Skip to main content

Towards a Eudaimonistic Virtue Epistemology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Virtue Epistemology Naturalized

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 366))

Abstract

This chapter is about the science of vision and memory in relation to virtue epistemology. My argument will turn on the point that the mechanisms underlying vision and knowledge that, according to current neuroscience, remain non-conscious can’t be considered virtuous mechanisms even if they are highly reliable. Hence, I argue, virtue epistemology cannot count these obvious forms of knowledge as true forms of knowledge. Virtue epistemology thus is at best a partial theory of knowledge.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Sosa’s approach can also be considered a mixed approach. Sosa distinguishes between animal knowledge and reflective knowledge. Animal knowledge requires the exercise of reliable cognitive faculties or abilities, whereas reflective knowledge requires a more active, or reflective, second-order stance (see e.g. Sosa 2007). Since Sosa does not require responsibility as a condition on knowledge, I shall here treat his approach as a kind of virtue reliabilism.

  2. 2.

    Others have expressed similar misgivings about virtue responsibilism. See e.g. Mark Alfano (Forthcoming). Alfano’s focus is on showing that none of us possesses virtuous character traits, except in particular situations, whereas I am content with showing that even clearly non-virtuous agents possess knowledge. I will not be dealing explicitly with Alfano’s critique, as I had already completed this paper when I became familiar with his. Thanks to Abrol Fairweather for drawing my attention to it.

  3. 3.

    http://csc.lexum.umontreal.ca/en/1992/1992scr2-871/1992scr2-871.html

  4. 4.

    This example is adapted from Brogaard and Smith (2005).

References

  • Alfano, M. Forthcoming. Expanding the situationist challenge to respinsibilist virtue epistemology. Philosophical Quarterly.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ariely, D. 2008. Predictably irrational: The hidden forces that shape our decisions. New York: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Axtell, G. 1997. Recent work in virtue epistemology. American Philosophical Quarterly 34: 410–430.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baehr, J. 2006. Character, reliability and virtue epistemology. The Philosophical Quarterly 56(223): 193–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baehr, J. 2011. The inquiring mind: On intellectual virtues and virtue epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, et al. http://www.yale.edu/acmelab/articles/bargh_chen_burrows_1996.pdf.

  • Barlow, D.H., and V.M. Durand. 2008. Abnormal psychology: An integrative approach. Belmont: Cengage Learning.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bor, D., J. Billington, and S. Baron-Cohen. 2007. Memory for digits in a case of synaesthesia and Asperger syndrome is related to hyperactivity in the lateral prefrontal cortex. Neurocase 13: 311–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, S., J. Boakes, D. Glaser, R. Green, J. MacKeith, and P. Whewell. 1997. Reported recovered memories of child sexual abuse: Recommendations for good practice and implications for training, continuing professional development and research. Psychiatric Bulletin 21(10): 663–665.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. 2005. I know. Therefore, I understand. Unpublished manuscript. Available at: https://sites.google.com/site/brogaardb/.

  • Brogaard, B. 2006. Can virtue reliabilism explain the value of knowledge? Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36: 335–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. 2011a. Intellectual flourishing as the fundamental epistemic norm, University. In J. Turri and Clayton Littlejohn. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. 2011b. Knowledge-how: A unified account. In Knowing how: Essays on knowledge, mind, and action, ed. J. Bengson and M. Moffett. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B., and B. Smith. 2005. On luck, responsibility, and the meaning of life. Philosophical Papers 34: 443–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castiello, U., and M. Jeannerod. 1991. Measuring time to awareness. Neuroreport 2: 797–800.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castiello, U., Y. Paulignan, and M. Jeannerod. 1991. Temporal dissociation of motor responses and subjective awareness. A study in normal subjects. Brain 114: 2639–2655.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., and D.J. Chalmers. 1998. The extended mind. Analysis 58: 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Code, L. 1984. Toward a ‘responsibilist’ epistemology. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 45(1): 29–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S. 1999. The number sense. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S. 2001. Précis of the number sense. Mind & Language 16: 16–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S. 2007. Symbols and quantities in parietal cortex: Elements of a mathematical theory of number representation and manipulation”. In. Sensorimotor foundations of higher cognition, volume XXII of Attention and Performance, chapter 24 (ed.) Patrick Haggard, Yves Rossetti, and Mitsuo Kawato, 527–574. Oxford: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S., G. Dehaene-Lambertz, and L. Cohen. 1998. Abstract representations of numbers in the animal and human brain. Trends in Neuroscience 21: 355–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S., N. Molko, L. Cohen, and A. Wilson. 2004. Arithmetic and the brain. Current Opinion in Neurobiology 14: 218–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. 2011. A natural history of the self. forthcoming.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eger, E., V. Michel, B. Thirion, A. Amadon, S. Dehaene, and A. Kleinschmidt. 2009. Deciphering cortical number coding from human brain activity patterns. Current Biology 19: 1608–1615.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M.A., and A.D. Milner. 1992. Separate visual pathways for perception and action. Trends in Neurosciences 15: 20–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M.A., D. Pelisson, and C. Prablanc. 1986. Large adjustments in visually guided reaching do not depend on vision of the hand or perception of target displacement. Nature 320: 748–750.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. 2000. Putting skeptics in their place. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. 2003. Knowledge as credit for true belief. In Intellectual virtue: Perspectives from ethics and epistemology, ed. M. DePaul and L. Zagzebski. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. 2007. The nature of ability and the purpose of knowledge. Philosophical Issues 17: 57–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greco, John, and John Turri. 2011. Virtue epistemology The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/epistemology-virtue/

  • Hubbard, E.M., M. Piazza, P. Pinel, Dehaene S. Numerical, and Spatial Intuitions. 2009. A role for posterior parietal cortex? In Cognitive biology: Evolutionary and developmental perspectives on mind, brain and behavior, ed. L. Tommasi, L. Nadel, and M.A. Peterson, 221–246. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jakobson, L.S., and M.A. Goodale. 1989. Trajectories of reaches to prismatically-displaced targets: Evidence for ‘automatic’ visuomotor recalibration. Experimental Brain Research 78: 575–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johansson, P., L. Hall, S. Sikström, and A. Olsson. 2005. Failure to detect mismatches between intention and outcome in a simple decision task. Science 310: 116–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johansson, P., L. Hall, S. Sikström, B. Tärning, and A. Lind. 2006. How something can be said about telling more than we can know. Consciousness and Cognition 15: 673–692.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karnath, H.-O., S. Ferber, and M. Himmelbach. 2001. Spatial awareness is a function of the temporal not the posterior lobe. Nature 411: 950–953.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelp, C. 2011. In defence of virtue epistemology. Synthese 179: 409–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. 2003. The value of knowledge and the pursuit of understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, J. 2007. Why we don’t deserve credit for everything we know. Synthese 158: 345–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, J. 2009. Knowledge and credit. Philosophical Studies 142: 27–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levin, Michael. 2004. Virtue epistemology: No new cures. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69(2): 397–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lythgoe, M., T. Pollak, M. Kalmas, M. de Hann, and W.K. Chong. 2005. Obsessive, prolific artistic output following subarachnoid hemorrhage. Neurology 64: 397–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marshall, W.L., G. Serran, L.E. Marshall, and Y.M. Fernandez. 2005. Recovering memories of the offense in “amnesic” sexual offenders. Sexual Abuse 17: 31–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milner, A.D., and M.A. Goodale. 2008. Two visual systems re-viewed. Neuropsychologia 46: 774–785.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montmarquet, J. 1996. Epistemic Virtue. Mind 96:384 (1987), pp. 482–497; Epistemic virtue and doxastic responsibility. (Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield, 1993); L. Zagzebski, Virtues of the Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, S.T., and R.B. Zajonc. 1993. Affect, cognition, and awareness: Affective priming with optimal and suboptimal stimulus exposures. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 64: 723–739.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Navarro, C. 2008. Why do some people sleepwalk? Scientific American, 31 Jan 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. 2006. Experience without the head. In Perceptual experience, ed. Tamar S. Gendler and John Hawthorne. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paulignan, Y., C.L. MacKenzie, R.G. Marteniuk, and M. Jeannerod. 1991. Selective perturbation of visual input during prehension movements. 1. The effect of changing object position. Experimental Brain Research 83: 502–512.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peek, F. 1996. The real rain man: Kim Peek. Salt Lake: Harkness.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pelisson, D., C. Prablanc, M.A. Goodale, and M. Jeannerod. 1986. Visual control of reaching movements without vision of the limb. II. Evidence of fast unconscious processes correcting the trajectory of the hand to the final position of a double-step stimulus. Experimental Brain Research 62: 303–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piazza, M., P. Pinel, D. Le Bihan, and S. Dehaene. 2007. “A magnitude code common to numerosities and number symbols in human intraparietal” cortex. Neuron 53: 293–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. 2008. Radical scepticism, epistemic luck and epistemic value. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 82(suppl): 19–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riggs, W. 2002. Reliability and the value of knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64: 79–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sacks, O. 1995. The man who mistook his wife for a hat, and other clinical tales. New York: Summit Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Serran, G.A., and V.L. Marshall. 2005. The “memory recovery technique” a strategy to improve recall of offense-related details in men who commit sexual assaults. Clinical Case Studies 4: 3–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Snyder, A.W., E. Mulcahy, J.L. Taylor, D. Mitchell, P. Sachdev, and S.C. Gandevia. 2003. Savant-like skills exposed in normal people by suppressing the left fronto-temporal lobe. Journal of Integrative Neuroscience 2: 149–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. 2007. A virtue epistemology. Apt belief and reflective knowledge, vol. 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Treffert, D.A. 2009. The savant syndrome: An extraordinary condition. A synopsis: Past, present, future. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 364: 1351–1357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vazire, S. 2010. Who knows what about a person? The self–other knowledge asymmetry (SOKA) model. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 98: 281–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. 2000. Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winkielman, P., and K.C. Berridge. 2004. Unconscious emotion. Current Directions in Psychological Science 13: 120–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wisconsin Medical Society, Islands of Genius. http://www.wisconsinmedicalsociety.org/savant_syndrome/

  • Young, R.L., M.C. Ridding, and T.L. Morrell. 2004. Switching skills by turning off part of the brain. Neurocase 10: 215–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. 1996. Virtues of the mind: An inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. 2003. The search for the source of epistemic good. Metaphilosophy 34: 12–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Berit Brogaard .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Brogaard, B. (2014). Towards a Eudaimonistic Virtue Epistemology. In: Fairweather, A. (eds) Virtue Epistemology Naturalized. Synthese Library, vol 366. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-04672-3_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics