Skip to main content
Log in

On temperance and risk spreading

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper shows that temperance is the highest order risk preference condition for which spreading N independent and unfair risks provides the highest level of welfare than any other possible allocations of risks. These results are also interpreted through the concept of N-superadditivity of the utility premium. This paper provides a novel application of temperance, not in terms of two risks as it is common, but in terms of N risks.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Ebert et al. (2017) and Courbage et al. (2018), respectively, reinterpret Eeckhoudt and Schlesinger (2006)’s results by showing that temperance ensures mutual aggravation, respectively, mutual mitigation, of risk changes.

  2. Obviously, the lottery \((0,X_{1}+X_{2},X_{3})\) is equivalent in terms of welfare to the lottery \((X_{1}+X_{2},0,X_{3})\) that is equivalent to the lottery \((X_{1}+X_{2},X_{3},0)\) since lotteries are three state equiprobable lotteries.

  3. Risks spreading refers, throughout the paper, to spreading the N risks each over N states.

  4. Note that there exists cases where each risk \(X_{i}\) is such that \( E(X_{i})\le 0\) and where it is impossible to compare random variables \(X_{i} \) with zero via a statistical rule. See Denuit et al. (1998) and Denuit et al. (2001) for more details.

  5. Note that under simple and usual regularity conditions (u defined over \( \mathbb {R}^{+}\), non-satiation and bounded marginal utility tending to plus infinity), item (b) of Proposition 1 holds when the DM is only temperate without requiring risk aversion and prudence (see Menegatti 2014, Propositions 2 and 3). Indeed, under these simple conditions, Menegatti (2014) shows that prudence implies risk aversion and that temperance implies prudence.

  6. In item (b) of Proposition 1, we assume that each \(X_{i}\) is dominated by 0 via second-order stochastic dominance as it is usual in economics since Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970). Note that second-order stochastic dominance implies stochastic dominance of higher orders. Consequently, our results hold in cases where \(X_{i}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}-s}0\)\(\forall s\ge 3\). If, instead of the Rothschild and Stiglitz assumption, we assume that \(X_{i}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}-s}0\) with \(s\ge 3\), it is easy to show that item (b) of Proposition 1 writes then as follows: for all mixed risk averse from 1 to 2s decision-makers (\((-1)^{n+1}u^{(n)}>0\)\(\forall n=1,\ldots ,2s\)) when \( X_{i}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}-s}0\).

  7. In the case where the L background risks are not introduced in each state, they can be then considered as additional risks. The DM faces then \(N+L\) risks. If we assume \(\tilde{\epsilon }_{l}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{k}}0\) with \(k=1,2,\) i.e. if we assume that these risks share the same properties as \(X_{i}\) for all i, this case brings us back to the previous remark (i.e. the case with a number of risks greater than the number of states).

References

  • Caballé, J., & Pomansky, A. (1996). Mixed risk aversion. Journal of Economic Theory, 71, 485–513.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Courbage, C., Loubergé, H., & Rey, B. (2018). On the properties of high-order non-monetary measures for risks. Geneva Risk and Insurance Review, 43, 77–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Denuit, M., Lefevre, C., & Scarsini, M. (2001). On s-convexity and risk aversion. Theory and Decision, 50(3), 239–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Denuit, M., Lefevre, C., & Shaked, M. (1998). The s-convex orders among real random variables, with applications. Mathematical Inequalities and Application, 1(4), 585–613.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ebert, S. (2013). Even (mixed) risk lovers are prudent: Comment. American Economic Review, 103(4), 1536–1537.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ebert, S., Nocetti, D. C., & Schlesinger, H. (2017). Greater mutual aggravation. Management Science, 64(6), 2473–2972.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eeckhoudt, L., & Schlesinger, H. (2006). Putting risk in its proper place. American Economic Review, 96, 280–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eeckhoudt, L., Schlesinger, H., & Tsetlin, E. (2009). Apportioning risks via stochastic dominance. Journal of Economic Theory, 113, 1–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ekern, S. (1980). Increasing Nth degree risk. Economic Letters, 6, 329–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M., & Savage, L. J. (1948). The utility analysis of choices involving risk. Journal of Political Economy, 56, 279–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gollier, C. (1996). Decreasing absolute prudence: Characterization and applications to second-best risk sharing. European Economic Review, 40(9), 1799–1815.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gollier, C., & Pratt, J. W. (1996). Risk vulnerability and the tempering effect of background risk. Econometrica, 64, 1109–1123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kimball, M. S. (1992). Precautionary motives for holding assets. In P. Newman, M. Milgate, & J. Falwell (Eds.), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Money and Finance. London: Macmilan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menegatti, M. (2014). New results on the relationship among risk aversion, prudence and temperance. European Journal of Operational Research, 232, 613–617.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nachman, D. C. (1982). Preservation of “More Risk Averse” under expectations. Journal of Economic Theory, 28, 361–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rothschild, M., & Stiglitz, J. (1970). ‘Increasing risk: I. A definition’. Journal of Economic Theory, 2, 225–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Louis Eeckhoudt as well as two anonymous referees for valuable comments and discussions. This research has benefited from the financial support of IDEXLYON from Université de Lyon (project INDEPTH) within the Programme Investissements d’Avenir (ANR- 16-IDEX-005).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christophe Courbage.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix: Proof of Proposition 1

Appendix: Proof of Proposition 1

The proof uses the theorem of Eeckhoudt et al. (2009) and its corollary.

Theorem

(Eeckhoudt et al. 2009) Suppose that\(Y_{i}\) dominates \(\eta \)\(_{i}\) via \(n_{i}\)th order stochastic dominance for\(i=1,2\) (\(\eta _{1}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{n_{1}}}Y_{1}\)and\(\eta _{2}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{n_{2}}}Y_{2}\)) and suppose that\(\eta _{1},\eta _{2},Y_{1},Y_{2}\)are mutually independent risks. The 50–50 lottery\([\eta _{1}+Y_{2},Y_{1}+\eta _{2}]\)dominates the 50–50 i \([\eta _{1}+\eta _{2},Y_{1}+Y_{2}]\) via \((n_{1}+n_{2})\)th order stochastic dominance.

Corollary

(Eeckhoudt et al. 2009) Suppose that\(Y_{i}\)dominates\(\eta _{i}\) via \( n_{i}\)th order Ekern dominance for\(i=1,2\) (\(\eta _1 \preceq _{{\text {Ekern}}_{n_1}} Y_1\)and\(\eta _2 \preceq _{{\text {Ekern}}_{n_2}} Y_2\)) and suppose that\(\eta _{1},\eta _{2},Y_{1},Y_{2}\)are mutually independent risks. The 50–50 lottery\([\eta _{1}+Y_{2},Y_{1}+ \eta _{2}]\)dominates the 50–50 lottery\([\eta _{1}+ \eta _{2},Y_{1}+Y_{2}]\) via \((n_{1}+n_{2})\)th order Ekern dominance.

When \(Y_{1}=Y_{2}=0\) and using the Expected Utility Theory model, the EST (2009) theorem and its corollary, respectively, can be rewritten as follows:

EST (2009) Theorem: the inequality \(E[u(x+\eta _{1})]+E[u(x+\eta _{2})]\ge u(x)+E[u(x+\eta _{1}+\eta _{2})]\) holds for all utility function u such that \((-1)^{(s+1)}u^{(s)}>0\)\(\forall s=1, \ldots , n_{1}+n_{2}\).

EST (2009) Corollary: the inequality \(E[u(x+\eta _{1})]+E[u(x+\eta _{2})]\ge u(x)+E[u(x+\eta _{1}+\eta _{2})]\) holds for all utility function u such that \((-1)^{(n_1+n_2+1)}u^{(n_1+n_2)}>0\).

In the case \(N=2\), Proposition 1 and Corollary 1, respectively, coincide with the EST theorem and its corollary. To prove the result in the case of N risks with \(N \ge 3\), we use the property of convolution stability of \(SD_{k}\) (see Propositions 3–11 in Denuit et al. (1998) for more details):

Convolution stability propertySuppose two random independent variables \(X_1\) and \(X_2\)such that \(X_{1}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{k}}0\) and \(X_{2} \preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{k}}0\) for all\(k=1,2\), then\(X_{1}+X_{2}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{k}} 0\) for all\(k=1,2\).

We make the proof of Eq. (6) by steps. Let us rewrite Eq. (6) as follows:

$$\begin{aligned}&\Bigl (\{X_{i}\}_{N}^{N}\Bigr )\succeq _1 \Bigl (\{X_{i}\}_{N}^{N-1}\Bigr ) \succeq _2 \Bigl (\{X_{i}\}_{N}^{N-2}\Bigr ) \succeq _3 \Bigl (\{X_{i}\}_{N}^{N-3} \Bigr ) \nonumber \\&\quad \succeq _4 \cdots \succeq _{N-2} \Bigl (\{X_{i}\}_{N}^{2}\Bigr ) \succeq _{N-1} \Bigl (\{X_{i}\}_{N}^{1} \Bigr ), \end{aligned}$$
(11)

where indexes \(1,2,\ldots , N-1\) indicate the different steps. In step 1, we show the first part of the preference relation, \(\Bigl (\{X_{i}\}_{N}^{N} \Bigr )\succeq _1 \Bigl (\{X_{i}\}_{N}^{N-1}\Bigr )\), in step 2 we show the second part of the preference relation, \(\Bigl (\{X_{i}\}_{N}^{N-1}\Bigr ) \succeq _2 \Bigl (\{X_{i}\}_{N}^{N-2}\Bigr )\), in step 3 we show the third part of the preference relation, \(\Bigl (\{X_{i}\}_{N}^{N-2}\Bigr ) \succeq _2 \Bigl (\{X_{i}\}_{N}^{N-3}\Bigr )\), etc.

Step 1\(\Bigl (\{X_{i}\}_{N}^{N}\Bigr )\succeq _{1}\Bigl ( \{X_{i}\}_{N}^{N-1}\Bigr )\) (P1)

The left-hand side term of (P1) writes as \(\sum _{i=1}^{N}E[u(x+X_{i})]\). In the set of N risks \(X_{i}\), we choose two risks that we name \(X_{t}\) and \(X_{l}\), and that we regroup into a single risk \(X_{t}+X_{l}\) in the right-hand side term of (P1). Using this, (P1) rewrites as

$$\begin{aligned}&\sum _{i=1}^{N}E[u(x+X_{i})]+E[u(x+X_{t})]+E[u(x+X_{l})]\\&\quad \ge \sum _{i=1}^{N}E[u(x+X_{i})]+E[u(x+X_{t}+X_{l})]+u(x) \end{aligned}$$

for all \(t\le N\), \(l\le N\), \(t\ne l\), \(i\ne t\) and \(i\ne l\) that is equivalent to

$$\begin{aligned} E[u(x+X_{t})]+E[u(x+X_{l})]\ge +E[u(x+X_{t}+X_{l})]+u(x) \end{aligned}$$

which holds following EST (2009) theorem for all u such that \( (-1)^{(s+1)}u^{(s)}>0\)\(\forall s=1,\ldots ,2k\) if \(X_{1}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{k}}Y_{1}\) and \(X_{2}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{k}}Y_{2}\), \(k=1,2\). This inequality also holds following EST (2009) corollary for all u such that \(u^{(4)}<0\) in the particular case where risks are zero-mean risks, i.e. \(X_{1}\preceq _{{\text {Ekern}}_{2}}Y_{1}\) and \(X_{2}\preceq _{{\text {Ekern}}_{2}}Y_{2}\).

In the expression \(\sum _{i=1}^{N}E[u(x+X_{i})]+E[u(x+X_{t}+X_{l})]+u(x)\) (with \(t\le N\), \(l\le N\), \(t\ne l\), \(i\ne t\) and \(i\ne l\)), we can consider that we have \((N-1)\) risks. Indeed, let us write \(X_{i}^{1}=X_{i}\)\( \forall i=1,\ldots ,N-2\), \(i\ne t\) and \(i\ne l\), and \( X_{N-1}^{1}=X_{t}+X_{l}\), then the above expression can be equivalently rewritten as \(\sum _{i=1}^{N-1}E[u(x+X_{i}^{1})]+u(x)\) with \(X_{i}^{1}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{k}}0\)\(\forall i\), for all \(k=1,2\) following the convolution stability property. Using the same technique as the one used at the beginning of step 1 to rewrite \(\sum _{i=1}^{N}E[u(x+X_{i})]\), the expression \( \sum _{i=1}^{N-1}E[u(x+X_{i}^{1})]+u(x)\) can thus be equivalently rewritten as \(\sum _{i=1}^{N-1}E[u(x+X_{i}^{1})]+E[u(x+X_{t}^{1})]+E[u(x+X_{l}^{1})]+u(x)\) for all \(t\le N-1\), \(l\le N-1\), \(i\ne t\) and \(i\ne l\).

Step 2\(\Bigl (\{X_{i}\}_{N}^{N-1}\Bigr )\succeq _{2}\Bigl ( \{X_{i}\}_{N}^{N-2}\Bigr )\) (P2)

Following the same methodology as the one used in step 1, (P2) rewrites equivalently as

$$\begin{aligned}&\sum _{i=1}^{N-1}E[u(x+X_{i}^{1})]+E[u(x+X_{t}^{1})]+E[u(x+X_{l}^{1})]+u(x) \\&\quad \ge \sum _{i=1}^{N-1}E[u(x+X_{i}^{1})]+E[u(x+X_{t}^{1}+X_{l}^{1})]+2u(x) \end{aligned}$$

for all \(t\le N-1\), \(l\le N-1\), \(t\ne l\), \(i\ne t\) and \(i\ne l\) that is equivalent to

$$\begin{aligned} E[u(x+X_{t}^{1})+E[u(x+X_{l}^{1})\ge E[u(x+X_{t}^{1}+X_{l}^{1})+u(x) \end{aligned}$$

which holds following EST (2009) theorem for all u such that \( (-1)^{(s+1)}u^{(s)}>0\)\(\forall s=1,\ldots ,2k\) if \(X_{1}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{k}}Y_{1}\) and \(X_{2}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{k}}Y_{2}\), \(k=1,2\). This inequality also holds following EST (2009) corollary for all u such that \(u^{(4)}<0\) in the particular case where risks are zero-mean risks, i.e. \(X_{1}\preceq _{{\text {Ekern}}_{2}}Y_{1}\) and \(X_{2}\preceq _{{\text {Ekern}}_{2}}Y_{2}\).

In the expression \( \sum _{i=1}^{N-1}E[u(x+X_{i}^{1})]+E[u(x+X_{t}^{1}+X_{l}^{1})]+2u(x)\), we can consider that we have \((N-2)\) risks \(X_{i}^{2}\) (i.e. \((N-3)\) risks \( X_{i}^{1}\) and 1 risk \(X_{t}^{1}+X_{l}^{1}\)). Thus, it can be equivalently rewritten as \(\sum _{i=1}^{N-2}E[u(x+X_{i}^{2})]+2u(x)\) with \(X_{i}^{2}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{k}}0\) for all \(k=1,2\) following the convolution stability property. It can also be rewritten as \( \sum _{i=1}^{N-2}E[u(x+X_{i}^{2})]+E[u(x+X_{t}^{2})]+E[u(x+X_{l}^{2})]+2u(x)\) for all \(t\le N-2\), \(l\le N-2\), \(t\ne l\), \(i\ne t\) and \(i\ne l\).

Step 3\(\Bigl (\{X_{i}\}_{N}^{N-2}\Bigr )\succeq _{3}\Bigl ( \{X_{i}\}_{N}^{N-3}\Bigr )\) (P3)

Following the same methodology as the one used in step 2, (P3) rewrites equivalently as

$$\begin{aligned}&\sum _{i=1}^{N-2}E[u(x+X_{i}^{2})]+E[u(x+X_{t}^{2})]+E[u(x+X_{l}^{2})]+2u(x) \\&\quad \ge \sum _{i=1}^{N-2}E[u(x+X_{i}^{2})]+E[u(x+X_{t}^{2}+X_{l}^{2})]+3u(x) \end{aligned}$$

for all \(t\le N-2\), \(l\le N-2\), \(t\ne l\), \(i\ne t\) and \(i\ne l\) that is equivalent to

$$\begin{aligned} E[u(x+X_{t}^{2})+E[u(x+X_{l}^{2})\ge +E[u(x+X_{t}^{2}+X_{l}^{2})]+u(x) \end{aligned}$$

which holds following EST (2009) theorem for all u such that \( (-1)^{(s+1)}u^{(s)}>0\)\(\forall s=1,\ldots ,2k\) if \(X_{1}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{k}}Y_{1}\) and \(X_{2}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{k}}Y_{2}\), \(k=1,2\). This inequality also holds following EST (2009) corollary for all u such that \(u^{(4)}<0\) in the particular case where risks are zero-mean risks, i.e. \(X_{1}\preceq _{{\text {Ekern}}_{2}}Y_{1}\) and \(X_{2}\preceq _{{\text {Ekern}}_{2}}Y_{2}\).

In the expression \(\sum _{i=1}^{N-2}E[u(x+X_{i}^{2})]+E[u(x+X_{t}^{2}+X_{l}^{2})]+3u(x)\), we can consider that we have \((N-4)\) risks \(X_{i}^{3}\) (i.e. \((N-2)\) risks \( X_{i}^{2}\) and 1 risk \(X_{t}^{2}+X_{l}^{2}\)). Thus, it can be equivalently rewritten as \(\sum _{i=1}^{N-3}E[u(x+X_{i}^{3})]+3u(x)\) with \(X_{i}^{3}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{k}}0\) for all \(k=1,2\) following the convolution stability property. It can also be rewritten as \( \sum _{i=1}^{N-3}E[u(x+X_{i}^{3})]+E[u(x+X_{t}^{3})]+E[u(x+X_{l}^{3})]+3u(x)\) for all \(t\le N-3\), \(l\le N-3\), \(t\ne l\), \(i\ne t\) and \(i\ne l\).

Step m\(\Bigl (\{X_{i}\}_{N}^{N-(m-1)}\Bigr )\succeq _{m}\Bigl ( \{X_{i}\}_{N}^{N-m}\Bigr )\) (Pm)

(Pm) rewrites equivalently as

$$\begin{aligned}&\sum _{i=1}^{N-(m-1)} E[u(x+X_i^{m-1})] + E[u(x+X_t^{m-1})] + E[u(x+X_l^{m-1})] + (m-1)u(x) \\&\quad \ge \sum _{i=1}^{N-(m-1)} E[u(x+X_i^{m-1})] + E[u(x+X_t^{m-1}+X_l^{m-1})] +mu(x) \end{aligned}$$

for all \(t\le N-(m-1)\), \(l\le N-(m-1)\), \(t\ne l\), \(i\ne t\) and \(i\ne l\) that is equivalent to

$$\begin{aligned} E[u(x+X_{t}^{m-1})+E[u(x+X_{l}^{m-1})\ge +E[u(x+X_{t}^{m-1}+X_{l}^{m-1})]+u(x) \end{aligned}$$

which holds following EST (2009) theorem for all u such that \( (-1)^{(s+1)}u^{(s)}>0\)\(\forall s=1,\ldots ,2k\) if \(X_{1}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{k}}Y_{1}\) and \(X_{2}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{k}}Y_{2}\), \(k=1,2\). This inequality also holds following EST (2009) corollary for all u such that \(u^{(4)}<0\) in the particular case where risks are zero-mean risks, i.e. \(X_{1}\preceq _{{\text {Ekern}}_{2}}Y_{1}\) and \(X_{2}\preceq _{{\text {Ekern}}_{2}}Y_{2}\).

In the expression \( \sum _{i=1}^{N-(m-1)}E[u(x+X_{i}^{m-1})]+E[u(x+X_{t}^{m-1}+X_{l}^{m-1})]+mu(x) \), we can consider that we have \((N-m)\) risks \(X_{i}^{m}\) (i.e. \((N-m-1))\) risks \(X_{i}^{m-1}\) and 1 risk \(X_{t}^{m-1}+X_{l}^{m-1}\)). Thus, it can be equivalently rewritten as \( \sum _{i=1}^{N-m}E[u(x+X_{i}^{m})]+E[u(x+X_{t}^{m})]+E[u(x+X_{l}^{m})]+mu(x)\) with \(X_{i}^{m}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{k}}0\) for all \(k=1,2\) following the convolution stability property.

$$\begin{aligned} \ldots \end{aligned}$$

Step N-2\(\Bigl (\{X_{i}\}_{N}^{3}\Bigr )\succeq _{N-2} \Bigl ( \{X_{i}\}_{N}^{2}\Bigr )\)\((P(N-2))\)

\((P(N-2))\) rewrites equivalently as

$$\begin{aligned}&\sum _{i=1}^{N-(N-3)} E[u(x+X_i^{N-3})] + E[u(x+X_t^{N-3})] + E[u(x+X_l^{N-3})] + (N-3)u(x) \\&\quad \ge \sum _{i=1}^{N-(N-3)} E[u(x+X_i^{N-3})] + E[u(x+X_t^{N-3}+X_l^{N-3})] +(N-2)u(x) \end{aligned}$$

for all \(t\le N-(N-3)\), \(l\le N-(N-3)\), \(t\ne l\), \(i\ne t\) and \(i\ne l\) that is equivalent to

$$\begin{aligned} E[u(x+X_{t}^{N-3})+E[u(x+X_{l}^{N-3})\ge +E[u(x+X_{t}^{N-3}+X_{l}^{N-3})]+u(x) \end{aligned}$$

which holds following EST (2009) theorem for all u such that \( (-1)^{(s+1)}u^{(s)}>0\)\(\forall s=1,\ldots ,2k\) if \(X_{1}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{k}}Y_{1}\) and \(X_{2}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{k}}Y_{2}\), \(k=1,2\). This inequality also holds following EST (2009) corollary for all u such that \(u^{(4)}<0\) in the particular case where risks are zero-mean risks, i.e. \(X_{1}\preceq _{{\text {Ekern}}_{2}}Y_{1}\) and \(X_{2}\preceq _{{\text {Ekern}}_{2}}Y_{2}\).

In the expression \(\sum _{i=1}^{N-(N-3)} E[u(x+X_i^{N-3})] + E[u(x+X_t^{N-3}+X_l^{N-3})] +(N-2)u(x)\), we have 2 risks \(X_i^{N-2}\) (1 risk \(X_i^{N-3}\) and 1 risk \(X_t^{N-3}+X_l^{N-3}\)). Thus, it can be equivalently rewritten as \(\sum _{i=1}^{2} E[u(x+X_i^{N-2})] + (N-2) u(x)\) with \(X_{i}^{N-2} \preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{k}} 0\) for all \(k=1,2\) following the convolution stability property.

Step N-1 \(\Bigl (\{X_{i}\}_{N}^{2}\Bigr )\succeq _{N-1} \Bigl ( \{X_{i}\}_{N}^{1}\Bigr )\) \((P(N-1))\)

\((P(N-1))\) rewrites equivalently as

\(\sum _{i=1}^{2}E[u(x+X_{i}^{N-2})]+(N-2)u(x)\ge E[u(x+X_{1}^{N-2}+X_{2}^{N-2})]+(N-1)u(x)\) which holds following EST (2009) theorem for all u such that \((-1)^{(s+1)}u^{(s)}>0\)\(\forall s=1,\ldots ,2k \) if \(X_{1}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{k}}Y_{1}\) and \(X_{2}\preceq _{{\text {SD}}_{k}}Y_{2}\), \( k=1,2\). This inequality also holds following EST (2009) corollary for all u such that \(u^{(4)}<0\) in the particular case where risks are zero-mean risks, i.e. \(X_{1}\preceq _{{\text {Ekern}}_{2}}Y_{1}\) and \(X_{2}\preceq _{{\text {Ekern}}_{2}}Y_{2}\).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Courbage, C., Rey, B. On temperance and risk spreading. Theory Decis 88, 527–539 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-019-09737-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-019-09737-0

Keywords

Navigation