Skip to main content
Log in

The effect of unconditional preferences on Sen’s paradox

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Sen’s Liberal paradox describes a conflict between weak Pareto, minimal liberalism, and either transitivity or a best element over a domain of individual preferences. This paper examines variants of that paradox with varying amounts of unconditional preferences. We define a notion of unconditional preferences under which, in the absence of Pareto, there can be no cycles. We then define a stronger condition, that makes an individual’s preferences for her own private attributes independent of all other attributes. Under this assumption, there can be no cycles with or without Pareto. We also show there exists a social decision function satisfying those conditions. We then determine the probability of a cycle assuming a much weaker independence condition that does not restrict the domain. This probability converges to one as the number of non-private attributes within the social states increases. Finally, we use simulations to determine the probability that liberalism and Pareto conflict with best elements, maximal elements, and transitivity separately.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A social state is “a complete description of society including every individual’s position in it” (Sen, 1970, 152). Sen (1970) uses the terms “social states” and “alternatives” interchangeably, but settles on alternatives for his theorem. We use social states to reduce confusion about a personal realm and a social realm (Barry, 1986).

  2. Sen proved his theorem for weak individual orderings but the theorem also applies to purely strict individual orderings.

  3. Sen (1979) defines a social ordering as reflexive (\(\forall s_j \in \mathcal{S}: s_j \succeq s_j\)), weakly complete (\(\forall s_j,s_k \in \mathcal{S}: s_j \succeq s_k\) or \(s_k \succeq s_j\)), and weakly transitive (\(\forall s_j, s_k, s_l, \in \mathcal{S}: (s_j \succeq s_k\) & \(s_k \succeq s_l) \rightarrow s_j \succeq s_l\)).

  4. Social state \(s_j \in \mathcal{S}\) is a best element of \(\mathcal{S}\) if and only if \(\forall s_k: s_k \in \mathcal{S} \rightarrow s_j \succeq s_k\) (Sen 1979, 10).

  5. Consider Lady Chatterley’s Lover for example. If Prude and Lewd had IID preferences, Prude would prefer (neither read) to (only Prude reads), and (only Lewd reads) to (only Prude reads); Lewd would prefer (only Lewd reads) to (neither reads), and (neither reads) to (only Prude reads). In this case, \(\mathbf{P} \) and \(\mathbf{L} _j\), \(j=1,2\) would create a transitive order with a best element, regardless of their remaining binary preferences.

  6. \(s_k \sim s_j\) indicates social indifference between \(s_k\) and \(s_j\).

  7. For \(N=d_0=d=2\), IC preferences are a generated by \(p=0.5\).

  8. As a first step in creating the PCP distribution, we randomly choose an order of preferences for each individual using IC. As a second step, for each level \(\ell \) and each individual i, we randomly choose i’s type (\(\alpha \) or \(\gamma \)) with probabilities Pr(i is type \(\alpha \) on level \(\ell ) = p\) and Pr(i is type \(\gamma \) on level \(\ell ) = 1-p\). If \(\alpha \) preferences are drawn for individual i on level \(\ell \), we flip a coin to determine whether \(\{a_i = 0\} \succ _i\, \{a_i = 1\}\) or \(\{a_i = 1\} \succ _i \,\{a_i = 0\}\) on level \(\ell \) and rearrange i’s preferences accordingly. If \(\gamma \) preferences are drawn for individual i on level \(\ell \), we shuffle an individual’s preferences for the set of social states they are decisive over on level \(\ell \) until it rules out \(\alpha \) preferences for that individual, thus creating \(\gamma \) preferences for the individual on level \(\ell \). The effect of this procedure is it maintains the preference type drawn for an individual on a level while creating IC distributed preferences for all other binary pairs.

  9. With a half-million trials, we are \(95\%\) confident that the true probability is within 0.0015 of the relative frequencies reported. This statement is based on the standard deviation of a univariate proportion, \(\sqrt{{\eta (1-\eta )}\over {T}}\), where \(\eta = 0.5\), the worst case value, and T is the number of trials.

  10. With incompleteness, a social ranking can be transitive for two trivial reasons: (1) the antecedent for transitivity is false (i.e., \(\not \exists \) \(x,y,z: x \succ y\) and \(y \succ z\)) or, (2) the consequent is unknown (i.e. x?z).

  11. In contrast, Igersheim (2013) prohibits invasive preferences if they interfere with a libertarian right.

References

  • Arrow, K. J. (1951). Social choice and individual values. Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barry, B. (1986). Lady Chatterley’s lover and doctor Fischer’s bomb party: liberalism, pareto optimality, and the problem of objectionable preferences. In J. Elster & A. Hylland (Eds.), Foundations of social choice theory (pp. 11–43). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blau, J. H. (1975). Liberal values and independence. Review of Economic Studies, 42(3), 395–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chung, H. (2019). The impossibility of liberal rights in a diverse world. Economics and Philosophy, 35(1), 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dougherty, K. L., & Edward, J. (2011). The calculus of consent and constitutional design. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dougherty, K. L., & Heckelman, J. C. (2020). The probability of violating Arrow’s conditions. European Journal of Political Economy, 65, 101936.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowding, K. (2016). Power, luck and freedom: Collected essays. Manchester University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Farrell, M. J. (1976). Liberalism in the theory of social choice. Review of Economic Studies, 43(1), 3–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein, W. V. (1994). The expected likelihood of transitivity: A survey. Theory and Decision, 37(2), 175–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein, W. V. (2002). Condorcet’s paradox and the likelihood of its occurrence: Different perspectives on balanced preferences. Theory and Decision, 52(2), 171–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein, W. V., & Lepelley, D. (2010). Voting paradoxes and group coherence: The condorcet efficiency of voting rules. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (1973). Manipulation of voting schemes: A general result. Econometrica, 41(4), 587–601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (1974). A pareto-consistent libertarian claim. Journal of Economic Theory, 7(4), 388–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hammond, P. J. (1998). Rigths, free exchange and widespread externalities. In J.-F. Laslier, M. Fleurbaey, N. Gravel, & A. Trannoy (Eds.), Freedom in economics: New perspectives in normative analysis (pp. 139–157). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Igersheim, H. (2013). Invoking a cartesian product structure on social states. Theory and Decision, 74(4), 463–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, C. (2004). The impossibility of a Paretian Republican? Some comments on Pettit and Sen. Economics and Philosophy, 20, 65–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Munger, M. C. (2008). Economic choice, political decision, and the problem of limits. Public Choice, 137(3–4), 507–522.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piggins, A., & Salerno, G. (2016). Sen cycles and externalities. Economics Letters, 149, 25–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Risse, M. (2001). What to make of the liberal paradox? Theory and Decision, 50(2), 169–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saari, D. G. (2001). Decisions and elections: Explaining the unexpected. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Saari, D. G. (2008). Disposing dictators, demystifying voting paradoxes. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Saari, D. G., & Petron, A. (2006). Negative externalities and Sen’s liberalism theorem. Economic Theory, 28(2), 265–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Satterthwaite, M. A. (1975). Strategy-proofness and Arrow’s conditions: Existence and correspondence theorems for voting procedures and social welfare functions. Journal of Economic Theory, 10(2), 187–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, T. (2018). Cycles and social choice: The true and unabridged story of a most protean paradox. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. K. (1970). The impossibility of a Paretian liberal. The Journal of Political Economy, 78(1), 152–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. K. (1979). Collective choice and social welfare. Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sher, I. (2018). Evaluating allocations of freedom. The Economic Journal, 128(612), F65–F94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suzumura, K. (2011). Welfarism, individual rights, and procedural fairness. In K. Arrow, A. Sen, & K. Suzumura (Eds.), Handbook of social choice and welfare (Vol. 2, pp. 605–684). Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Keith L. Dougherty.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

We thank Jac Heckelman for comments on an early version of this paper.

Supplementary Information

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

Supplementary file 1 (pdf 131 KB)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dougherty, K.L., Edward, J. The effect of unconditional preferences on Sen’s paradox. Theory Decis 93, 427–447 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-021-09863-8

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-021-09863-8

Keywords

Navigation