Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Phaenomenologica ((PHAE,volume 173))

Abstract

“To the things themselves!” Thus sounded the battle cry of the movement of phenomenology, inaugurated in 1900-1901 by Edmund Husserl. Among the philosophers who would subsequently associate themselves with this movement, and eagerly reiterate Husserl’s maxim, was Martin Heidegger. The final story of the personal relationship of these two major figures of twentieth Century philosophy still remains to be told,1 but it is certain that it ended in personal tragedy, at least from Husserl’s point of view. As far as the relation between their philosophical doctrines is concerned, Husserl and the early Heidegger’s agreement that philosophy had to be carried out as phenomenology has not led to consensus among commentators. It has been and remains unclear to what extent “phenomenology” actually means the same thing to Husserl and Heidegger. Opinions ränge from the view that “Husserlian and Heideggerian phenomenology are radically different, and have virtually nothing to do with each other,”2 to the contention that “the whole of Sein und Zeit Springs from an indication given by Husserl,” and amounts to nothing more than a detailed elaboration of a particular Husserlian theme.3

“Away with empty word analyses! We must question the things themselves. Back to experience, to seeing, which alone can give our words sense and rational justification.” Very much to the point! But what, then, are these things? And what sort of experience is it to which we must return [...]?

Husserliana XXV, p. 21.

Whence and how is it determined what must be experienced as “the things themselves” in accordance with the principle of phenomenology? Is it consciousness and its objectivity or is it the being of beings [das Sein des Seienden] in its unconcealedness and concealment?

Zur Sache des Denkens, p. 87.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Though a good deal is written on the subject, it remains a difficult as well as delicate issue. For various accounts of the relationship, see Hugo Ott, Martin Heidegger: Unterwegs zu seiner Biographie, esp. pp. 167–179; Theodore Kisiel, “Husserl and Heidegger”; and Thomas Sheehan, “Husserl and Heidegger: The Making and Unmaking of a Relationship.”

    Google Scholar 

  2. Richard Schacht, “Husserlian and Heideggerian Phenomenology,” p. 294.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology ofPerception, p. vii.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Cf. GA 19, p. 587: “They come to the point where they think phenomenology is an easy science, in which one intuits essences, sort of lying on the couch with one’s pipe.”

    Google Scholar 

  5. A note on the previous literature. Ernst Tugendhat’s landmark study Der Wahrheitsbegriff bei Husserl und Heidegger is still an important work, not least because of the critical distance the author displays in relation to both Husserl and Heidegger. Tugendhat also offers an Interpretation of their relation that, in

    Google Scholar 

  6. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology ofPerception, p. 57.

    Google Scholar 

  7. David Farrell Krell, Intimations ofMortality, p. 99.

    Google Scholar 

  8. See GA 12, p. 114; GA 29/30, p. 534 (a speech given on the occasion of Eugen Fink’s birthday in 1965); ZSD, pp. 48, 90; and “Preface/Vorwort,” pp. xv-xvii.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Cf., e.g., Otto Pöggeler, “Die Krise des phänomenologischen Philosophiebegriffs (1929),” and Der Denkweg Martin Heideggers, p. 358. Theodore Kisiel has dubbed the period 1919–1929 as Heidegger’s “phenomenological decade” (The Genesis of Heidegger’s Being and Time, p. 59).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Although the technical term “ontological difference” does not appear in Sein und Zeit, the distinction between being and entities is used throughout the work. I borrow the notion of “operative concepts” from Eugen Fink, Nähe und Distanz, esp. pp. 184–190.

    Google Scholar 

  11. As Donn Welton subtly puts it, “while he [Husserl] did ‘depart’ from Cartesianism, to echo Landgrebe’s well-chosen term, he never abandoned it” (The Other Husserl, p. 97).

    Google Scholar 

  12. Cf. John van Buren, The Young Heidegger, p. 365.

    Google Scholar 

  13. See Bernet, Kern, and Marbach, Edmund Husserl: Darstellung seines Denkens, pp. 10, 213.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2004 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Overgaard, S. (2004). Introduction. In: Husserl and Heidegger on Being in the World. Phaenomenologica, vol 173. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-2239-5_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-2239-5_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-6579-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-4020-2239-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics