Skip to main content

Emotions and the Development of Virtue in Puritan Thought: An Investigation of Puritan Friendship

  • Chapter
Puritanism and Emotion in the Early Modern World

Abstract

Recent theological and philosophical meta-narratives paint the Puritans as the impetus behind a massive shift in history highlighting the individualistic nature of the spiritual life they promoted. This shift in emphasis from a communal to a more personal piety ultimately led to individualism in ethics, which, in the opinion of these thinkers, inevitably lead to the individualism that plagues our current culture. Most famous among these broad stroke meta-narratives of the Puritans is that of sociologist Max Weber. In Weber there is a sense that ‘inner worldly asceticism’ led to the individualism found later in Western society mentioned above.1 A more contemporary philosopher, Charles Taylor, in his book A Secular Age consistently comes back to a Protestant, and at times explicitly Puritan, explanation of individualism in spirituality.2 In one sense, it is hard to deny the claims of these historical narratives given by Weber, Taylor and others. There seems to be at least a strong precedent for tracing the changes in broader historical and theological modernity to these sixteenth and seventeenth-century thinkers. However, as I will show in this chapter, this is not the full story. The moral and spiritual life promulgated by the Puritans utilised the same ancient, patristic and medieval traditions that contemporary sociologists, philosophers and theologians are attempting to revive;3 that is, a tradition of classical ethics that emphasises the right ordering of the emotions of an individual person in the development of virtue that extends to, and is drawn from, those within a political and ecclesial community.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 34.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 44.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Max Weber, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, Talcott Parsons (trans.), 2nd edn (New York: Routledge, 2001).

    Google Scholar 

  2. See Charles Taylor, A Secular Age (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2007), 80, 129, 165, 230, 266.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See, for example, Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (University of Notre Dame Press, 1984);

    Google Scholar 

  4. Alasdair MacIntyre, Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (University of Notre Dame Press, 1988);

    Google Scholar 

  5. Jean Porter, The Recovery of Virtue: The Relevance of Aquinas for Christian Ethics (Louisville: Westminster/John Knox Press, 1990);

    Google Scholar 

  6. Jean Porter, Nature as Reason: A Thomistic Theory of the Natural Law (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 2005).

    Google Scholar 

  7. For an account of some of the differences between Aristotle and Aquinas on the passions, see Eleonore Stump, ‘The Non-Aristotelian Character of Aquinas’s Ethics: Aquinas on the Passions’ in Sarah Coakley (ed.), Faith, Rationality, and the Passions (Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, 2012).

    Google Scholar 

  8. See, for example, Augustine, Confessions, Henry Chadwick (trans.) (Oxford University Press, 2008), 1.1.1, 4.12.18. See also Augustine, Expositions of the Psalms, John E. Rotelle (ed.), Maria Boulding (trans.), 6 vols (Brooklyn: New City Press, 2000).

    Google Scholar 

  9. For a recent look at Baxter with regard to community and ethics, see James Calvin Davis, ‘Pardoning Puritanism: Community, Character, and Forgiveness in the Work of Richard Baxter’, Journal of Religious Ethics, 29(2) (2001): 283–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. I show this in more detail in Nathaniel A. Warne, ‘Metaphysics, Emotions and the Flourishing Life’ in Douglas James Davies and Nathaniel A. Warne (eds), Emotions and Religious Dynamics (Farnham: Ashgate, 2014), 75–94.

    Google Scholar 

  11. For a very clear and lengthy analysis of the cognitive aspect of the soul and its relation to the rational soul in Aristotle, see Kristján Kristjánsson, Aristotle, Emotions, and Education (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2007), 20–25.

    Google Scholar 

  12. For an interesting discussion of moderation in Reformation England, see Ethan H. Shagan, The Rule of Moderation: Violence, Religion and the Politics of Restraint in Early Modern England (Cambridge University Press, 2011), 7–29.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  13. Aristotle, ‘The Nicomachean Ethics’ in Jonathan Barnes (ed.), The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, revised by J.O. Urmson Ross, vol. 2 (Princeton University Press, 1984), 1106b29–35.

    Google Scholar 

  14. See Fenner, A Treatise of the Affections, 4–5, 7; Alec Ryrie, Being Protestant in Reformation Britain (Oxford University Press, 2013), 17–20.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  15. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, Fathers of English Dominican Province (trans.) (Notre Dame: Ava Maria Press, 1948), I–II 3.2 (hereinafter ST).

    Google Scholar 

  16. Ibid., II–II 23.1. For a more in-depth look at ‘communication’ with the divine, see J. Bobik, ‘Aquinas on Communicatio, the Foundation of Friendship and Caritas’, Modern Schoolman, 65 (1986): 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Paul Wadell, Friendship and the Moral Life (University of Notre Dame Press, 1989), 122.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Thomas Aquinas, Commentary on Aristotle’s ‘Nicomachean Ethics’, C.J. Litzinger (trans.) (Notre Dame: Dumb Ox Books, 1993).

    Google Scholar 

  19. For more on the medieval break with Aristotle on friendship, see Daniel Schwartz, Aquinas on Friendship (Oxford University Press, 2007), 43–5; Aquinas, ST, II–II 26.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  20. Steve Summers, Friendship: Exploring its Implications for the Church in Postmodernity (London: T & T Clark, 2009), 88.

    Google Scholar 

  21. William W. Young, The Politics of Praise: Naming God and Friendship in Aquinas and Derrida (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2007), 8.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Aelred of Rievaulx (1109–67) addressed this problem of unequal friends by following Cicero in claiming that reciprocity is essential to true friendship, but charity demands that we extend benevolence even to those untrustworthy enemies we cannot entrust our secrets to. Aelred agrees with Aquinas that charity should extend to all, but that is not the same thing as saying that friendship should extend to all. See Aelred of Rievaulx, On Spiritual Friendship, Marsha L. Dutton (ed.), Lawrence C. Braceland (trans.) (Collegeville: Cistercian Publications, 2010).

    Google Scholar 

  23. M.M. Knappen, ‘The Puritan Character as Seen in the Diaries’ in Two Elizabethan Puritan Diaries (Gloucester: American Society of Church History, 1966), 15.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Francis J. Bremer, Puritanism (Oxford University Press, 2009), 61.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  25. For more on the Puritan practice of conference, see Joanne J. Jung, Godly Conversation: Rediscovering the Puritan Practice of Conference (Grand Rapids: Reformation Heritage Books, 2011).

    Google Scholar 

  26. Patrick Collinson, The Religion of Protestants: The Church in English Society 1559– 1625 (Oxford University Press, 1984), 271.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ibid., 99–113; Rosalind Hursthouse, On Virtue Ethics (Oxford University Press, 1999).

    Google Scholar 

  28. One point where the Puritan discussion of virtue is distinctive is an emphasis on the workplace specifically in the doctrine of calling or vocation. According to Lee Hardy, this is a place where Catholics had to adopt Protestant perspectives. Lee Hardy, The Fabric of This World: Inquiries into Calling, Career Choice, and the Design of Human Work (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1990), 44.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2016 Nathaniel Warne

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Warne, N. (2016). Emotions and the Development of Virtue in Puritan Thought: An Investigation of Puritan Friendship. In: Ryrie, A., Schwanda, T. (eds) Puritanism and Emotion in the Early Modern World. Christianities in the Trans-Atlantic World, 1500–1800. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137490988_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics