Skip to main content

Spontaneous Localization Theories with a Particle Ontology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Do Wave Functions Jump?

Part of the book series: Fundamental Theories of Physics ((FTPH,volume 198))

Abstract

Spontaneous localization theory is a quantum theory proposed by GianCarlo Ghirardi, together with Alberto Rimini and Tullio Weber in 1986. However, soon it became clear to Ghirardi that his work was more than just one theory: he actually developed a framework, a family of theories in which the wavefunction jumps, but where the ontology of the theory is underdetermined. After acknowledging that the wavefunction did not provide a satisfactory ontology, he assumed that matter was described by a continuous matter density field in three-dimensional space, whose evolution is governed by a stochastic wavefunction evolution. Alternatively, Bell assumed that the wavefunction would govern a spatiotemporal event ontology, dubbed ‘flashes.’ However, not much work has been done with the perhaps most obvious possibility, namely that physical objects are made of particles. This paper has two aims. First to explain the reason why people require spontaneous localization theory to be more than just a theory about the wavefunction. This is done by showing how the problem everyone in the foundation of quantum mechanics take to be the fundamental problem of quantum mechanics, namely the measurement problem, is a red herring. Then, the paper explores the possibility of spontaneous localization theories of particles. I argue that this discussion is not a mere exercise, as spontaneous localization theories of particles may be amenable to a relativistic extension which does not require a foliation, and because in general the peculiar type of indeterminism of spontaneous localization theories may help sheding new light on the nature of the tension between quantum theory and relativity.

Forthcoming in: V. Allori, A. Bassi, D. Dürr and N. Zanghí (eds.) Do Wave Functions Jump? Perspectives on the Work of GianCarlo Ghirardi. Springer.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See e.g. Bell [2].

  2. 2.

    See Dürr et al. [7], Allori et al. [8,9,10], Allori [11,12,13,14,15].

  3. 3.

    That is, regardless of whether some coordinates \(r_{1} , r_{2} , \ldots ,r_{N}\), where N is the number of particles thought to exist in the universe (roughly of the order of \(10^{90}\)) can be interpreted as the position of real particles or not, the wavefunction is a function of a high-dimensional variable \(q = \left( {r_{1} , r_{2} , \ldots ,r_{N} } \right)\).

  4. 4.

    Se Allori [11,12,13,14,15,16] and references therein for an exposition of these arguments.

  5. 5.

    The reason for this is unclear, and I cannot fully explore this issue in this paper. Presumably however one could say that historically the theory developed and flourished after the proposal of the Schrödinger’s equation, and so from that moment on it seemed unthinkable to not consider it as part of the theory.

  6. 6.

    However, see Sect. 4 for more on this.

  7. 7.

    See Albert [17], Ney [18, 19] and references therein for proposals to make sense of this.

  8. 8.

    See Dürr et al. [7], Goldstein and Teufel [20], Goldstein and Zanghí [21], Allori [16] for a defense of the nomological approach. Since the wavefunction is part of the axioms of quantum theory, it can be naturally regarded as a Humean law (see [22,23,24,25]). There are other ways in which someone could think of the wavefunction, broadly speaking, as nomological. One can think of the wavefunction as a property which expresses some non-material aspect of the particles [26]. Similarly, one can endorse a dispositional account where laws are understood in terms of dispositions, which in turn are described by the wave-function [27, 28]. Arguably, since dispositions can be time dependent, the objection to the nomological view that laws of nature are time independent while the wavefunction evolves in time seems less compelling here. Having said that, I think these proposals are not very promising in that they rely on the notion of properties which are notoriously a rough nut to crack. As Esfeld [24] has pointed out, there are several severe problems in trying to spell out what fundamental properties are, both in the classical and the quantum domain. On a different tone, let me notice that the objection that in theories with the wavefunction only there are two spaces involved and the relationship between these spaces is a mystery closely resembles one of the objection against Cartesian dualism: if mental states are not in three-dimensional space, how are they interacting with physical states? With this analogy in mind, one can argue that the answer of the proponents of the POA will be similar to the one of the reductive physicalist, presumably a functionalist: the wavefunction is whatever function it plays to generate the empirical data (see [15] for more on this).

  9. 9.

    For more, see Allori [15].

  10. 10.

    See Egg and Esfeld [30], Esfeld and Deckert [31].

  11. 11.

    Here’s a sketch of some possible responses. To the objection that flashes are counterintuitive one could reply that a satisfactory explanation can lead us far from common sense, so sometimes getting away from commonsensical explanation may be the right thing to do. For instance, while common sense suggests that matter is continuous, atomic theory has shown us that it is not the case: atomic theory, with its in-breath and in-depth explanatory power, is a better explanation of the behavior of matter than our common sense. So, we are justified in accepting atomic theory even if it pictures a world which is distant from what we initially thought. Moreover, the reply goes, in the case of GRWf abandoning common sense for an unfamiliar ontology makes the theory more compatible with relativity, as suggested by Bell (however, see Sect. 6). Also, one could question the fact that the ontology and the explanation is really counterintuitive in a negative sense. It is true that the action of fields is continuous even if there are no flashes. However, this is a problem only if the field are intended as material, which in the POA is not necessarily the case: they could be taken to be not generated by the particles, but rather alike to nomological entities, similarly to what happens for the wavefunction in quantum theory (see Allori [14] for a discussion of this). Also, see Esfeld [32] for a defense of GRWf. To the objection that the matter density has tails which could be crossed by other objects without any visible interaction, one could arguably maintain that this is counterintuitive merely when we look at things from a classical perspective: only because classically matter which encounters other matter interacts with it, it does not mean that it has to be the case in the quantum domain. Moreover, the fact that the quantum formalism is in terms of particles does not seem to force us to interpret it as a theory of particles, as one could presumably endorse the formalism of a continuous localization theories (CSL) which does not require particles [32]. Finally nonlocality is a puzzle for all theories, not merely GRWm, so that it is unclear how serious the last objection actually is.

  12. 12.

    See Allori et al. [8, 10], Bedingham [35], Allori [15].

  13. 13.

    However, see Bohm and Hiley [36], p. 346.

  14. 14.

    Other particle theories, aside from the pilot-wave theory, are stochastic mechanics [37], and Bell-type quantum field theories [38,39,40]. In both theories the wavefunction evolves deterministically, in contrast with GRW-type particle theories. In the former the particles evolve according to a stochastic Markov process, while in the latter the evolution is also stochastic but the particles can also be created and destroyed.

  15. 15.

    For more on empirical coherence, see Barrett [41], Huggett and Wüthrich [42].

  16. 16.

    See Dürr et al. [46, 47].

  17. 17.

    For a criticism, see Barret [49] and Esfeld and Gisin [50], who argue that these theories, even if they are Lorentz invariant in terms of the overall histories of their PO, are unable to describe single events in a relativistic invariant way.

  18. 18.

    Another interesting attempt of a relativistic pilot-wave theory without a foliation has been proposed by Sutherland [52, 53], which however involves retrocausation.

  19. 19.

    Of course, if the rGRWp proposed above requires a microscopic inverse arrow of time, then this may be taken to diminish the explanatory power of the theory. However, since the theory has yet to be constructed this kind of considerations seem premature.

References

  1. Schrödinger, Erwin. 1935. Die gegenwärtige Situation in der Quantenmechanik Die Naturwissenschaften 23: 807–812, 823–828, 844–849.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Bell, John Stuart. 1987. Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  3. de Broglie, Louis. 1927. La Nouvelle Dynamique des Quanta. In: Solvay Conference, Electrons et Photons. Translated in G. Bacciagaluppi and A. Valentini (2009): Quantum Theory at the Crossroads: Reconsidering the 1927 Solvay Conference: 341–371. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Bohm, David. 1952. A Suggested Interpretation of the Quantum Theory in Terms of ‘Hidden’ Variables, I and II. Physical Review, 85, 166–193.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Everett, Hugh. 1957. Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics. Review of Modern Physics, 29, 454–462.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ghirardi, Giancarlo, Rimini, Alberto, and Weber, Tullio. 1986. Unified Dynamics for Microscopic and Macroscopic Systems. Physical Review D, 34, 470–491.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Dürr, Detlef, Goldstein, Sheldon, and Zanghì, Nino. 1997. Bohmian Mechanics and the Meaning of the Wave Function. In: Cohen, R. S., Horne, M. & Stachel, J. (Eds.), Experimental Metaphysics—Quantum Mechanical Studies for Abner Shimony, Vol. 1; Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 193: 25–38. Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Allori, Valia, Goldstein, Sheldon, Tumulka, Roderich, and Zanghì, Nino. 2008. On the Common Structure of Bohmian Mechanics and the Ghirardi-Rimini-Weber Theory. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 59, 353–389.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Allori, Valia, Goldstein, Sheldon, Tumulka, Roderich, and Zanghì, Nino. 2011. Many-Worlds and Schrödinger’s First Quantum Theory. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62, 1–27.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Allori, Valia, Goldstein, Sheldon, Tumulka, Roderich, and Zanghì, Nino. 2014. Predictions and Primitive Ontology in Quantum Foundations: A Study of Examples. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65, 323–352.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Allori, Valia. 2013a. Primitive Ontology and the Structure of Fundamental Physical Theories. In: Albert, David Z., and Ney, Alyssa (eds.). The Wave Function. New York: Oxford University Press. 58–75.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Allori, Valia. 2013b. On the Metaphysics of Quantum Mechanics. In: Lebihan, Soazig (ed.), Precis de la Philosophie de la Physique: 116–151. Vuibert.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Allori, Valia. 2015a. Quantum Mechanics and Paradigm Shifts. Topoi, 32, 313–323.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Allori, Valia. 2015b. Primitive Ontology in a Nutshell. International Journal of Quantum Foundations 1 (3): 107–122.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Allori, Valia. 2019. Scientific Realism without the Wave-Function: An Example of Naturalized Quantum Metaphysics. In: Saatsi, Juha, French, Steven (eds.) Scientific Realism and the Quantum, Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Allori, Valia. 2018. Primitive Ontology and Scientific Realism. Or: The Pessimistic Meta-Induction and the Nature of the Wave Function. Lato Sensu: Revue de la Société de Philosophie des Sciences 5 (1): 69–76 (2018).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Albert, David Z. 2015. After Physics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ney, Alyssa. 2017. Finding the World in the Wave Function: Some Strategies for Solving the Macro-object Problem. Synthese, 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ney, Alyssa. Forthcoming. Finding the World in the Wave Function. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Goldstein, Sheldon, and Teufel, Stefan. 2001. Quantum Spacetime without Observers: Ontological Clarity and the Conceptual Foundations of Quantum Gravity. In Callender, Carig, and Huggett, Nick (eds.), Physics meets Philosophy at the Planck Scale, 275–289. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Goldstein, Sheldon, and Zanghì, Nino. 2013. Reality and the Role of the Wave Function in Quantum Theory. In Albert, David Z., and Ney, Alyssa (eds.). The Wave Function. New York: Oxford University Press: 96–109.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Bhogal, Harjit, and Perry, Zee. 2017. What the Humean Should Say About Entanglement. Noûs, 1, 74–94.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Callender, Craig. 2015. One World, One Beable. Synthese, 192, 3153–3177.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Esfeld, Michael. 2014. Quantum Humeanism, or: Physicalism without Properties. The Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 453–470.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Miller, Elisabeth. 2014. Quantum Entanglement, Bohmian Mechanics, and Humean Supervenience. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 92, 567–583.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Monton, Bradely. 2013. Against 3 N-Dimensional Space. In: Albert, David Z., and Ney, Alyssa, The Wave-function: Essays in the Metaphysics of Quantum Mechanics: 154–167. New York, Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Esfeld, Michael, Lazarovici, Dustin, Huber, Mario, and Dürr, Detlef. 2014. The Ontology of Bohmian Mechanics. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65, 773–796.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Suarez, Mauricio. 2015. Bohmian Dispositions Synthese, 192 (10): 3203–3228.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Bennatti, Fabio, Ghirardi, GianCarlo, Grassi, Renata. 1995. Describing the Macroscopic World: Closing the Circle within the Dynamical Reduction Program. Foundations of Physics, 25, 5–38.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Egg, Matthias and Esfeld, Michael. 2014. “Non-local common cause explanations for EPR”. European Journal for Philosophy of Science 4, pp. 181–196.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Esfeld, Michael and Deckert, Dirk-André. 2017. A minimalist ontology of the natural world. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Esfeld, Michael. 2019. From the Measurement Problem to the Primitive Ontology Programme.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Healey, Richard. 2015 How Quantum Theory Helps us Explain. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 66: 1–43.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Lewis, Peter J. 2019. On Closing the Circle.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Bedingham, Daniel. 2011. Relativistic state reduction dynamics. Foundations of. Physics 41: 686–704..

    Google Scholar 

  36. Bohm, David, and Hiley, Basil J. 1993. The Undivided Universe, London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Nelson, Edward.1985. Quantum Fluctuations. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Bell, John S. 1986. Beables for Quantum Field Theory. Physics Reports, 137:49–54.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Dürr, Detlef, Goldstein, Sheldon, Tumulka, Roderick and Zanghì, Nino. 2004. Bohmian Mechanics and Quantum Field Theory. Physical Review Letters, 93:090402.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Dürr, Detlef, Goldstein, Sheldon, Tumulka, Roderick and Zanghì, Nino. 2005. Bell-type Quantum Field Theories. Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and General, 38(4):R1–R43.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Barrett, Jeffrey, A. 1999. The Quantum Mechanics of Minds and Worlds. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Huggett, Nick, and Wüthrich, Christian. 2013. Emergent Spacetime and Empirical (in) coherence. Studies in Histories and Philosophy of Science B44: 276–285.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Gao, Shan. 2017. The Meaning of the Wave Function: In Search of the Ontology of Quantum Mechanics, Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Laudan, Larry. 1981. A Confutation of Convergent Realism. Philosophy of Science, 48, 19–49.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Tumulka, Roderich. 2006. A Relativistic Version of the Ghirardi-Rimini-Weber Model. Journal of Statistical Physics, 125, 821–840.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Dürr, Detlef, Münch-Berndl, Katrin, Goldstein, Sheldon, and Zanghì, Nino. 1999. Hypersurface Bohm-Dirac Models. Journal of Statistical Physics, 67, 843–907.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Dürr, Detlef, Goldstein, Sheldon, Norsen, Travis, Struyve, Ward, and Zanghì, Nino. 2014. Can Bohmian Mechanics be Made Relativistic? Proceedings of the Royal Society A 470(2162): 20130699.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Bedingham, Daniel, Dürr, Detlef, Ghirardi, GianCarlo, Goldstein, Sheldon, Tumulka, Roderich and Zanghì, Nino. 2014. “Matter density and relativistic models of wave function collapse”. Journal of Statistical Physics 154: 623–631.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Barrett, Jeffrey A. 2014. Entanglement and disentanglement in relativistic quantum mechanics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 47, pp. 168–174.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Esfeld, Michael, and Gisin, Nicolas. 2014. The GRW Flash Theory: A Relativistic Quantum Ontology of Matter in Space-Time? Philosophy of Science 81 (2):248–264.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Goldstein, Sheldon, and Tumulka, Roderich. 2003. Opposite Arrows of Time Can Reconcile Relativity and Nonlocality. Class. Quantum Gravity 20: 557–564.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Sutherland, Roderick. 2008. Causally Symmetric Bohm Model. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 39: 782–805.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Sutherland, Roderick. 2017. Lagrangian Description for Particle Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics—Entangled Many-Particle Case. Foundations of Physics 47: 174–207.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Valia Allori .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Allori, V. (2021). Spontaneous Localization Theories with a Particle Ontology. In: Allori, V., Bassi, A., Dürr, D., Zanghi, N. (eds) Do Wave Functions Jump? . Fundamental Theories of Physics, vol 198. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-46777-7_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics