Skip to main content
Log in

A logic of knowing why

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

When we say “I know why he was late”, we know not only the fact that he was late, but also an explanation of this fact. We propose a logical framework of “knowing why” inspired by the existing formal studies on why-questions, scientific explanation, and justification logic. We introduce the \({{\mathcal {K}}{}\textit{y}}_i\) operator into the language of epistemic logic to express “agent i knows why \(\varphi \)” and propose a Kripke-style semantics of such expressions in terms of knowing an explanation of \(\varphi \). We obtain two sound and complete axiomatizations w.r.t. two different model classes depending on different assumptions about introspection. Finally we connect our logic with justification logic technically by providing an alternative semantics and an in-depth comparison on various design choices.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. “Wh” stands for the wh-question words.

  2. Nomic explanations are explanation in terms of laws of nature.

  3. There are also various dimensions of each paradigm, e.g, probabilistic versus non-probabilistic, singular events or laws to be explained.

  4. See Schurz (1995) and Weber et al. (2013) for critical surveys.

  5. LP was invented to give an arithmetic semantics to intuitionistic logic under the Brouwer-Heyting-Kolmogorov provability interpretation.

  6. Similar ideas also appeared in van Benthem (1991).

  7. According to our semantics to be introduced later, it is also allowed to know why for different reasons (for different people), which might help to model mutual misunderstanding.

  8. E.g., there is no proof for the consistency of PA within PA, given PA is consistent.

  9. Though as Johan van Benthem pointed out via personal communication, in many cases there is often a best or shortest explanation for the fact.

  10. Note that here \(\rightarrow \) is a material implication which should not be treated as an arbitrary conditional.

  11. Martin Stokhof suggested an example where one explains to the other why he is the best candidate for a job, but in fact he is not, and his explanation may base on false premises.

  12. The situation is like in Padmanabha et al. (2018) where the bundled modality \(\exists \Box \) cannot distinguish constant domain and increasing domain models.

  13. Note that this is not one of the four introspection axioms of \({{\mathcal {K}}{}\textit{y}}_i\) mentioned earlier.

  14. The “S5 version” of justification logic \(\mathbf {JT45}\) also adds another condition about negative introspection: \(\overline{{\mathcal {E}}(t, \varphi )} \subseteq {\mathcal {E}}(?t, \lnot (t{}:{}\varphi ))\), and requires strong evidence, where ? is a new operation for justification terms in the language, cf. Artemov (2008). To simplify the discussion, we focus on \(\mathbf {LP}\) here.

  15. In the multi-agent setting, \(!_i\) was introduced to capture the proof check done by each agent (Yavorskaya 2006).

  16. The alternative semantics does not work if we just have only one evidence function.

  17. We may also discuss whether \({{\mathcal {K}}{}\textit{y}}_i\varphi \rightarrow {{\mathcal {K}}{}\textit{y}}_i{\mathcal {K}}_i\varphi \) is reasonable.

  18. There are also modal logic approaches to handle scientific explanations cf. e.g, Šešelja and Straßer (2013) and Sedlár and Halas (2015).

References

  • Artemov, S. (1995). Operational modal logic. Technical report MSI 9529, Cornell University.

  • Artemov, S. (2001). Explicit provability and constructive semantics. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 7(1), 1–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Artemov, S. (2006). Justified common knowledge. Theoretical Computer Science, 357(1), 4–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Artemov, S. (2008). The logic of justification. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 1(04), 477–513.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Artemov, S., & Nogina, E. (2005). Introducing justification into epistemic logic. Journal of Logic and Computation, 15(6), 1059–1073.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (1998). Philosophy of science. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bromberger, S. (1966). Questions. The Journal of Philosophy, 63(20), 597–606.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bucheli, S., Kuznets, R., & Studer, T. (2011). Justifications for common knowledge. Journal of Applied Non-classical Logics, 21(1), 35–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bucheli, S., Kuznets, R., & Studer, T. (2014). Realizing public announcements by justifications. Journal of Computer and System Sciences, 80(6), 1046–1066.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fagin, R., Halpern, J., Moses, Y., & Vardi, M. (1995). Reasoning about knowledge. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fan, J., Wang, Y., & van Ditmarsch, H. (2015). Contingency and knowing whether. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 8, 75–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitting, M. (2005). The logic of proofs, semantically. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 132(1), 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitting, M. (2008). A quantified logic of evidence. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 152(1), 67–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitting, M. (2016). Modal logics, justification logics, and realization. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 167(8), 615–648.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gattinger, M., van Eijck, J., & Wang, Y. (2017). Knowing values and public inspection. In Proceedings of ICLA ’17 (forthcoming).

  • Groenendijk, J., & Stokhof, M. (1982). Semantic analysis of wh-complements. Linguistics and Philosophy, 5(2), 175–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halpern, J. Y., & Pucella, R. (2011). Dealing with logical omniscience: Expressiveness and pragmatics. Artificial Intelligence, 175(1), 220–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. Mankato: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G., & Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science, 15(2), 135–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1962). Knowledge and belief: An introduction to the logic of the two notions (Vol. 181). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1981). On the logic of an interrogative model of scientific inquiry. Synthese, 47(1), 69–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1983). New foundations for a theory of questions and answers (pp. 159–190). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J., & Halonen, I. (1995). Semantics and pragmatics for why-questions. The Journal of Philosophy, 92(12), 636–657.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1981). Explanatory unification. Philosophy of Science, 48(4), 507–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koura, A. (1988). An approach to why-questions. Synthese, 74(2), 191–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuznets, R., & Studer, T. (2012). Justifications, ontology, and conservativity. In T. Bolander, T. Braüner, S. Ghilardi, & L. Moss (Eds.), Advances in modal logic (Vol. 9, pp. 437–458). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuznets, R., & Studer, T. (2013). Update as evidence: Belief expansion. In S. Artemov & A. Nerode (Eds.), Logical foundations of computer science, LFCS 2013, Springer, LNCS, Vol. 7734, pp. 266–279.

  • Kuznets, R., & Studer, T. (2019). Justification logic. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Padmanabha, A., Ramanujam, R., & Wang, Y. (2018). Bundled fragments of first-order modal logic: (Un)decidability. In Proceedings of FSTTCS 2018 (pp. 43:1–43:20).

  • Pischke, N. (2017). Dynamic extensions for the logic of knowing why with public announcements of formulas. arXiv e-prints 1707.05617.

  • Plaza, J. (2007). Logics of public communications. Synthese, 158(2), 165–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Renne, B. (2008). Dynamic epistemic logic with justification. PhD thesis, New York, NY, USA, aAI3310607.

  • Renne, B. (2012). Multi-agent justification logic: Communication and evidence elimination. Synthese, 185(1), 43–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (1995). Scientific explanation: A critical survey. Foundations of Science, 1(3), 429–465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (1999). Explanation as unification. Synthese, 120(1), 95–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2005). Explanations in science and the logic of why-questions: Discussion of the Halonen–Hintikka-approachand alternative proposal. Synthese, 143(1), 149–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sedlár, I., & Halas, J. (2015). Modal logics of abstract explanation frameworks. In Abstract in proceedings of CLMPS 15.

  • Šešelja, D., & Straßer, C. (2013). Abstract argumentation and explanation applied to scientific debates. Synthese, 190(12), 2195–2217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Benthem, J. (1991). Reflections on epistemic logic. Logique and Analyse, 34(133–134), 5–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Ditmarsch, H., Halpern, J. Y., van der Hoek, W., & Kooi, B. (Eds.). (2015). Handbook of epistemic logic. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wang, Y. (2015). A logic of knowing how. In Proceedings of LORI-V (pp. 392–405).

  • Wang, Y. (2017). A new modal framework for epistemic logic. In Proceedings of TARK ’17 (pp. 515–534).

  • Wang, Y., & Fan, J. (2013). Knowing that, knowing what, and public communication: Public announcement logic with Kv operators. In Proceedings of IJCAI’13 (pp. 1139–1146).

  • Wang, Y. (2018a). Beyond knowing that: A new generation of epistemic logics. In H. van Ditmarsch & G. Sandu (Eds.), Jaakko Hintikka on knowledge and game theoretical semantics, outstanding contributions to logic (Vol. 12, pp. 499–533). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wang, Y. (2018b). A logic of goal-directed knowing how. Synthese, 195(10), 4419–4439.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wang, Y., & Fan, J. (2014). Conditionally knowing what. Advances in Modal Logic, 10, 569–587.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, E., van Bouwel, J., & De Vreese, L. (2013). Scientific explanation. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Yavorskaya, T. (2006). Multi-agent explicit knowledge. In D. Grigoriev, J. Harrison, & E. A. Hirsch (Eds.), Proceedings of CSR 2006 (pp. 369–380). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank Albert Anglberger, Johan van Benthem, Huimin Dong, Mel Fitting, Dominik Klein, Fenrong Liu, Olivier Roy, Martin Stokhof, Che-Ping Su, Frank Veltman, Lu Wang, Wei Wang, Junhua Yu, Liying Zhang, and Yuncheng Zhou for discussions and useful suggestions on earlier versions of this paper. The insightful comments from the anonymous reviewers of this journal also helped in improving the paper. Yanjing Wang acknowledges the support from the National Program for Special Support of Eminent Professionals and NSSF major Project 12&ZD119. Thomas Studer is supported by the Swiss National Science Foundation Grant 200021_165549.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yanjing Wang.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Xu, C., Wang, Y. & Studer, T. A logic of knowing why. Synthese 198, 1259–1285 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02104-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02104-0

Keywords

Navigation