Skip to main content

From Thought Experiments to Real Experiments in Pragmatics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Perspectives on Pragmatics and Philosophy

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 1))

Abstract

The puzzle of thought experiments is a hot topic in the philosophy of science. The chapter raises the puzzle with respect to pragmatics as follows: How is it possible that thought experiments in pragmatics yield new experiential information about communication, although they are carried out entirely in one’s head? The chapter shows, first, that the structure of thought experiments in pragmatics consists of a series of plausible inferences. Second, the function of thought experiments is to serve as the initial step in the process of plausible argumentation as well as to test the plausibility of rival hypotheses. Third, while on the one hand, thought experiments and real experiments may be continuous, on the other hand, the former may be also indispensable components of the latter. Fourth, these properties provide a solution to the puzzle of thought experiments in pragmatics. The key idea of the solution is that thought experiments in pragmatics cannot generate new experiential information; rather, during the process of plausible argumentation they contribute to the retrospective re-evaluation of experiential information already given.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    For state-of-the-art overviews of current approaches to experimental pragmatics see e.g. Breheny (2011), Katsos and Cummins (2010), Noveck and Reboul (2008), Noveck and Sperber (2004a, b), Noveck and Sperber (2007), Németh T. (2006), Sauerland and Yatsushiro (2009), Meibauer and Steinbach (2011), Németh T. and Bibok (2010).

  2. 2.

    For discussion see Brown and Fehige (2010), Rescher (2005), Sorensen (1992), Kühne (2005), Buzzoni (2008), Cohnitz (2006), Brown (1991), Gendler (2000), Cohnitz (2006).

  3. 3.

    “How, […] relying upon familiar data, can thought experiment lead us to new knowledge or to new understanding of nature?” (Kuhn 1977: 241).

  4. 4.

    The terminology in the literature on thought experiments is vague. For example, the terms ‘empirical’ and ‘experiential’ are not defined, and very often they are used interchangeably. Since the definition of ‘empirical’ is highly controversial and we cannot discuss it here, we will use the notion ‘experiential’ in a pre-explicative sense. We will apply this term to pieces of information which are rooted in a person’s ‘experiences’ whatever the latter may be. For example, the results of real experiments or communicative situations in which one has already taken part, count as experiences and statements about such experiences are called ‘experiential’.

  5. 5.

    See Brown (1991), Kuhn (1977), Rescher (1991), (2005), Gendler (2000), Norton (2004a, b), Irvine (1991), Häggquist (1996), Cohnitz (2006), Nersessian (1993), Miščević (1992), Cooper (2005), Gooding (1990), McAllister (1996).

  6. 6.

    We will divide the quotations into smaller units which makes it easier to refer to parts of the quotation to be analysed. The units do not necessarily correspond to paragraphs in the original text.

  7. 7.

    For their precise definitions and numerous applications to different linguistic theories see the work mentioned. A first attempt to apply this approach to thought experiments is Kertész (2010).

  8. 8.

    A well-known example is inductive inferences, in which the set of the explicit premises has to be supplemented by the background assumption that the cases not examined also possess the characteristics that could be found in the investigated ones. The conclusion states the presence of these characteristics as a generalisation.

  9. 9.

    “The sort of ‘self-criticism’ at issue does not reflect any vicious or vitiating circularity, but in effect amounts simply to a feedback process that uses later, more refined stages of the analysis to effect revisionary sophistications in the materials from which earlier stages proceeded. One indeed returns to ‘the same point’ but does so at a different cognitive level” (Rescher 1976: 119; emphasis as in the original).

  10. 10.

    However, we will see later that this impression needs to be refined.

  11. 11.

    Latent background assumptions are set within ‘<’ and ‘>’. Moreover, we accept ‘the weakest link principle’ which says that the conclusion of a plausible inference takes its plausibility value from that of the ‘weakest’ explicit premise or latent background assumption (see e.g. Rescher 1976: XI f., 15, Kertész and Rákosi 2012). We also remark that the expressions ‘it is plausible that’ and ‘it is certain that’ merely indicate a very simplified representation of plausible statements. Kertész and Rákosi (2012) uses numerical scales of plausibility values whose introduction in the present paper would be beside the point.

  12. 12.

    The pattern of both inferences corresponds to that of plausible modus ponens: {it is plausible that if A then B; A is plausible} ⇒ B is plausible.

  13. 13.

    Of course, this applies to our reconstruction of Grice’s argumentation in (6), (7), (9) and (10), too.

  14. 14.

    A detailed analysis of this structure, using the terminology of the framework we proposed above, would transgress the limits of the present paper.

  15. 15.

    For examples supporting this insight in the practice of current pragmatic research see Németh T. (2008), (2010).

  16. 16.

    Here we use the notion of ‘evidence’ pre-explicatively. For its explication within the present metascientific framework, see Kertész and Rákosi (2012).

  17. 17.

    See also Searle (1969: 43–45).

  18. 18.

    Carston (2002a) criticises Levinson’s approach because, according to her, he does not offer an overall solution to Grice’s circle. Rather, he merely assumes that his approach to generalised conversational implicature, which he developed independently of the circularity issue, may soften its harmfulness. Carston also remarks that there are particularised conversational implicatures which influence propositional meaning, while others do not.

  19. 19.

    The issue of the relationship between ‘philosophical’ and ‘scientific’ thought experiments is an important one, but discussing it would transgress the limits of the present paper.

  20. 20.

    See (iv) in Sect. 2.4 for these notions.

  21. 21.

    In fact, it is not the experiment itself, but the experimental report that is to be considered as plausible argumentation. The experimental report is for example part of Noveck and Sperber (2007) and thus the argumentation cycles it consists of are comparable to the argumentation cycles including the thought experiments. In this context we remark that, first, it would be necessary to ask questions with respect to pragmatic experiments in analogy to (P2) and (P3)—that is, what kind of structure they have and what their functions are. However, for lack of space we refer to Kertész and Rákosi (2012) where these questions are raised and partially answered in an extensive case study within the framework of plausible argumentation. Second, the philosophical literature also discusses the fact that every real experiment has to be carried out in thought before it is carried out in reality (see e.g. Buzzoni 2008).

  22. 22.

    Gibbs and Moise (1997) was fiercely criticised in Nicolle and Clark (1999); see also Gibbs (1999) answer.

  23. 23.

    This claim is in accordance, for example, with Gähde (2000) and Rescher (2005).

References

  • Ariel, Mira. 2008. Pragmatics and grammar. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bach, Kent. 1994. Conversational impliciture. Mind and Language 9: 124–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bach, Kent. 1999. The myth of conventional implicature. Linguistics and Philosophy 22: 327–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bach, Kent. 2001. You don’t say? Synthese 128: 15–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bach, Kent. 2007. Regressions in pragmatics (and semantics). In pragmatics, ed. Noël Burton-Roberts, 24–44. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borsley, Robert D ed. 2005. Data in theoretical linguistics. Lingua 115: 1475–1665.

    Google Scholar 

  • Breheny, Richard. 2011. Experimentation-based pragmatics. In Foundations of Pragmatics, eds. Wolfram Bublitz and Neal R. Norrick, 561–586. Berlin and New York: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Breheny, Richard, Napoleon Katsos, and John Williams. 2006. Are generalised scalar implicatures generated by default? An on-line investigation into the role of context in generating pragmatic inferences. Cognition 100: 434–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, James Robert. 1991. The laboratory of the mind: Thought experiments in the natural sciences. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, James Robert, and Yiftach Fehige. 2010. Thought experiments. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/thought-experimen/. Accessed 13 June 2011.

  • Buchanan, Ray. 2010. A puzzle about meaning and communication. Noûs 44: 340–371.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buzzoni, Marco. 2008. Thought experiment in the natural sciences: An operational and reflexive-transcendental conception. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capone, Alessandro. 2006. On Grice’s circle (a theory-internal problem in linguistic theories of the Gricean type). Journal of Pragmatics 38: 645–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, Robyn. 2002a. Linguistic meaning, communicated meaning and cognitive pragmatics. Mind and Language 17: 127–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, Robyn. 2002b. Thoughts and utterances: The pragmatics of explicit communication. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, Robyn. 2004. Truth-conditional content and conversational implicature. In The semantics/pragmatics distinction, ed. Claudia Bianchi, 1–36. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, Herbert H., and Adrian Bangartner. 2004. Changing ideas about reference. In Experimental pragmatics, eds. Ira A. Noveck, and Dan Sperber, 25–49. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohnitz, Daniel. 2006. Gedankenexperimente in der Philosophie. Paderborn: Mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, Rachel. 2005. Thought experiments. Metaphilosophy 36: 328–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Featherston, Sam, and Susanne Winkler eds. 2009. The Fruits of Empirical Linguistics, Vol. 1: Process. Berlin and New York: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gähde, Ulrich. 2000. Gedankenexperimente in Erkenntnistheorie und Physik: strukturelle Parallelen. In Rationalität, Realismus, Revision: Vorträge des 3. internationalen Kongresses der Gesellschaft für Analytische Philosophie vom 15. bis zum 18. Sep 1997 in München, ed. Julian Nida-Rümelin, 457–46. Berlin and New York: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, Tamar Szabó. 1998. Galileo and the indispensability of scientific thought experiment. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49: 397–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, Tamar Szabó. 2000. Thought experiments: On the power and limits of imaginary cases. New York: Garland Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs Jr, Raymond W. 1999. Speaker’s intuitions and pragmatic theory. Cognition 69: 355–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs Jr, Raymond W. 2004. Psycholinguistic experiments and linguistic pragmatics. In Experimental pragmatics, eds. Ira A. Noveck, and Dan Sperber, 50–71. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs Jr, Raymond W., and Jessica F. Moise. 1997. Pragmatics in understanding what is said. Cognition 62: 51–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gooding, D. 1990. Experiment and the making of meaning. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Green, Georgia M. 1996. Pragmatics and natural language understanding. Mahwah: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul. 1989a. Logic and conversation. In Grice 1989d, 22–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul. 1989b. Further notes on logic and conversation. In Grice 1989d, 41–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul 1989c. Meaning. In Grice 1989d, 213–223.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul. 1989d. Studies in the way of words. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guasti, Maria Teresa, Gennaro Chierchia, Stephen Crain, Francesca Foppolo, Andrea Gualmini, and Luisa Meroni. 2005. Why children and adults sometimes (but not always) compute implicatures. Language and cognitive processes 20: 667–696.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Häggquist, Sören. 1996. Thought experiments in philosophy. Stockholm: Almquist & Wiksell International.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horovitz, Tamara, and Gerald J. Massey (eds.). 1991a. Thought experiments in science and philosophy. Savage: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horovitz, Tamara, and Gerald J. Massey. 1991. Introduction. In: eds. Horovitz and Massey, 1–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huang, Yan. 2010. Neo-Gricean pragmatic theory of conversational implicature. In The Oxford handbook of linguistic analysis, eds. Bernd Heine, and Heiko Narrog, 607–631. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irvine, Andrew D. 1991. Thought experiments in scientific reasoning. In eds. Horovitz and Massey, 149–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katsos, Napoleon, and Chris Cummins. 2010. Pragmatics: From theory to experiment and back again. Language and Linguistics Compass 4(5): 282–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kempson, Ruth M. 1975. Presupposition and the delimitation of semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kepser, Stephan and Marga Reis eds. 2005. Linguistic evidence. Empirical, theoretical and computational perspectives. Berlin and New York: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kertész, András. 2010. On stage setting thought experiments in cognitive linguistics: A case study. In Von Katastrophen, Zeichen und vom Ursprung der menschlichen Sprache, ed. Cornelia Stroh, 7–30. Bochum: Brockmeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kertész, András, and Csilla Rákosi. 2012. Data and evidence in linguistics: A plausible argumentation model. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kiefer, F. 1979. What do conversational maxims explain? Lingvisticae Investigationes 3: 57–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas S. 1970. The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas S. 1977. A function for thought experiments. In The essential tension: Selected studies in scientific tradition and change by Thomas S. Kuhn, 240–265. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kühne, Ulrich. 2005. Die Methode des Gedankenexperiments. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larson, Meredit, Ryna Doran, Yaron McNabb, Rachel Baker, Matthew Berends, Alex Djalali, and Gregory Ward. 2009. Distinguishing the Said from the Implicated using a novel experimental paradigm. In eds. Uli Sauerland and Kazuko Yatsushiro, 74–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, Stephen C. 2000. Presumptive meanings. The theory of generalized conversational implicature. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liedtke, Frank. 2011. The impact of literal meaning on what-is-said. In eds. Jörg Meibauer and Markus Steinbach, 43–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mach, Ernst. 1960. The science of mechanics. La Salle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mach, Ernst. 1976. On thought experiments. In Knowledge and error, ed. Ernst Mach, 137–47. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • McAllister, James. 1996. The evidential significance of thought experiment in science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 27: 233–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meibauer, Jörg. 2012. Pragmatic evidence, context, and story design. An essay on recent developments in experimental pragmatics. In Converging data sources in cognitive linguistics, eds. András Kertész, Monika Schwarz-Friesel and Manfred Consten, 768–776. Amstredam etc.: Elsevier. [= Special Issue of Language Sciences 34/6].

    Google Scholar 

  • Meibauer, Jörg, and Markus Steinbach. 2011. Experimental pragmatics/semantics. Benjamins: Amsterdam & Philadelphia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miščević, Nenad. 1992. Mental models and thought experiments. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 6: 215–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moue, Aspasia S., Kyriakos A. Masavetas, and Haido Karayianni. 2006. Tracing the developments of thought experiments in the philosophy of natural sciences. Journal for the General Philosophy of Science 37: 61–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neale, Stephen. 1992. Paul Grice and the philosophy of language. Linguistics and Philosophy 15: 509–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Németh T., Enikő. 2010. How lexical-semantic factors influence the verbs’ occurrence with implicit direct object arguments in Hungarian. In The role of data at the semantics-pragmaticsed, eds. Enikő Németh T. and Károly Bibok, 305–348.

    Google Scholar 

  • Németh, T., Enikő. 2006. Review of Noveck and Sperber eds. 2004. Intercultural Pragmatics 3: 111–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Németh, T., Enikő. 2008. Verbal information transmission without communicative intention. Intercultural Pragmatics 5: 153–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Németh, T., Enikő, and Bibok Károly (eds.). 2010. The role of data at the semantics–pragmatics interface. Berlin & New York: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, Nancy. 1993. In the theoretician’s laboratory: Thought experiments as mental modelling. In: Proceedings of the 1992 biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association, Vol. 2, 291–301. Michigan: Philosophy of Science Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, Thomas. 1980. Scientific discovery, logic and rationality. In Scientific discovery, logic, and rationality, ed. Thomas Nickles, 1–59. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nicolle, Steve, and Billy Clark. 1999. Experimental pragmatics and what is said: A response to Gibbs and Moise. Cognition 69: 337–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, John D. 2004a. Why thought experiments do not transcend empiricism. In Contemporary debates in philosophy of science, ed. Christopher Hitchcock, 44–66. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, John D. 2004b. On thought experiments: Is there more to the argument? In: Proceedings of the 2002 biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association [= Philosophy of Science 71: 1139–1151.].

    Google Scholar 

  • Noveck, Ira A. 2001. When children are more logical than adults: Experimental investigations of scalar implicature. Cognition 78: 165–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noveck, Ira, and Anne Reboul. 2008. Experimental pragmatics: A Gricean turn in the study of language. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 12: 425–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noveck, Ira, and Dan Sperber (eds.). 2004a. Experimental pragmatics. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noveck, Ira A., and Dan Sperber. 2007. The why and how of experimental pragmatics. In Pragmatics, ed. Noël Burton-Roberts, 184–212. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noveck, Ira and Dan Sperber. 2004. Introduction. In eds. Noveck, Ira and Dan Sperber, 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peijnenburg, Jeanne, and David Atkinson. 2003. When are thought experiments poor ones? Journal for General Philosophy of Science 34: 305–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Penke, Martina and Anette Rosenbach eds. 2007. What Counts as Evidence in Linguistics? Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polya, George. 1948. How to solve it. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polya, George. 1954. Patterns of plausible inference. London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, François. 1989. The pragmatics of what is said. Mind and Language 4: 295–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, François. 2001. What is said. Synthese 128: 75–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, François. 2004. Literal meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, Nicholas. 1976. Plausible reasoning. Assen and Amsterdam: Van Gorcum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, Nicholas. 1987. How serious a fallacy is inconsistency? Argumentation 1: 303–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, Nicholas. 2005. ‘What if?’: Thought experimentation in philosophy. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, Nicholas. 1991. Thought experimentation in presocratic philosophy. In eds. Horovitz and Massey, 31–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sadock, Jerrold M. 1978. On testing for conversational implicature. In Syntax and semantics 9: Pragmatics, ed. Peter Cole, 281–297. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sauerland, Uli, and Kazuko Yatsushiro. 2009. Semantics and pragmatics. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saul, Jennifer. 2002. What is said and psychological reality: Grice’s project and relevance theorist’s criticisms. Linguistics and Philosophy 24: 347–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John R. 1969. Speech acts. An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen, Roy A. 1992. Thought experiments. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sternefeld, Wolfgang ed. 2007. Data in generative grammar [= Theoretical Linguistics 33/3: 269–413].

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomason, Sarah G. 1991. Thought experiments in linguistics. In eds. Horovitz and Massey, 247–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, Douglas N. 1992. Plausible argument in everyday conversation. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, Douglas N. 2001. Abductive, presumptive and plausible arguments. Informal Logic 21: 141–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, Douglas, Chris Reed, and Fabrizio Macagno. 2008. Argumentation schemes. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Winkler, Susanne and Sam Featherston eds. 2009. The fruits of empirical linguistics. Vol. 2: Product. Berlin and New York: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

András Kertész’ contribution to the present paper was supported by the Research Group for Theoretical Linguistics of the Hungarian Academy of Sciences as well as the projects OTKA K 77823 and TAMOP 4.2.1./B-09/1/KONV-2010-0007. We are grateful to Enikő Németh T. and an anonymous reviewer for helpful comments on earlier drafts.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ferenc Kiefer .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kertész, A., Kiefer, F. (2013). From Thought Experiments to Real Experiments in Pragmatics. In: Capone, A., Lo Piparo, F., Carapezza, M. (eds) Perspectives on Pragmatics and Philosophy. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 1. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-01011-3_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics