Skip to main content

LOST WANDERERS IN THE FOREST OF KNOWLEDGE: SOME THOUGHTS ON THE DISCOVERY-JUSTIFICATION DISTINCTION

  • Chapter
Revisiting Discovery and Justification

Part of the book series: Archimedes ((ARIM,volume 14))

Abstract

Neo-positivism is dead. Let that imperfect designation stand for the project that dominated and defined the philosophy of science, especially in its Anglophone form, during the fifty or so years following the end of the Second World War. While its critics were many,1 its death was slow, and some think still to find a pulse.2 But die it did in the cul-de-sac into which it was led by its own faulty compass.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

REFERENCES

  • Albert, Hans and Topitsch, Ernst (eds.) (1971), Werturteilsstreit. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchge-sellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchdahl, Gerd (1969), Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Science; The Classical Origins: Descartes to Kant. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, Rudolf (1933), “Ueber Protokollsätze.” Erkenntnis 3: 215–228.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, Rudolf (1950), “Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology.” Revue internationale de philosophie 4(11): 20–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, Rudolf (1963), “Intellectual Autobiography.” In The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.) The Library of Living Philosophers, Vol. 11. La Salle, IL: Open Court, pp. 3–84.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, Nancy (1999), The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, Nancy et al. (1996), Otto Neurath: Philosophy between Science andPolitics. Ideas in Context, no. 38. Quentin Skinner et al. (eds.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ciaffa, Jay A. (1998), Max Weber and the Problems of Value-free Social Science: A Critical Examination of the Werturteilsstreit. Lewisburg, NJ: Bucknell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coffa, J. Alberto (1991), The Semantic Tradition from Kant to Carnap: To the Vienna Station. Linda Wessels (ed.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, Heather (2004), “Robert Merton and the Ethos of Science.” Paper presented at the Fifth International Conference of HOPOS, the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science, San Francisco, pp. 24–27 June 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, Pierre (1906), La Theorié physique. Son objet et sa structure. Paris: Chevalier & Rivière.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, Albert (1946), “Autobiographical Notes.” In Schilpp 1949, pp. 1–94. Quotations are taken from the corrected English translation in: Autobiographical Notes: A Centennial Edition. Paul Arthur Schilpp, trans. and ed. La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, 1979.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, Paul (1975), Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge. London:NLB.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, Paul (1978), Science in a Free Society. London: NLB.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, Arthur (1984a), “The Natural Ontological Attitude.” In Jarret Leplin (ed.) Scientific Realism. Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 83–107. Reprinted in Fine 1986, pp. 112–135.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, Arthur (1984b), “And Not Anti-Realism Either.” Noûs 18:51–65. Reprinted in Fine 1986, pp. 136–150.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, Arthur (1986), The Shaky Game: Einstein, Realism, and the Quantum Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, Philipp (1953), “The Variety of Reasons for the Acceptance of Scientific Theories.” In Frank (ed.) 1956, pp. 13–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, Philipp (1957), Philosophy of Science: The Link Between Science and Philosophy. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, Nelson (1955), “The New Riddle of Induction.” In Fact, Fiction, and Forecast. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 59–83. First delivered as a lecture at the University of London, May 26, 1953.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, Norwood Russell (1958), Patterns of Discovery: An Inquiry into the Conceptual Foundations of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, Don (1994), “Einstein, Kant, and the Origins of Logical Empiricism.” In Language, Logic, and the Structure of Scientific Theories: The Carnap-Reichenbach Centennial. Wesley Salmon and Gereon Wolters (eds.) Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press; Konstanz: Universitätsverlag, pp. 45–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, Don (1998), “Astride the Divided Line: Platonism, Empiricism, and Einstein's Epistemological Opportunism.” In Idealization in Contemporary Physics. Niall Shanks (ed.) Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities, Vol. 63. Amsterdam and Atlanta: Rodopi, pp. 143–163.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, Don (2000), “Vertrieben und Verirrt: Politics and the Philosophy of Science in Exile.” Paper delivered at the Third International Conference on the History of the Philosophy of Science, Vienna, Austria, 6–9 July 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, Don (2003), “Two Left Turns Make a Right: On the Curious Political Career of North American Philosophy of Science at Mid-century.” In Logical Empiricism in North America. Alan Richardson and Gary Hardcastle (eds.) Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 25–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joravsky, David (1970), The Lysenko Affair. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, Philip (1985), Vaulting Ambition: Sociobiology and the Quest for Human Nature. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, Philip (1993), The Advancement of Science: Science without Legend, Objectivity without Illusions. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, Philip (1996), The Lives to Come: Tthe Genetic Revolution and Human Possibilities. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, Philip (1998a), “Reviving the Sociology of Science.” PSA 98. Proceedings of the 1998 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association. Part II, Symposia Papers. Don Howard (ed.) Philosophy of Science S67: pp. S33-S44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, Philip (1998b), “A Plea for Science Studies.” In Koertge 1998, pp. 32–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, Philip (2002), Science, Truth, and Democracy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, Philip and Cartwright, Nancy (1996), “Science and Ethics: Reclaiming Some Neglected Questions.” Perspectives on Science: Historical, Philosophical, Social 4: 145–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koertge, Noretta (ed.) (1998), A House Built on Sand: Exposing Postmodernist Myths about Science. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas S. (1962), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas S. (1969), “Postscript-1969.” In The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 174–210.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas S. (1973), “Objectivity, Value Judgment, and Theory Choice.” Matchette Lecture delivered at Furman University, 30 November 1973. First published in: The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1977, pp. 320–339.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kusch, Martin (1995), Psychologism: A Case Study in the Sociology of Philosophical Knowledge. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kusch, Martin (2002), Knowledge by Agreement: The Programme of Communitarian Epistemology. Oxford: Clarendon Press; New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, Helen (1990), Science as Social Knowledge: Values and Objectivity in Scientific Inquiry. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, Helen (2002), The Fate of Knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, Ernan (1982), “Values in Science.” In PSA 1982, Vol. 2. P. D. Asquith and T. Nickles (eds.) East Lansing, Michigan: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 3–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merton, Robert K. (1938), “Science and the Social Order.” Philosophy of Science 5: 321–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merton, Robert K. (1942), “Science and Technology in a Democratic Social Order.” Journal of Legal and Political Sociology 1: 115–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nemeth, Elizabeth (1981), Otto Neurath und der Wiener Kreis. Revolutionäre Wissenschaftlichkeit als Anspruch. Frankfurt and New York: Campus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nemeth, Elizabeth and Stadler, Friedrich (eds.) (1996), Encylopedia and Utopia: the Life and Work of Otto Neurath (1882–1945), Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook, no. 4. Dordrecht, Boston, and London: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neurath, Otto (1913), “Die Verirrten des Cartesius und das Auxiliarmotiv. Zur Psychologie des Entschlusses.” Jahrbuch der Philosophischen Gesellschaft an der Universität Wien. Leipzig: Johann Ambrosius Barth. Page numbers and quotations from the English translation: “The Lost Wanderers of Descartes and the Auxiliary Motive (On the Psychology of Decision),” In Otto Neurath. Philosophical Papers, 1913–1946. Robert S. Cohen and Marie Neurath (ed.) and trans. Vienna Circle Collection, Vol. 16. Henk L. Mulder, Robert S. Cohen, and Brian McGuinness (eds.) Dordrecht, Boston, and Lancaster: D. Reidel, 1983, pp. 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neurath, Otto (1928), Lebensgestaltung und Klassenkampf. Berlin. E. Laub. Page numbers and translations from the excerpt translated as “Personal Life and Class Struggle” in Neurath 1973, pp. 249–298.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neurath, Otto (1932), “Protokollsätze.” Erkenntnis 3:204–214. Page numbers and translations from the excerpt translated as “Protocol Sentences” in Neurath 1983, pp. 91–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neurath, Otto (1934), “Radikaler Physikalismus und, wirkliche Welt.” Erkenntnis 4: 346–362. Page numbers and translations from the excerpt translated as “Radical Physicalism and the ‘Real World”’ in Neurath 1983, pp. 100–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neurath, Otto (1935), “Einheit der Wissenschaft als Aufgabe.” Erkenntnis 5:16–22. Page numbers and translations from the excerpt translated as “The Unity of Science as a Task” in Neurath 1983, pp. 115–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neurath, Otto (1973), Empiricism and Sociology. Marie Neurath and Robert S. Cohen (eds.) Vienna Circle Collection, Vol. 1. Dordrecht and Boston: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neurath, Otto (1983), Philosophical Papers 1913–1946. Robert S. Cohen and Marie Neurath (eds.) and trans. Vienna Circle Collection, Vol. 16. Dordrecht, Boston, and Lancaster: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, Karl Raimund. (1934), Logik der Forschung. Zur Erkenntnistheorie der modernen Naturwis-senschaft. Schriften zur wissenschaftlichen Weltauffassung, Philipp Frank and Moritz Schlick (eds.) Vienna: Julius Spring.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.O. (1951), “Two Dogmas of Empiricism.” Philosophical Review 60:20–13. Reprinted in: From a Logical Point of View. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1953, pp. 20–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.O. (1960), Word & Object. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.O. (1969), “Epistemology Naturalized.” In Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. New York and London: Columbia University Press, pp. 69–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.O. (1981), “Things and Their Place in Theories.” In Theories and Things. Cambridge, Massachusetts and London: Harvard University Press, pp. 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, Hans (1928), Philosophie der Raum-Zeit-Lehre. Berlin: Julius Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, Hans (1938), Experience and Prediction: An Analysis of the Foundations and the Structure of Knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, Hans (1951), The Rise of Scientific Philosophy. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reisch, George (1991), “Did Kuhn Kill Logical Empiricism?” Philosophy of Science 58: 264–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reisch, George (1995), “A History of the International Encyclopedia of Unified Science.” Ph.D. Dissertation. University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reisch, George (2005), How the Cold War Transformed Philosophy of Science: To the Icy Slopes of Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlick, Moritz (1934), “Ueber das Fundament der Erkenntnis.” Erkenntnis 4: 79–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlick, Moritz (1935), “Sind die Naturgesetze Konventionen?” In Actes du Congrès International de Philosophie Scientifique, Paris 1935. Vol. 4, Induction et Probabilité. Actualités Scientifique et Industrielles, no. 391. Paris: Hermann, 1936, pp. 8–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shrader-Frechette, Kristin (1985), Risk Analysis and Scientific Method: Methodological and Ethical Problems with Evaluating Societal Hazards. Dordrecht and Boston: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shrader-Frechette, Kristin(1991), Risk and Rationality: Philosophical Foundations for Populist Reforms. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shrader-Frechette, Kristin (1993), Burying Uncertainty: Risk and the Case against Geological Disposal of Nuclear Waste. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, Miriam (2001), Social Empiricism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stadler, Friedrich (1997), Studien zum Wiener Kreis. Ursprung, Entwicklung und Wirkung des Logischen Empirismus im Kontext. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. English translation: The Vienna Circle: Studies in the Origins, Development, and Influence of Logical Empiricism. Vienna and New York: Springer-Verlag, 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stump, David and Galison, Peter (eds.) (1996), The Disunity of Science: Boundaries, Contexts, and Power. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, Stephen (1953), The Philosophy of Science: An Introduction. London: Hutchinson & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, Stephen (1961), Foresight and Understanding: An Enquiry into the Aims of Science. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, Stephen (1972) Human Understanding, Vol. 1. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uebel, Thomas E. (1992), Overcoming Logical Positivism from Within: The Emergence of Neurath's Naturalism in the Vienna Circle's Protocol Sentence Debate. Amsterdam and Atlanta: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uebel, Thomas E. (ed.) (1991), Rediscovering the Forgotten Vienna Circle: Austrian Studies on Otto Neurath and the Vienna Circle. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 133. Dordrecht, Boston, and Lancaster: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, Bas (2002), The Empirical Stance. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, Jessica (1999), “Merton's Shadow: Perspectives on Science and Democracy since 1940.” Historical Studies in the Physical and Biological Sciences 30: 279–306.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhai, Zhenming (1990), “The Problem of Protocol Statements and Schlick's Concept of ‘Konsta-tierungen.”’ PSA 1990: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. 1. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 15–23.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2006 Springer

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

HOWARD, D. (2006). LOST WANDERERS IN THE FOREST OF KNOWLEDGE: SOME THOUGHTS ON THE DISCOVERY-JUSTIFICATION DISTINCTION. In: SCHICKORE, J., STEINLE, F. (eds) Revisiting Discovery and Justification. Archimedes, vol 14. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/1-4020-4251-5_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics