}_0\mathbf {y}\) if and only if \(x_t > y_t\) for all \(t \in \mathbb {Z}_+\).

A social welfare relation (swr) is a binary relation \(\succsim \) on \(\mathbf {X}\), where for all \({}_0\mathbf {x}\), \({}_0\mathbf {y} \in \mathbf {X}\), \({}_0\mathbf {x} \, \succsim \, {}_0\mathbf {y}\) stands for \(({}_0\mathbf {x}, \, {}_0\mathbf {y}) \in \; \succsim \) and entails that \({}_0\mathbf {x}\) is deemed socially at least as good as \({}_0\mathbf {y}\). Denote by \(\sim \) and \(\succ \) the symmetric and asymmetric parts of \(\succsim \); i.e., \({}_0\mathbf {x} \, \sim \, {}_0\mathbf {y}\) is equivalent to \({}_0\mathbf {x} \, \succsim \, {}_0\mathbf {y}\) and \({}_0\mathbf {y} \, \succsim \, {}_0\mathbf {x}\) and entails that \({}_0\mathbf {x}\) is deemed socially indifferent to \({}_0\mathbf {y}\), while \({}_0\mathbf {x} \, \succ \, {}_0\mathbf {y}\) is equivalent to \({}_0\mathbf {x} \, \succsim \, {}_0\mathbf {y}\) and \({}_0\mathbf {y} / \succsim \, {}_0\mathbf {x}\) and entails that \({}_0\mathbf {x}\) is deemed socially preferred to \({}_0\mathbf {y}\).

All comparisons are made at time 0. We abuse notation slightly by writing, for T, \(T' \ge 0\), \(_T \mathbf {x}\) and \(_{T'} \mathbf {y}\) when referring to \({}_0\mathbf {x}'\) and \({}_0\mathbf {y}'\) where, for all t, \(x'_t = x_{T+t}\) and \(y'_t = y_{T'+t}\). This notational convention allows us to write \(_T \mathbf {x}\), \(_{T'} \mathbf {y} \in \mathbf {X}\) and \(_T\mathbf {x} \, \succsim \, _{T'}\mathbf {y}\). It is used throughout the paper; e.g., in the definition of condition IF, in the statement of Lemma 2, and in the proofs of Proposition 2 and Lemma 3.

A social welfare function (swf) representing \(\succsim \) is a mapping \(W : \mathbf {X} \rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) with the property that for all \(_0\mathbf {x}\), \(_0\mathbf {y} \in \mathbf {X}\), \(W(_0\mathbf {x}) \ge W(_0\mathbf {y})\) if and only if \(_0\mathbf {x} \, \succsim \, _0\mathbf {y}\). A mapping \(W : \mathbf {X} \rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) is monotone if \(_0\mathbf {x} \, \ge \, _0\mathbf {y}\) implies \(W(_0 \mathbf {x}) \ge W(_0 \mathbf {y})\).

In the present section we impose conditions on the swr sufficient to obtain a numerical representation in terms of an swf with a recursive structure (see Proposition 2 below), similar to but not identical to [Koopmans 1960, Sects. 3–7].

To obtain a numerical representation, we impose two conditions.

Condition O (Order) \(\succsim \) is complete (for all \(_0\mathbf {x}\), \(_0\mathbf {y} \in \mathbf {X}\), \(_0\mathbf {x} \, \succsim \, _0\mathbf {y}\) or \(_0\mathbf {y} \, \succsim \, _0\mathbf {x}\)) and transitive (for all \(_0\mathbf {x}\), \(_0\mathbf {y}\), \(_0\mathbf {z} \in \mathbf {X}\), \(_0\mathbf {x} \, \succsim \, _0\mathbf {y}\) and \(_0\mathbf {y} \, \succsim \, _0\mathbf {z}\) imply \(_0\mathbf {x} \, \succsim \, _0\mathbf {z}\)).

Condition RC (Restricted Continuity) For all \(_0\mathbf {x}\), \(_0\mathbf {y} \in \mathbf {X}\), if \(_0\mathbf {x}\) satisfies \(x_t = z\) for all \(t \ge 1\), and the sequence of streams \(\langle _0\mathbf {x}^n\rangle _{n \in \mathbb {N}}\) satisfies \(\lim _{n \rightarrow \infty } \sup _{t} |x_t^n - x_t| = 0\) with, for each \(n \in \mathbb {N}\), \(_0\mathbf {x}^n \in \mathbf {X}\) and \(_0 \mathbf {x}^n \, \nprec \, _0 \mathbf {y}\) (resp. \(_0 \mathbf {x}^n \, \nsucc \, _0 \mathbf {y}\)), then \(_0 \mathbf {x} \, \nprec \, _0 \mathbf {y}\) (resp. \(_0 \mathbf {x} \, \nsucc \, _0 \mathbf {y}\)).

Condition RC is weaker than ordinary supnorm continuity as, under condition RC, the stream \(_0\mathbf {x}\) to which the sequence \(\langle _0\mathbf {x}^n\rangle _{n \in \mathbb {N}}\) converges is restricted to having a constant level of well-being from period 1 on.

Condition C (Continuity) For all \(_0\mathbf {x}\), \(_0\mathbf {y} \in \mathbf {X}\), if the sequence of streams \(\langle _0\mathbf {x}^n\rangle _{n \in \mathbb {N}}\) satisfies \(\lim _{n \rightarrow \infty } \sup _{t} |x_t^n - x_t| = 0\) with, for each \(n \in \mathbb {N}\), \(_0\mathbf {x}^n \in \mathbf {X}\) and \(_0 \mathbf {x}^n \, \nprec \, _0 \mathbf {y}\) (resp. \(_0 \mathbf {x}^n \, \nsucc \, _0 \mathbf {y}\)), then \(_0 \mathbf {x} \, \nprec \, _0 \mathbf {y}\) (resp. \(_0 \mathbf {x} \, \nsucc \, _0 \mathbf {y}\)).

Condition C is entailed by Koopmans (1960) Postulate 1. As the analysis of Sect. 3 shows, the weaker continuity condition RC enables us to show existence of sustainable recursive social welfare functions.

The central condition in Koopmans (1960) analysis is the stationarity postulate (Postulate 4). Combined with Koopmans’ Postulate 3b (the condition requiring that the evaluation of two streams with the same present well-being not depend on what that level of well-being is), the stationarity postulate is equivalent to the following independence condition (where we borrow the name that Fleurbaey and Michel (2003) use for a slightly stronger version of this condition).

Condition IF (Independent Future) For all \(_0\mathbf {x}\), \(_0\mathbf {y} \in \mathbf {X}\) with \(x_0 = y_0\), \(_0\mathbf {x} \, \succsim \, _0\mathbf {y}\) if and only if \(_1\mathbf {x} \, \succsim \, _1\mathbf {y}\).

Condition IF means that an evaluation concerning only generations from the next period on can be made as if the present time (time 0) was actually at time 1; i.e., as if generations \(\{0,1, \dots \}\) would have taken the place of generations \(\{1,2, \dots \}\). If we extended our framework to also include comparisons at future times, then IF would imply time consistency as long as the swr is time invariant.

With the well-being of each generation t expressed by a one-dimensional indicator \(x_t\), it is uncontroversial to ensure through the following condition that a higher value of \(x_t\) cannot lead to a socially less preferred stream.

Condition M (Monotonicity) For all \(_0\mathbf {x}\), \(_0\mathbf {y} \in \mathbf {X}\), if \(_0\mathbf {x} \, > \, _0\mathbf {y}\), then \(_0\mathbf {y} \, \nsucc \, _0\mathbf {x}\).

Combined with the completeness part of condition O, it follows from condition M that, for all \(_0\mathbf {x}\), \(_0\mathbf {y} \in \mathbf {X}\), if \(_0\mathbf {x} \, \ge \, _0\mathbf {y}\), then \(_0\mathbf {x} \, \succsim \, _0\mathbf {y}\). Condition M is obviously implied by the “Strong Pareto” condition.

Condition SP (Strong Pareto) For all \(_0\mathbf {x}\), \(_0\mathbf {y} \in \mathbf {X}\), if \(_0\mathbf {x} \, > \, _0\mathbf {y}\), then \(_0\mathbf {x} \, \succ \, _0\mathbf {y}\).

With condition M we need not impose Koopmans (1960) extreme streams postulate (Postulate 5) and can consider the set of infinite streams bounded in well-being.

As the fifth and final condition of our basic representation result (Proposition 2), we impose the following efficiency condition.

Condition RD (Restricted Dominance) For all x, \(z \in Y\), if \(x < z\), then \((x,\,_{\text {con}}z) \, \prec \, _{\text {con}}z\).

To evaluate the implications of RD, consider the following three conditions.

Condition WS (Weak Sensitivity) There exist \(_0\mathbf {x}\), \(_0\mathbf {y}\), \(_0\mathbf {z} \in \mathbf X \) such that \((x_0,\,_1\mathbf {z}) \, \succ \, (y_0,\,_1\mathbf {z})\).

Condition DF (Dictatorship of the Future) For all \(_0\mathbf {x}\), \(_0\mathbf {y} \in \mathbf {X}\) such that \(_0\mathbf {x} \, \succ \, _0\mathbf {y}\), there exist , \(\bar{y} \in Y\), with for all \(t\in \mathbb {Z}_+\), and \(T' \in \mathbb {Z}_+\) such that, for every \(_0\mathbf {z}\), , \((_0\mathbf {z}_{T-1},\,_T\mathbf {x}) \, \succ \, (_0\mathbf {v}_{T-1},\,_T\mathbf {y})\) for all \(T > T'\).

Condition NDF (No Dictatorship of the Future) Condition DF does not hold.

Condition SP implies condition RD, which in turn implies condition WS. Condition WS coincides with Koopmans (1960) Postulate 2. Condition NDF generalizes one of Chichilnisky’s (1996) two main axioms to our setting where we consider the set of infinite streams bounded in well-being.

Proposition 1

Assume that the swr \(\succsim \) satisfies conditions O and IF. Then WS is equivalent to NDF.

As already noted at the end of the introduction, the proof of this and later results are provided in an appendix.

Since RD strengthens WS, it follows from Proposition 1 that RD ensures “No Dictatorship of the Future”, provided that the swr satisfies conditions O and IF. To appreciate why we cannot replace RD with an even stronger efficiency condition, we refer to the analysis of Sect. 3 and the impossibility result of Proposition 4.

To state Proposition 2, we introduce the following notation:

$$\begin{aligned} \mathcal {U} :=&\, \{U: Y \rightarrow \mathbb {R} \mid U \, \text {is continuous and non-decreasing;} \\&\qquad \qquad \qquad U(Y)\text { is not a singleton}\} \\ \mathcal {U}_I :=&\, \{U: Y \rightarrow \mathbb {R} \mid U \, \text {is continuous and increasing}\} \\ \mathcal {V}(U) :=&\, \{V: U(Y)^2 \rightarrow \mathbb {R} \mid V \, \text {satisfies (V.0), (V.1), (V.2), and (V.3)} \} \, , \end{aligned}$$

where, for all \(U \in \mathcal {U}\), U(Y) denotes the range of U, and the properties of the aggregator function V, (V.0)–(V.3), are as follows:

  1. (V.0)

    V(uw) is continuous in (uw) on \(U(Y)^2\).

  2. (V.1)

    V(uw) is non-decreasing in u for given w.

  3. (V.2)

    V(uw) is increasing in w for given u.

  4. (V.3)

    \(V(u, w) < w\) for \(u < w\), and \(V(u, w) = w\) for \(u = w\).

Proposition 2

The following two statements are equivalent.

  1. (1)

    The swr \(\succsim \) satisfies conditions O, RC, IF, M, and RD.

  2. (2)

    There exists a monotone swf \(W: \mathbf {X} \rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) representing \(\succsim \) and satisfying, for some \(U \in \mathcal {U}_I\) and \(V \in \mathcal {V}(U)\), \(W(_0 \mathbf {x}) = V(U(x_0),W(_1 \mathbf {x}))\) for all \(_0 \mathbf {x} \in \mathbf {X}\) and \(W(_\mathrm {con}z) = U(z)\) for all \(z \in Y\).

For a given representation W (with associated utility function U) of an swr satisfying conditions O, RC, IF, M, and RD, we refer to \(U(x_t)\) as the utility of generation t and \(W(_0 \mathbf {x})\) as the welfare derived from the infinite stream \(_0 \mathbf {x}\).

3 Hammond Equity for the Future

Discounted utilitarianism satisfies conditions O, RC, IF, M, and RD. Hence, these conditions do not by themselves prevent “Dictatorship of the Present”, in the terminology of Chichilnisky’s (1996).

Condition DP (Dictatorship of the Present) For all \(_0\mathbf {x}\), \(_0\mathbf {y} \in \mathbf {X}\) such that \(_0\mathbf {x} \, \succ \, _0\mathbf {y}\), there exist , \(\bar{y} \in Y\), with for all \(t \in \mathbb {Z}_+\), and \(T' \in \mathbb {Z}_+\) such that, for any \(_0\mathbf {z}\), , \((_0\mathbf {x}_{T-1},\,_T\mathbf {z}) \, \succ \, (_0\mathbf {y}_{T-1},\,_T\mathbf {v})\) for all \(T > T'\).

Condition NDP (No Dictatorship of the Present) Condition DP does not hold.

Condition NDP generalizes the other of Chichilnisky’s (1996)’s two main axioms to our setting where we consider the set of infinite streams bounded in well-being.

We impose a weak new equity condition that ensures NDP. Combined with RC, this condition entails that the interest of the present are taken into account only if the present is worse-off than the future. Consider a stream \((x,\, _{\text {con}} z)\) having the property that well-being is constant from the second period on. For such a stream we may unequivocally say that, if \(x < z\), then the present is worse- off than the future. Likewise, if \(x > z\), then the present is better-off than the future.

Condition HEF (Hammond Equity for the Future) For all x, y, z, \(v \in Y\), if \(x> y> v > z\), then \((x,\, _{\text {con}} z) \, \nsucc \, (y,\, _{\text {con}} v)\).Footnote 6

For streams where well-being is constant from the second period on, condition HEF captures the idea of giving priority to an infinite number of future generations in the choice between alternatives where the future is worse-off compared to the present in both alternatives. If the present is better-off than the future and a sacrifice now leads to a uniform gain for all future generations, then such a transfer from the present to the future cannot lead to a less desirable stream, as long as the present remains better-off than the future.

To appreciate the weakness of condition HEF, consider weak versions of the standard “Hammond Equity” condition (Hammond 1976) and Lauwers (1998) non-substitution condition.

Condition WHE (Weak Hammond Equity) For all \(_0\mathbf {x}\), \(_0\mathbf {y} \in \mathbf {X}\), if \(_0 \mathbf {x}\) and \(_0 \mathbf {y}\) satisfy that there exists a pair \(\tau '\), \(\tau ''\) such that \(x_{\tau '}> y_{\tau '}> y_{\tau ''} > x_{\tau ''}\) and \(x_t = y_t\) for all \(t \ne \tau '\), \(\tau ''\), then \(_0 \mathbf {x} \, \nsucc \, _0 \mathbf {y}\).Footnote 7

Condition WNS (Weak Non-Substitution) For all x, y, z, \(v \in Y\), if \(v > z\), then \((x,\, _{\text {con}} z) \, \nsucc \, (y,\, _{\text {con}} v)\).

By assuming, in addition, that well-beings are at least cardinally measurable and fully comparable, we may also consider weak versions of the Lorenz Domination and Pigou-Dalton principles. Such equity conditions have been used in the setting of infinite streams by, e.g., Birchenhall and Grout (1979), Asheim (1991), Fleurbaey and Michel (2001), and Hara et al. (2008).

Condition WLD (Weak Lorenz Domination) For all \(_0\mathbf {x}\), \(_0\mathbf {y} \in \mathbf {X}\), if \(_0 \mathbf {x}\) and \(_0 \mathbf {y}\) are such that \(_0 \mathbf {y}_{T-1}\) weakly Lorenz dominates \(_0 \mathbf {x}_{T-1}\) and \(_T \mathbf {x} \, = \, _T \mathbf {y}\) for some \(T > 1\), then \(_0 \mathbf {x} \, \nsucc \, _0 \mathbf {y}\).Footnote 8

Condition WPD (Weak Pigou-Dalton) For all \(_0\mathbf {x}\), \(_0\mathbf {y} \in \mathbf {X}\), if \(_0 \mathbf {x}\) and \(_0 \mathbf {y}\) are such that there exist a positive number \(\epsilon \) and a pair \(\tau '\), \(\tau ''\) satisfying \(x_{\tau '} - \epsilon = y_{\tau '} \ge y_{\tau ''} = x_{\tau ''} + \epsilon \) and \(x_t = y_t\) for all \(t \ne \tau '\), \(\tau ''\), then \(_0 \mathbf {x} \, \nsucc \, _0 \mathbf {y}\).

While it is clear that condition HEF is implied by WNS, it is perhaps less obvious that, under O and M, HEF is at least as weak as each of WHE, WPD, and WLD.

Proposition 3

Assume that the swr \(\succsim \) satisfies conditions O and M. Then each of WHE, WPD, and WLD implies HEF.

Note that condition HEF involves a comparison between a sacrifice by a single generation and a uniform gain for each member of an infinite set of generations that are worse-off. Hence, contrary to the standard “Hammond Equity” condition, if well-beings are made (at least) cardinally measurable and fully comparable, then the transfer from the better-off present to the worse-off future specified in condition HEF increases the sum of well-beings for a sufficiently large number T of generations. This entails that condition HEF is implied by both WPD and WLD, independently of what specific cardinal scale of well-beings is imposed (provided that conditions O and M are satisfied). Hence, “Hammond Equity for the Future” can be endorsed from both an egalitarian and utilitarian point of view. In particular, condition HEF is weaker and more compelling than the standard “Hammond Equity” condition.

However, in line with the Diamond-Yaari impossibility result (Diamond 1965) on the inconsistency of equity and efficiency conditions under continuity,Footnote 9 the equity condition HEF is in conflict with the following weak efficiency condition under RC.

Condition RS (Restricted Sensitivity) There exist x, \(z \in Y\) with \(x > z\) such that \((x,\,_{\text {con}}z) \, \succ \, _{\text {con}}z\).

Condition SP implies condition RS, which in turn implies condition WS.

Proposition 4

There is no swr \(\succsim \) satisfying conditions RC, RS, and HEF.

Impossibility results arising from HEF are further explored in Asheim et al. (2007). Here we concentrate on swrs that satisfy HEF. We note that it follows from Proposition 4 that RD is the strongest efficiency condition compatible with HEF under RC, when comparing streams \((x,\, _{\text {con}} z)\) where well-being is constant from the second period on with constant streams \(_{\text {con}} z\).

The following result establishes that “Dictatorship of the Present” is indeed ruled out by adding condition HEF to conditions O, RC, IF, and M.

Proposition 5

Assume that the swr \(\succsim \) satisfies conditions O, RC, IF, and M. Then HEF implies NDP.

How does the basic representation result of Proposition 2 change if we also impose condition HEF on an swr \(\succsim \) satisfying conditions O, RC, IF, M, and RD? To investigate this question, introduce the following notation:

$$\begin{aligned} \mathcal {V}_{S}(U) := \{V: U(Y)^2 \rightarrow \mathbb {R} \mid V \, \text {satisfies (V.0), (V.1), (V.2), and (V.3')} \} \, , \end{aligned}$$

where (V.3\('\)) is given as follows:

(V.3\('\)):

\(V(u, w) < w\) for \(u < w\), and \(V(u, w) = w\) for \(u \ge w\).

Note that, for each \(U \in \mathcal {U}\), \(\mathcal {V}_{S}(U) \subseteq \mathcal {V}(U)\).

Proposition 6

The following two statements are equivalent.

  1. (1)

    The swr \(\succsim \) satisfies conditions O, RC, IF, M, RD, and HEF.

  2. (2)

    There exists a monotone swf \(W: \mathbf {X} \rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) representing \(\succsim \) and satisfying, for some \(U \in \mathcal {U}_I\) and \(V \in \mathcal {V}_{S}(U)\), \(W(_0 \mathbf {x}) = V(U(x_0),W(_1 \mathbf {x}))\) for all \(_0 \mathbf {x} \in \mathbf {X}\) and \(W(_\mathrm {con}z) = U(z)\) for all \(z \in Y\).

We refer to a mapping satisfying the property presented in statement (2) of Proposition 6 as a sustainable recursive swf. Proposition 6 does not address the question whether there exists a sustainable recursive swf for any \(U \in \mathcal {U}_I\) and \(V \in \mathcal {V}_{S}(U)\). This question of existence is resolved through the following proposition, which also characterizes the asymptotic properties of such social welfare functions.

Proposition 7

For all \(U \in \mathcal {U}_I\) and \(V \in \mathcal {V}_{S}(U)\), there exists a monotone mapping \(W: \mathbf {X} \rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) satisfying \(W(_0 \mathbf {x}) = V(U(x_0),W(_1 \mathbf {x}))\) for all \(_0 \mathbf {x} \in \mathbf {X}\) and \(W(_\text {con}z) = U(z)\) for all \(z \in Y\). Any such mapping W satisfies, for each \(_0 \mathbf {x} \in \mathbf {X}\),

$${\lim }_{T \rightarrow \infty }W(_T \mathbf {x}) = {\lim \inf }_{t \rightarrow \infty } U(x_t) \, .$$

By combining Propositions 6 and 7 we obtain our first main result.

Theorem 1

There exists a class of swrs \(\succsim \) satisfying conditions O, RC, IF, M, RD, and HEF.

The proof of the existence part of Proposition 7 is based on an algorithmic construction. For any \(_0 \mathbf {x} \in \mathbf {X}\) and each \(T \in \mathbb {Z}_+\), consider the following finite sequence:

$$\begin{aligned} \left. \begin{array}{l} w(T,T) = \lim \inf _{t \rightarrow \infty } U(x_t) \\ w(T-1,T) = V(U(x_{T-1}), w(T,T)) \\ \cdots \\ w(0,T) = V(U(x_0), w(1,T)) \end{array} \right\} \end{aligned}$$
(1)

Define the mapping \(W_{\sigma }: \mathbf {X} \rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) by

$$\begin{aligned} W_{\sigma }(_0 \mathbf {x}) := {\lim }_{T \rightarrow \infty }w(0,T) \, . \end{aligned}$$
(W)

In the proof of Proposition 7 we show that \(W_{\sigma }\) is a sustainable recursive swf.

It is an open question whether \(W_{\sigma }\) is the unique sustainable recursive swf given \(U \in \mathcal {U}_I\) and \(V \in \mathcal {V}_{S}(U)\). As reported in the following proposition, we can show uniqueness if the aggregator function satisfies a condition introduced by [Koopmans et al. 1964, p. 88]: \(V \in \mathcal {V}(U)\) satisfies the property of weak time perspective if there exists a continuous increasing transformation \(g : \mathbb {R} \rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) such that \(g(w) - g(V(u,w))\) is a non-decreasing function of w for given u.

Proposition 8

Let \(U \in \mathcal {U}_I\) and \(V \in \mathcal {V}_{S}(U)\). If V satisfies the property of weak time perspective, then there exists a unique monotone mapping \(W: \mathbf {X} \rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) satisfying \(W(_0 \mathbf {x}) = V(U(x_0),W(_1 \mathbf {x}))\) for all \(_0 \mathbf {x} \in \mathbf {X}\) and \(W(_\text {con}z) = U(z)\) for all \(z \in Y\). This mapping, \(W_{\sigma }\), is defined by (W).

We have not been able to establish that the property of weak time perspective follows from the conditions we have imposed. However, it is satisfied in special cases; e.g., with V given by

$$\begin{aligned} \quad V(u,w) \; = {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} \; \; (1 - \delta ) u + \delta w \quad &{}\text {if} \;\; u < w \\ \; \; w \quad &{}\text {if} \;\; u \ge w \, , \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$
(2)

where \(\delta \in (0,1)\).Footnote 10 We can also show that the set of supnorm continuous sustainable recursive swfs contains at most \(W_{\sigma }\). However, even though \(W_{\sigma }\) is continuous in the weak sense implied by condition RC, it need not be supnorm continuous.

Once we drop one of the conditions RC, IF, and RD, and combine the remaining two conditions with O, M, and HEF, new possibilities open up. It is clear that:

  • The mapping \(W: \mathbf {X} \rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) defined by \(W(_0 \mathbf {x}) := {\lim \inf }_{t \rightarrow \infty } U(x_t)\) for some \(U \in \mathcal {U}_I\) represents an swr satisfying O, RC, IF, M, and HEF, but not RD.

  • The maximin swr satisfies O, RC, M, RD, and HEF, but not IF.

  • Leximin and undiscounted utilitarian swrs for infinite streams satisfy O, IF, M, RD, and HEF, but not RC (cf. Proposition 13).

It follows from Propositions 1, 5, and 6 that any sustainable recursive swf represents an swr satisfying NDF and NDP. [Chichilnisky’s 1996, Definition 6] defines “sustainable preferences” by imposing NDF and NDP as well as numerical representability and SP. When showing existence in her Theorem 1, she considers swrs violating condition IF. Hence, through showing general existence for our sustainable recursive swf, we demonstrate that NDF and NDP can be combined with (a) numerical representability, (b) condition IF which implies stationarity, and (c) sensitivity to present well-being—and thus be imposed within the Koopmans (1960) framework—provided that SP is replaced by weaker dominance conditions.Footnote 11

4 Independent Present

The following condition is invoked as Postulate \(3'\)a in Koopmans (1960)’ characterization of discounted utilitarianism.

Condition IP (Independent Present) For all \(_0\mathbf {x}\), \(_0\mathbf {y}\), \(_0\mathbf {z}\), \(_0\mathbf {v} \in \mathbf {X}\), \((x_0,\,x_1,\,_2\mathbf {z}) \, \succsim (y_0,\,y_1,\,_2\mathbf {z})\) if and only if \((x_0,\,x_1,\,_2\mathbf {v}) \, \succsim \, (y_0,\,y_1,\,_2\mathbf {v})\).

Condition IP requires that the evaluation of two streams differing only in the first two periods not depend on what the common continuation stream is. We suggest in this section that this condition may not be compelling, both through appeal to ethical intuition, and through formal results.

We suggest that it might be supported by ethical intuition to accept that the stream \((1,4,5,5,5,\ldots )\) is socially better than \((2,2,5,5,5,\ldots )\), while not accepting that \((1,4,2,2,2,\ldots )\) is socially better than \((2,2,2,2,2,\ldots )\). It is not obvious that we should treat the conflict between the worst-off and the second worst-off generation presented by the first comparison in the same manner as we treat the conflict between the worst-off and the best-off generation put forward by the second comparison.

Turn now to the formal results. Koopmans (1960) characterizes discounted utilitarianism by means of conditions IF, WS, and IP. However, it turns out that conditions IF, WS, and IP contradict HEF under RC and M. Furthermore, this conclusion is tight, in the sense that an swr exists if any one of these conditions is dropped. This is our second main result.

Theorem 2

There is no swr \(\succsim \) satisfying conditions RC, IF, M, WS, HEF, and IP. If one of the conditions RC, IF, M, WS, HEF, and IP is dropped, then there exists an swr \(\succsim \) satisfying the remaining five conditions as well as condition O.

In the following proposition, we reproduce Koopmans (1960) characterization of discounted utilitarianism within the formal setting of this paper.Footnote 12

Proposition 9

The following two statements are equivalent.

  1. (1)

    The swr \(\succsim \) satisfies conditions O, RC, IF, M, WS, and IP.

  2. (2)

    There exists a monotone swf \(W: \mathbf {X} \rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) representing \(\succsim \) and satisfying, for some \(U \in \mathcal {U}\) and \(\delta \in (0,1)\), \(W(_0 \mathbf {x}) = (1-\delta )U(x_0) + \delta W(_1 \mathbf {x})\) for all \(_0 \mathbf {x} \in \mathbf {X}\).

Strengthening WS to RD in statement (1) is equivalent to replacing \(\mathcal {U}\) by \(\mathcal {U}_I\) in statement (2).

This proposition follows from standard results for additively separable representations (Debreu 1960; Gorman 1968a; Koopmans 1986a), by exploiting the overlap of periods that conditions IF and IP give rise to (cf. Lemma 3).

Furthermore, we note that the discounted utilitarian swf exists and is unique.

Proposition 10

For all \(U \in \mathcal {U}\) and \(\delta \in (0,1)\), there exists a unique monotone mapping \(W: \mathbf {X} \rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) satisfying \(W(_0 \mathbf {x}) = (1-\delta )U(x_0) + \delta W(_1 \mathbf {x})\) for all \(_0 \mathbf {x} \in \mathbf {X}\). This mapping, \(W_{\delta }\), is defined by, for each \(_0 \mathbf {x} \in \mathbf {X}\),

$$W_{\delta }(_0 \mathbf {x}) = (1-\delta )\sum \limits _{t=0}^{\infty } \delta ^t U(x_t) \, .$$

Propositions 9 and 10 have the following implication.

Proposition 11

There is no swr \(\succsim \) satisfying conditions O, RC, IF, M, IP, NDP, and NDF.

To summarize, it follows from Theorem 2 and Propositions 1 and 11 that, within a Koopmans framework where O, RC, IF, M, and WS are imposed, condition IP contradicts both HEF and NDP. Hence, in such a framework, IP is in conflict with consequentialist equity conditions that respect the interests of future generations.

5 Applying Sustainable Recursive SWFs

We apply sustainable recursive swfs for studying optimal harvesting of a renewable resource where, following Krautkraemer (1985), well-being may be derived directly from the resource stock. Using discounted utilitarianism in this setting reduces the resource stock below the green golden-rule (defined below) and leads to resource deterioration for sufficiently high discounting (Heal 1998).

Maximizing sustainable recursive swfs leads to very different conclusions, as reported in Proposition 12. Before stating this result, we introduce the model.

The law of motion governing the bio-mass of the renewable resource, k, is given by a standard increasing, concave stock-recruitment function, f, and therefore the production framework is formally the same as the standard neoclassical aggregate model of economic growth. The function \(f:\mathbb {R} _{+}\rightarrow \mathbb {R}_{+}\) is assumed to satisfy:

  1. (i)

    \(f(0)=0\),

  2. (ii)

    f is continuous, increasing and strictly concave on \(\mathbb {R}_{+}\)

  3. (iii)

    \(\lim _{k\rightarrow 0}\tfrac{f(k)}{k}>1\) and \(\lim _{k\rightarrow \infty }\tfrac{f(k)}{k}<1\).

It can be shown that there exists a unique number \(\bar{k} > 0\) such that \(f(\bar{k}) = \bar{k}\) and \(f(k) > k\) for \(k \in (0, \bar{k})\).

A feasible path from \(k \in [0,\bar{k}]\) is a sequence of resource stocks \(_0 \mathbf {k}\) satisfying:

$$k_0 = k \, , \quad 0 \le k_{t+1} \le f(k_t) \; \text { for } t > 0 \, .$$

It follows from the definition of \(\bar{k}\) that \(k_t \in [0,\bar{k}]\) for \(t > 0\). Hence, \(\bar{k}\) is the maximal attainable resource stock if one starts from an initial stock in \([0,\bar{k}]\). Associated with a feasible path \(_0 \mathbf {k}\) from \(k \in [0,\bar{k}]\) is a consumption stream \(_0 \mathbf {c}\), defined by

$$c_t = f(k_t) - k_{t+1} \; \text { for } t \ge 0 \, .$$

Well-being, x, depends on consumption and resource amenities through a function \(x : [0, \bar{k}]^2 \rightarrow \mathbb {R}\), which is assumed to satisfy:

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{l} \text {(i)}\;x \text { is continuous and quasi-concave on } [0, \bar{k}]^2, \\ \text {(ii)}\;x \text { is non-decreasing in }(c,k),\text { and increasing in }c\; \text {(when }k>0\text {).} \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
(3)

The set of of admissible well-beings is given by \(Y := [x(0,0), x(\bar{k},\bar{k})]\). Associated with a feasible path \(_0 \mathbf {k}\) from \(k \in [0,\bar{k}]\) is a well-being stream \(_0 \mathbf {x}\), defined by

$$x_t = x(f(k_t) - k_{t+1},k_t) \; \text { for } t \ge 0 \, .$$

For any \(k \in [0,\bar{k}]\), the set of well-being streams associated with feasible resource paths from k is contained in \(\mathbf {X} = Y^{\mathbb {Z}_+}\).

It follows from the continuity and strict concavity of f and the continuity and quasi-concavity of x, combined with property (3)(ii), that there exists a unique number \(k^{*} \in [0, \bar{k}]\) such that \(x(f(k^{*}) - k^{*}, k^{*}) \ge x(f(k) - k, k)\) for all \(k \in [0,\bar{k}]\). Since, for any \(k \in (0, \bar{k})\), \(x(f(k)-k,k) > x(f(0)-0,0)=x(0,0)\), we have that \(k^{*} > 0\). Clearly, an additional assumption can be imposed to ensure the existence of \(k \in (0, \bar{k})\) such that \(x(f(k)-k,k) > x(f(\bar{k})-\bar{k},\bar{k})=x(0,\bar{k})\), so that \(k^{*} < \bar{k}\). The subsequent analysis holds with (and without) any such assumption.

We write \(c^{*} := f(k^{*}) - k^{*}\) and \(x^{*} := x(c^{*}, k^{*})\). By keeping the resource stock constant at \(k^{*}\), a maximum sustainable well-being equal to \(x^{*}\) is attained; this corresponds to the green golden-rule (Chichilnisky et al. 1995). The following result shows that if \(k \in [k^{*}, \bar{k}]\) and a sustainable recursive swf is maximized, then welfare corresponds to the green golden-rule, and the resource stock never falls below the green golden-rule level.

Proposition 12

Assume that an economy maximizes a sustainable recursive swf \(W: \mathbf {X} \rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) on the set of well-being streams associated with feasible resource paths from \(k \in [k^{*}, \bar{k}]\). Then an optimum exists, and for any optimal resource path \(_0 \hat{\mathbf {k}}\), with associated well-being stream \(_0 \hat{\mathbf {x}}\),

$$W(_t \hat{\mathbf {x}}) = W(_{\mathrm{con}}x^{*}) , \;\; \hat{x}_t \ge x^{*} \, , \;\; \text {and} \;\; \hat{k}_t \ge k^{*} \; \text {for} \; t \ge 0 \, .$$

Hence, in contrast to the existence problem encountered when Chichilnisky’s (1996) “sustainable preferences” are applied to such a setting (see Figuieres and Tidball 2016 where this problem motivates an interesting analysis), optima exist when sustainable recursive swfs are used to evaluate streams (at least, for \(k \in [k^{*}, \bar{k}]\)). Moreover, in contrast to the outcome under discounted utilitarianism, sustainable recursive swfs sustain well-being at or above its maximum sustainable level, by sustaining the resource stock at or above the green golden-rule level.

In a companion paper (Asheim and Mitra 2010) it is demonstrated how sustainable recursive swfs can be used to resolve in an appealing way the interesting distributional conflicts that arise in the DHS model of capital accumulation and resource depletion. In particular, applying sustainable recursive swfs in this setting leads to growth and development at first when capital is productive, while protecting the generations in the distant future from the grave consequences of discounting when the vanishing resource stock undermines capital productivity.

6 Concluding Remarks

Koopmans (1960) has often been interpreted as presenting the definitive case for discounted utilitarianism. In Sects. 2 and 3 we have sought to weaken this impression by exploring other avenues within the general setting of his approach. In particular, by not imposing condition IP, used by Koopmans (1960) to characterize discounted utilitarianism, we have been able to combine our new equity condition HEF with the essential features of the Koopmans (1960) framework: (a) numerical representability, (b) sensitivity to the interests of the present generation, and (c) condition IF which includes Koopmans (1960)’ stationarity postulate. This leads to a non-empty class of sustainable recursive social welfare functions. We have argued that condition HEF is weak, as it is implied by all the standard consequentialist equity conditions suggested in the literature, yet strong enough to ensure that the Chichilnisky’s (1996) conditions are satisfied. As we have discussed in Sect. 5, sustainable recursive social welfare functions are applicable and yield consequences that differ from those of discounted utilitarianism.

In this final section we note that even wider possibilities open up if we are willing to give up numerical representability by not imposing RC. In particular, we are then able to combine the equity condition HEF and the independence condition IP with our basic conditions O and IF, while strengthening our efficiency conditions M and RD to condition SP.

Proposition 13

There exists an swr \(\succsim \) satisfying conditions O, IF, SP, HEF, and IP.

The proof of this proposition employs the leximin and undiscounted utilitarian swrs for infinite streams that have been axiomatized in recent contributions (see, Asheim and Tungodden 2004a; Basu and Mitra 2007; Bossert et al. 2007).

We end by making the observation that continuity is not simply a “technical” condition without ethical content. In a setting where RC (or a stronger continuity condition like C) is combined with RS (or a stronger efficiency condition like SP), it follows from Proposition 4 that condition HEF is not satisfied. Hence, on this basis one may claim that, in combination with a sufficiently strong efficiency condition, continuity rules out swfs that protect the interests of future generations by implying that the equity condition HEF does not hold. In the main analysis of this paper we have avoided the trade-off between continuity and numerical representability on the one hand, and the ability to impose the equity condition HEF on the other hand, by weakening the efficiency condition in an appropriate way.