Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 320))

Abstract

This chapter proposes a new criterion of theory choice. I begin with a criticism on a traditional criterion of theory choice. Contra the traditional approach, I argue that theory choice is a situation where scientists are reasoning what theory should be favoured as the most promising theory in the area rather than the one where scientists choose a theory among all the alternatives to be the best theory in the area. Then, I elaborate the concept of promisingness of theories in terms of potential usefulness. Moreover, I compare promisingness with other diachronic criteria, such as Popper’s potential progressiveness, Lakatos’ predictive novelty, McMullin’s P-fertility, Laudan’s fertility-promise, Ivani’s fruitfulness, and Šešelja et al’s pursuit worthiness. Finally, I argue for the promisingness criterion from a normative viewpoint.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    It has been recognised that theory choice is not a best phrase if theory is construed narrowly, given that choice in scientific change usually involves the commitment to some non-theoretical elements (e.g. values and experimental procedure). Thus, theory here should be understood in a broad sense, referring to a unit of scientific consensus which encompasses both the theoretical and the non-theoretical elements. Thomas Kuhn’s “paradigm (as disciplinary matrix)” (1970), Imre Lakatos’ “research programme” (1968), Larry Laudan’s “research tradition” (1977), and Hasok Chang’s “system of practice” (2014) are among the most famous attempts to articulate such a unit of scientific consensus. In order to avoid making any commitment by adopting the phrases like “paradigm choice” and “system choice”, I wish to follow the traditional phrase “theory choice”, where theory is construed loosely. Accordingly, theories in the chapter refer to scientific consensuses based on some exemplary practices. For example, when talking of the Mendelian theory, I refer it to a scientific consensus based on some exemplary practices in the study of heredity (e.g. Bateson 1902).

  2. 2.

    Nevertheless, there is a persistent debate on what counts as a best theory in contemporary philosophy of science (e.g. Kuhn 1977; Ivanova and Paternotte 2013; McMullin 2014; Morreau 2014).

  3. 3.

    Here I mean early Weldon (1902–1904). For a detailed analysis of Weldon’s view on inheritance, see Chap. 4.

  4. 4.

    That being said, I would like to highlight that my argument should be not understood in the way that scientists did not look for the best theory at the time in theory choice. They did work hard to look for the best available theory sometimes but by doing so, they ultimately aimed at the most promising theory.

  5. 5.

    As I have shown in Sect. 4.3, Weldon’s work on inheritance in the first decade of the twentieth century can be divided into two periods: 1901–1904 and 1904–1906. The works in the first period were basically the criticisms of Mendelism.

  6. 6.

    Note that Weldon accepted that there were the phenomena of discontinuous variation, but he did not think that discontinuous variation played any significant role in the process of evolution. In other words, what Weldon differed from Bateson was the significance of discontinuous variation in the study of evolution.

  7. 7.

    It should be noted that by arguing that simplicity and external consistency are two virtues that typically project prominsingness, I am not offering an algorithm of theory choice.

  8. 8.

    Pearson founded the world’s first statistics department at UCL in 1911 and has been widely credited as the founder of modern statistics.

  9. 9.

    In addition, Weldon’s professional experience influenced his adoption of the statistical approach. Since 1895, Weldon had closely collaborated with the Marine Biological Association, where the research carried out would well fit with the statistical approach. Moreover, Weldon’s close collaboration and friendship with Pearson also reinforced his commitment to the statistical approach.

  10. 10.

    Unfortunately, McMullin (1976, 2014) talks little of U-fertility, because his focus has been P-fertility.

References

  • Baker, Alan. 2003. Quantitative Parsimony and Explanatory Power. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 54 (2): 245–259.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bateson, William. 1894. Materials for the Study of Variation Treated with Especial Regard to Discontinuity in the Origin of Species. London: Macmillan & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1902. Mendel’s Principles of Heredity: A Defence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1905. Compulsory Greek at Cambridge. Nature 71 (1843): 390.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1909. Mendel’s Principles of Heredity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumann, Peter. 2005. Theory Choice and the Intransitivity of ‘Is a Better Theory Than’. Philosophy of Science 72 (1): 231–240.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, Seamus. 2017. Constraints on Rational Theory Choice. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 68 (3): 639–661.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang, Hasok. 2014. Epistemic Activities and Systems of Practice: Units of Analysis in Philosophy of Science After the Practical Turn. In Science After the Practice Turn in the Philosophy, History and Social Studies of Science, ed. Léna Soler, Sjoerd Zwart, Michael Lynch, and Vincent Israel-Jost, 67–79. New York/London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Correns, Carl. 1900. G. Mendels Regel über das Verhalten der Nachkommenschaft der Rassenbastarde. Berichte der Deutschen Botanischen Gesellschaft 18 (4): 158–168.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darden, Lindley. 1977. William Bateson and the Promise of Mendelism. Journal of the History of Biology 10 (1): 87–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forster, Malcolm, and Elliott Sober. 1994. How to Tell When Simpler, More Unified, or Less Ad Hoc Theories will Provide More Accurate Predictions. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (1): 1–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Froggatt, Peter, and Norman C. Nevin. 1971. The ‘Law of Ancestral Heredity’ and the Mendelian-Ancestrian Controversy in England, 1889-1906. Journal of Medical Genetics 8 (1): 1–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galton, Francis. 1889. Natural Inheritance. London/New York: Macmillan & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ivani, Silvia. 2019. What We (Should) Talk about When We Talk about Fruitfulness. European Journal for Philosophy of Science 9 (1): 4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ivanova, Milena, and Cedric Paternotte. 2013. Theory Choice, Good Sense and Social Consensus. Erkenntnis 78 (5): 1109–1132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas Samuel. 1957. The Copernican Revolution. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1970. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2nd ed. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1977. Objectivity, Value Judgment, and Theory Choice. In The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change, 320–339. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1983. Rationality and Theory Choice. Journal of Philosophy 80 (10): 563–570.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, Imre. 1968. Criticism and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 69: 149–186.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1978. Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes. In The Methodology of Scientific Research Programme, ed. John Worrall and Gregory Currie, 8–101. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, Larry. 1977. Progress and Its Problems: Toward a Theory of Scientific Growth. Berkeley/Los Angeles: The University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1981. A Problem-Solving Approach to Scientific Progress. In Scientific Revolutions, edited by Ian Hacking, 144–155. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, Ernst. 1982. The Growth of Biological Thought. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, Ernan. 1976. The Fertility of Theory and the Unit for Appraisal in Science. In Essays in Memory of Imre Lakatos, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, ed. Robert S. Cohen, Paul Feyerabend, and M.W. Wartofsky, 395–432. Dordrecht/Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1982. Values in Science Volume. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 2: 3–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. The Virtues of a Good Theory. In The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Science, ed. Martin Curd and Stathis Psillos, 2nd ed., 561–571. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mendel, Gregor. 1866. Versuche über Pflanzenhybriden. Verhandlungen des Naturforschenden Vereins Brünn IV (Abhandlungen): 3–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morreau, Michael. 2014. Mr. Fit, Mr. Simplicity and Mr. Scope: From Social Choice to Theory Choice. Erkenntnis 79 (6): 1253–1268.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Theory Choice and Social Choice: Kuhn Vindicated. Mind 124 (493): 239–262.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, Bernard J. 1973. The Biometric Defense of Darwinism. Journal of the History of Biology 6 (2): 283–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, Samir. 2011. Theory Choice and Social Choice: Kuhn versus Arrow. Mind 120 (477): 83–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olby, Robert Cecil. 1989. The Dimensions of Scientific Discovery: The Biometric-Mendelian Debate. The British Journal for the History of Science 22 (3): 299–320.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearson, Karl. 1898. Mathematical Contributions to the Theory of Evolution. On the Law of Ancestral Heredity. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London 62: 386–412.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1908. On a Mathematical Theory of Determinantal Inheritance, from Suggestions and Notes of the Late W. F. R. Weldon. Biometrika 6 (1): 80–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearson, Karl, and Alice Lee. 1900. Mathematical Contributions to the Theory of Evolution. VIII. On the Inheritance of Characters Not Capable of Exact Quantitative Measurement. Part I. Introductory. Part II. On the Inheritance of Coat-Colour in Horses. Part III. On the Inheritance of Eye-Co. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series A, Containing Papers of a Mathematical or Physical Character 195: 79–150.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, Karl. 1963. Truth, Rationality, and the Growth of Scientific Knowledge. In Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge, 215–250. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Provine, William B. 1971. The Origin of Theoretical Population Genetics. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Punnett, Reginald Crundall. 1911. Mendelism. 3rd ed. New York: The MacMillan Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizza, Davide. 2014. Arrow’s Theorem and Theory Choice. Synthese 191 (8): 1–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rueger, Alexander. 1996. Risk and Diversification in Theory Choice. Synthese 109 (2): 263–280.

    Google Scholar 

  • Šešelja, Dunja, and Erik Weber. 2012. Rationality and Irrationality in the History of Continental Drift: Was the Hypothesis of Continental Drift Worthy of Pursuit? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (1): 147–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Šešelja, Dunja, Laszlo Kosolosky, and Christian Straßer. 2012. Rationality of Scientic Reasoning in the Context of Pursuit: Drawing Appropriate Distinctions. Philosophica 86: 51–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waters, C.Kenneth. 2004. What was Classical Genetics? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 35 (4): 783–809.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. The Nature and Context of Exploratory Experimentation: An Introduction to Three Case Studies of Exploratory Research. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 29 (3): 275–284.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Shifting Attention from Theory to Practice in Philosophy of Biology. In New Directions in the Philosophy of Science, ed. Maria Carla Galavotti, Dennis Dieks, Wenceslao J. Gonzalez, Stephan Hartmann, Thomas Uebel, and Marcel Weber, 121–139. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weldon, Walter Frank Rapheal. 1894. The Study of Animal Variation. Nature 50: 25–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1895. Remarks on Variation in Animals and Plants. To Accompany the First Report of the Committee for Conducting Statistical Inquiries into the Measurable Characteristics of Plants and Animals. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London 57: 379–382.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1902a. Mendel’s Laws of Alternative Inheritance in Peas. Biometrika 1 (2): 228–254.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1902b. On the Ambiguity of Mendel’s Categories. Biometrika 2 (1): 44–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weldon, Walter Frank Rapheal, Karl Pearson, and Charles B. Davenport. 1901. Editorial: The Spirit of Biometrika. Biometrika 1 (1): 3–6.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Shan, Y. (2020). Promisingness in Theory Choice. In: Doing Integrated History and Philosophy of Science: A Case Study of the Origin of Genetics. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 320. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-50617-9_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics