Skip to main content

Peirce’s Existential Graphs as a Contribution to Transcendental Logic

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Peirce and Husserl: Mutual Insights on Logic, Mathematics and Cognition

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 46))

Abstract

Peirce, among his vast logical works, also invented a less known logical framework called by him Existential Graphs. It offers a diagrammatic method to represent logical expressions and logical deductions, so that logical deductions are formulated as transformations of diagrams. In this paper, after a short introduction to Existential Graphs (EGs hereafter), I will propose an interpretation of the framework of EGs in a way that it offers a method for meaning explanation of logical connectives. According to this interpretation, I will try to show, that the meaning explanation displayed by EG is different both from truth-functional and inferentialist approaches. I will focus on the philosophical merits of this framework, more precisely I am going to suggest that the features of EGs satisfy certain essential criteria of a theory of logic as put forward by transcendental investigations. Indeed EGs provide us with a powerful tool to carry out logical analyses not only in a formal way but also as belonging to what Husserl calls the “phenomenology of reason”.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    As Husserl emphasizes: (Husserl 1969, p. 264).

  2. 2.

    As emphasized by Peirce, e. g. in “The first rule of logic” (Peirce 1998, p. 44).

  3. 3.

    Kant says :

    It would therefore concern the origin of our cognitions of objects in so far as that cannot be ascribed to the objects; while general logic, on the contrary, has nothing to do with this origin of cognition, but rather ... deals only with the form of the understanding, which can be given to the representations wherever they may have originated (Kant 1998, A56, B81).

  4. 4.

    Notice that in his classification, Peirce uses the term objective logic (Peirce 1976, p. 30), but it is different from our definition of the term here. It goes without saying that our conception is also different from the employment of this term by Hegel.

  5. 5.

    For the phenomenological concept of neutral-modification, or modification-to-empty (Leermodifikation see the relevant parts in Husserl (1969, 2002)).

  6. 6.

    It is worth mentioning that (Mohanty 1976, p. 131 f) sees a similarity between this Husserlian distinction which we are going to discuss and the distinction between three branches of logic that Peirce makes in his classification of sciences.

  7. 7.

    For further discussions about the distinction between consequence-level and truth-level see the corresponding part in Shafiei (2019).

  8. 8.

    This is a wonderful property of a logical framework, as far as the exact investigations pertained to transcendental logic are concerned. Among the various frameworks developed in the last century, besides EG, Dialogical logic introduced by Paul Lorenzen and Kuno Lorenz also possesses such a property, as I discussed in Shafiei (2019). About the basic accordance of the dialogal logic with the logical features offered by the transcendental investigations, I have discussed in Shafiei (2018).

  9. 9.

    Roberts describes the shape of the pseudograph as “a cut entirely filled in, or blackened” (Roberts 1973, p. 36), which is indeed an unsuitable chose of the words.

  10. 10.

    Peirce CP. 4.430.

  11. 11.

    In “Habits of Reasoning: On the Grammar and Critics of Logical Habits” (Pietarinen and Bellucci 2016) authors say:

    According to Peirce, any proof of a leading principle can only consist in showing that the leading principle to be proved is already admitted to be true in another form in the argument that is supposed to prove it. The only proof of a principle is the proof of its un-eliminability.

    This observation is also provides further evidence for the affinity of Peirce’s approach with the transcendental method.

  12. 12.

    As I already mentioned, the only other framework which fulfills the mentioned phenomenological requirement is the dialogical logic, in which the rules for logical connectives should be symmetric, which means that they should not depend on the role of the utterer.

References

  • Bellucci, F., & Pietarinen, A.-V. (2016). Existential graphs as an instrument of logical analysis: Part I ALPHA. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 9(2), 209–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1969). Formal and transcendental logic (D. Cairns, Trans.). The Hague, Netherlands: Martin Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1969). Ideas: General introduction to pure phenomenology (W. R. Gibson, Trans.) London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1973). Experience and judgment (J. Churchill & K. Ameriks, Trans). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2002). Logische Untersuchungen. Ergänzungsband. Erster Teil (Ed.) U. Melle, volume XX/1 of Husserliana. Netherlands: The Hague.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1998). Critique of pure reason (P. Guyer & A. W. Wood, Trans.). The Cambridge edition of the works of Immanuel Kant Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ma, M. & Pietarinen, A.-V. (2018). A Graphical Deep Inference System for Intuitionistic Logic, Logique & Analyse, 245, 73–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohanty, J. N. (1976). Edmond Husserl’s theory of meaning. The Hague, Netherlands: Martin Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oostra, A. (2010). Los gráficos alfa de peirce aplicados a la lógica intuicionista. Cuadernos de Sistemática Peirceana, 2, 25–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1960). Collected papers of charles sanders Peirce. Edited by Hartshorne, C., Weiss, P., & Burks, A. W. (Eds.). USA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1976). The new elements of mathematics: Vol. 4: Mathematical philosophy (Ed.) C. Eisele. Mouton De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1998). The essential peirce: Selected philosophical writings (Peirce Edition Project ed., Vol. 2). Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietarinen, A.-V. (2006). Signs of logic: Peircean themes on the philosophy of language, games, and communication (Synthese Library 329). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietarinen, A.-V., & Bellucci, F. (2016). Habits of reasoning: On the grammar and critics of logical habits. In D. E. West & M. Anderson (Eds.), Consensus on Peirce’s Concept of Habit: Before and Beyond Consciousness (pp. 265–282). Cham: Springer International Publishing.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, D. (1973). The existential graphs of Charles S. Peirce. Mouton: The Hague.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shafiei, M. (2019). A phenomenological analysis of the distinction between structural rules and particle rules in dialogical logic. In C. Weiss (Ed.), Constructive semantics–meaning in between phenomenology and constructivism. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shafiei, M. (2018). Meaning and inentionality. A dialogical approach. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shin, S. J. (2002). The iconic logic of Peirce’s graphs. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stjernfelt, F. (2007). Diagrammatology: An investigation on the borderlines of phenomenology, ontology, and semiotics., Synthese library Netherlands: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zeman, J. J. (1964). The Graphical Logic of C. S. Peirce. USA: University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mohammad Shafiei .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Shafiei, M. (2019). Peirce’s Existential Graphs as a Contribution to Transcendental Logic. In: Shafiei, M., Pietarinen, AV. (eds) Peirce and Husserl: Mutual Insights on Logic, Mathematics and Cognition. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 46. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-25800-9_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics