Skip to main content
Log in

Elections, the curse of competence and credence policies

  • Published:
Public Choice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Prope cottidie tibi hoc ad forum descendenti meditandum est: “Novus sum, consulatum peto, Roma est.”

Almost every day, when you go down to the forum, you should meditate: “I am a commoner. I want to become consul. This is Rome.”

(Q. Tullius Cicero, Commentarium Petitionis Consulatus)

Abstract

A returning political phenomenon is the impact of “office seekers” in democracies. We examine the consequences when the public faces a new type of two-dimensional uncertainty: whether a politician is competent, and whether a politician is concerned about the consequences of public utility decisions (statesman) or about public opinion (office seeker). We identify new timing distortions, as both competent and incompetent office seekers may take hasty or excessively delayed decisions in order to imitate statesmen or competent office holders. Thus, the public may benefit by disregarding the candidates’ competence and by reelecting candidates based solely on its belief as to whether a politician is a statesman. This “curse of competence” may explain why politicians are so concerned about being perceived as statesmen and why we may expect the largest distortions for credence policies.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. On the role of economic policy competence in US presidential elections, see Congleton and Zhang (2013).

  2. Our paper is complementary to other approaches that model the trade-offs of popular but potentially harmful policies. Bischoff and Siemers (2013) have offered an interesting approach in which voters may hold biased beliefs about economic outcomes and vote retrospectively. This causes parties to offer a mixture of popular, but bad, policies and less popular, but good, policies. See also Gersbach (2009).

  3. We will later examine whether equilibria exist in which PG and PB choose I with different probabilities.

  4. Fewer (more) inefficiencies occur if competent office seekers put a higher (lower) probability on selecting I upon observing H.

  5. We stress that the result is obtained under the assumption that incompetent and competent office seekers choose I with the same probability.

  6. In principle, the public might also try to not reelect the agent at all, in order to limit distortions. This could be achieved e.g. by term limits. However, if the evaluation of competence in activities other than current office (e.g. in ensuing careers) is of an arbitrarily small value for office seekers, office seekers would choose I with probability one, thus inducing more distortions than in the optimal case.

  7. The purification approach was developed by Harsanyi (1973).

  8. Details are available upon request.

  9. To which extent the government can assess the contribution of the policy itself is unclear.

  10. Of course, there is no complete ignorance. Yet, there is a great heterogeneity of scientific explanations how a set of banking regulations may impact the likelihood of a crisis, most notably whether and which capital requirements are efficient (see Gersbach et al. 2015 for a discussion).

  11. In Stage 4, \(\theta \) does not become publicly known and utility changes cannot be traced back to the policy choices.

  12. Similar cases may also be observed in firms. Sometimes, it remains unclear for a long time—or forever—whether a particular project was valuable, in particular if only a combination of several projects together determines success. If it is uncertain whether employees are intrinsically motivated or motivated by the assessment of competence, the curse of competence may impact promotion decisions.

References

  • Beniers, K. J., & Dur, R. (2007). Politicians’ motivation, political culture, and electoral competition. International Tax and Public Finance, 14(1), 29–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernholz, P. (2013). The slow and hidden road to serfdom. Procesos de Mercado. Revista Europea de Economia Politica, X(2), 201–237.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bischoff, I., & Siemers, L. (2013). Biased beliefs and retrospective voting: Why democracies choose mediocre policies. Public Choice, 156(1–2), 163–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coate, S., & Morris, S. (1995). On the form of transfers to special interests. Journal of Political Economy, 103, 1210–1235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Congleton, R. (2007). Informational limits to democratic public policy: The jury theorem, yardstick competition, and ignorance. Public Choice, 132, 333–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Congleton, R., & Zhang, Y. (2013). Is it all about competence? The human capital of U.S. presidents and economic performance. Constitutional Political Economy, 24, 108–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dalton, R. J. (2017). Political trust in North America. In S. Zmerli & T. W. G. van der Meer (Eds.), Handbook on political trust. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dixit, A. (1992). Investment and hysteresis. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 6(1), 107–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dover, E. (1998). The presidential election of 1996, Clinton’s incumbency and television. Westport, CT: Greenwood.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gersbach, H. (2009). Democratic mechanisms. Journal of the European Economic Association, 7(6), 1436–1469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gersbach, H., Haller, H., & Muller, J. (2015). The macroeconomics of Modigliani–Miller. Journal of Economic Theory, 157, 1081–1113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glazer, A. (1985). The advantages of being first. American Economic Review, 75(3), 473–480.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodhart, C. A., & Lastra, R. (2017) Populism and central bank independence, CEPR Discussion Paper DP12122.

  • Harsanyi, J. C. (1973). Games with randomly disturbed payoffs: A new rationale for mixed-strategy equilibrium points. International Journal of Game Theory, 2(1), 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hess, G. D., & Orphanides, A. (1995). War politics—An economic, rational-voter framework. American Economic Review, 85(4), 828–846.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, M. J. (2005). Why trust matters: Declining political trust and the demise of American liberalism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, M. J., & Rudolph, T. J. (2015). Why Washington won’t work: Polarization, political trust, and the governing crisis. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Holmström, B. (1999). Managerial incentive problems: A dynamic perspective. Review of Economic Studies, 66(1), 169–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lupia, A., & McCubbins, M. D. (1998). The democratic dilemma: Can citizens learn what they need to know?. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, S. (2001). Political correctness. Journal of Political Economy, 109(2), 231–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nye, J. S, Jr., Zelikow, P. D., & King, D. C. (1997). Why people don’t trust government. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pindyck, R. S. (1991). Irreversibility, uncertainty, and investment. Journal of Economic Literature, 29, 1110–1148.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rodrik, D. (2017) Populism and the economics of globalization, CEPR Discussion Paper DP12119.

  • Rogoff, K. (1990). Equilibrium political budget cycles. American Economic Review, 80(1), 12–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rogoff, K., & Sibert, A. (1988). Elections and macroeconomic policy cycles. Review of Economic Studies, 55, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scharfstein, D. S., & Stein, J. C. (1990). Herd behavior and investment. American Economic Review, 80(3), 465–479.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stevenson, B., & Wolfers, J. (2011). Trust in public institutions over the business cycle. American Economic Review, 101(3), 281–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warren, M. E. (Ed.). (1999). Democracy and trust. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

A first version entitled “Statesmen, Populists and the Curse of Competence” appeared in 1999 as University of Heidelberg Discussion Paper No. 301. I am grateful to three referees, Toke Aidt, Peter Bernholz, Roger Congleton, Gregory Egorov, Ulrich Erlenmaier, Thomas Gehrig, Ami Glazer, Hans Haller, Evgenij Komarov, Heinrich Ursprung and seminar participants at the 28th Silvaplana Workshop on Political Economy 2019 for valuable suggestions and comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hans Gersbach.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix

Appendix

Proof of Proposition 1

There are three possibilities. An office seeker can prefer I over NI, prefer NI over I, or can be indifferent between I and NI. We begin with the last case. An office seeker is indifferent if and only if

$$\begin{aligned} \alpha g_{1} (I,p^{0}) + (1-\alpha )h_{1}(I,p^{0}) = \alpha g_{1} (NI,p^{0}) + (1-\alpha )h_{1}(NI,p^{0}). \end{aligned}$$
(15)

Inserting the expressions from Eqs. (5)–(8), and using the simplification

$$\begin{aligned} i:&= h_{0}g_{0}\pi _{H} + (1-h_{0})p^0,\\ 1-i&= h_{0}(1-g_{0}\pi _{H}) + (1-h_{0}) (1-p^0) \end{aligned} $$

yields

$$\begin{aligned} g_0h_0\pi _{\mathrm{H}}-ih_0=\alpha \left( i\left( g_0-h_0\right) -p^0g_0\left( 1-h_0\right) \right) . \end{aligned}$$
(16)

Rearranging terms and simplifying yields, for \(\alpha <1\),

$$\begin{aligned} p^{0} = \frac{g_{0}\pi _{H}\left[ \alpha (h_{0}-g_{0}) + (1-h_{0}) \right] }{(1-\alpha )(1-h_{0}) }=g_{0}\pi _{H}\frac{ \alpha (1-g_{0}) + (1-\alpha )(1-h_{0})}{ (1-\alpha )(1-h_{0}) }=:p^*. \end{aligned}$$
(17)

In equilibrium, we must have \(p^* = p^0\), where \(p^*\) is the probability that the office seeker will choose I. Let us consider the boundary conditions for \(p^*\).

From Eq. (17), we conclude that \(p^*\ge g_0\pi _{\mathrm{H}}\) and thus \(p^*\) is positive. The other boundary condition \(p^*\le 1\) requires

$$\begin{aligned} \alpha \bigr [ g_{0}\pi _{H}(h_{0}-g_{0}) + (1-h_{0}) \bigl ] \le g_{0}\pi _{H}(h_{0}-1)+1-h_0, \end{aligned}$$

which implies

$$\begin{aligned} \alpha \le \frac{(1-h_0)(1-g_0\, \pi _{\mathrm{H}})}{(1-h_{0})+g_{0}\pi _{H}(h_{0}-g_{0})} =: \alpha ^{*}. \end{aligned}$$

Hence, for \(\alpha \le \alpha ^{*}\) and \(p^0 = p^*\) as derived in Eq. (17), an office seeker is indifferent between I and NI. Therefore, given \(p^{*}\) and associated a posteriori beliefs of the public for \( \alpha \le \alpha ^{*}\), a mixed strategy is optimal for an office seeker. This follows from the construction above. Moreover, one can easily verify that choosing the mixed strategy associated with \(p^*\) is preferred over choosing \(p^0=1\) or \(p^0=0\). The case \(p^0=0\) is studied below. The case \(p^0=1\) is analogous. The rationality of the public’s beliefs requires that the office seeker plays I with probability \(p^{*}\).

In the next step, we consider the case \(\alpha >\alpha ^{*}\). According to Eq. (17), \(p^{*}\) would become larger than 1. Straightforward calculations show that the office seekers are better off by selecting I over NI. Therefore, an office seeker will choose I for \(\alpha > \alpha ^{*}\) with certainty.

In the last step, we observe that a pure strategy equilibrium does not exist when the office seeker selects NI. For the case of \( \alpha > \alpha ^{*}\), this follows from the considerations in the last paragraph. When \(\alpha \le \alpha ^{*}\), choosing NI with probability 1 would imply the following beliefs:

$$\begin{aligned} g_{1}(I,0)&= 1,\\ g_{1}(NI,0)&= \frac{h_{0}g_{0}(1-\pi _{H}) + (1-h_{0}) g_{0}}{h_{0}(1-\pi _{H}g_{0}) + (1-h_{0})},\\ h_{1}(I,0)&= 1,\\ h_{1}(NI,0)&= \frac{h_{0}(1-g_{0}\pi _{H})}{h_{0}(1-\pi _{H}g_{0}) + (1-h_{0})}. \end{aligned}$$

Hence,

$$\begin{aligned} \alpha g_{1}(I,0) + (1-\alpha ) h_{1} (I,0) = 1> \alpha g_{1} (NI,0) + (1-\alpha ) h_{1} (NI,0), \end{aligned}$$

which implies that NI is not the office seeker’s optimal choice. Given the beliefs associated with \( p^{0} = 0\), it is in fact the worst choice. \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 2

Suppose there is an equilibrium in which PG chooses I with probability \(p_1 (0<p_1<1)\) and PB chooses I with probability \(p_2 \ne p_1 (0<p_2<1)\).

Then, the posterior beliefs that a politician is competent upon choosing I and NI, respectively, are

$$\begin{aligned} g_1(I, p_1, p_2)&= \frac{h_0g_0\pi _{\mathrm{H}} + (1-h_0)g_0p_1}{h_0g_0\pi _{\mathrm{H}} + (1-h_0)(g_0p_1 + (1-g_0)p_2)},\\ g_1(NI, p_1, p_2)&= \frac{h_0g_0(1-\pi _{\mathrm{H}}) + (1-h_0)g_0(1-p_1)}{h_0(1-g_0\pi _{\mathrm{H}}) + (1-h_0)(g_0(1-p_1) + (1-g_0)(1-p_2))}. \end{aligned}$$

For \(h_1(I, p_1, p_2)\) and \(h_1(NI, p_1, p_2)\), only the joint probabilities \(g_0p_1 + (1-g_0)p_2\) and \(g_0(1-p_1) + (1-g_0)(1-p_2)\) matter, and the formulas (7) and (8) can be applied with \(p^0\) and \(1-p^0\) respectively, replaced by these joint probabilities.

Hence, for \(\alpha >0\)—and thus in the case when competence matters for voters—this can only be an equilibrium if

$$\begin{aligned}&\alpha p_1 g_1(I, p_1, p_2) + \alpha (1-p_1) g_1(NI, p_1, p_2)\\&\quad +(1-\alpha )p_1h_1(I, p_1, p_2) + (1-\alpha )(1-p_1)h_1(NI, p_1, p_2)\\&\quad = \alpha p_2 g_1(I, p_1, p_2) + \alpha (1-p_2) g_1(NI, p_1, p_2) \\&\quad +\,(1-\alpha )p_2h_1(I, p_1, p_2) + (1-\alpha )(1-p_2)h_1(NI, p_1, p_2). \end{aligned}$$

Otherwise, the competent (incompetent) office seeker could improve his reelection chances by choosing \(p_2\) (\(p_1)\). We write \(A=h_0g_0\pi _{\mathrm{H}}+(1-h_0)(g_0p_1+(1-g_0)p_2)\) and \(1-A=h_0(1-g_0\pi _{\mathrm{H}})+(1-h_0)(g_0(1-p_1)+(1-g_0)(1-p_2))\).

This yields

$$\begin{aligned}&(p_1-p_2)\Bigg (\frac{h_0g_0\pi _{H}+\alpha (1-h_0)g_0 p_1}{A}\\&\qquad -\frac{\alpha \left( h_0g_0(1-\pi _{\mathrm{H}})+(1-h_0)g_0(1-p_1)\right) +(1-\alpha )h_0(1-g_0\pi _{\mathrm{H}})}{1-A}\Bigg )=0. \end{aligned}$$

Assuming \(\alpha >0\), this condition is satisfied if \(p_1 = p_2\), i.e. both PG and PB choose I with the same probability. However, other equilibria are also possible. An example is the parameter constellation \(h_0=g_0=\pi _{H}=\alpha =0.5\), which yields \(p_2=0.5\) as a second solution. Note that it is independent of \(p_1\).

For the case \(\alpha =0\) the original condition can be reduced to

$$\begin{aligned} h_1(I, p_1, p_2) = h_1(NI, p_1, p_2). \end{aligned}$$

This implies

$$(p_1-p_2)\left[\frac{h_0g_0\pi_H}{A}-\frac{h_0(1-g_0\pi_H)}{1-A}\right]=0.$$

Solving for \(p_2\) yields two possible solutions:

$$\begin{aligned} p_2&= p_1 \quad \text {and} \\ p_2&= \frac{g_0(\pi_H-p_1)}{1-g_0}.\end{aligned}$$

Now, we see that besides the obvious solution of \(p_1=p_2\), we can express \(p_2\) in terms of the parameters and \(p_1\). This equation can be solved for \(p_1\), \(p_2 \in (0,1)\) for suitable parameter values, which means that there are other possible equilibria if \(\alpha =0\). \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 3

We first derive the expected welfare of the public for different choices of \(\alpha \). We denote expected welfare as a function of the choice \(p^*\) of office seekers by \(W(p^*)\). \(W(p^*)\) is the expected value of the project, given the choices of statesmen and office seekers.

If \(\alpha \ge \alpha ^ *\), office seekers will play I with probability \(p^*=1\) according to Proposition 1, and social welfare is given by

$$\begin{aligned} W(p^*=1) = h_0 \Bigl (\pi _{\mathrm{H}} \, V_{\mathrm{H}} \bigl (g_0 + \delta \, (1-g_0)\bigr )\Bigr ) + (1-h_0) \, \bigl (\pi _{\mathrm{H}}\,V_{\mathrm{H}} + (1-\pi _{\mathrm{H}}) \, V_{\mathrm{L}}\bigr ). \end{aligned}$$

Next, suppose office seekers play I with probability \(p^*\), and \(p^*\ge \pi _{\mathrm{H}}\). In this case, welfare is given by

$$\begin{aligned} W(p^*\mid p^*\ge \pi _{H})&= \Bigl (\pi _{\mathrm{H}} \, V_{\mathrm{H}} \bigl (g_0 + \delta \, (1-g_0)\bigr )\Bigr )h_0 + \Bigl [g_0 \bigl (\pi _{\mathrm{H}} \, V_{\mathrm{H}} + (1-\pi _{\mathrm{H}}) \frac{p^*- \pi _{\mathrm{H}}}{1-\pi _{\mathrm{H}}} \, V_{\mathrm{L}} \bigr )\\&\quad +\,(1-g_0) \bigl (p^*(\pi _{\mathrm{H}}\, V_{\mathrm{H}} + (1-\pi _{\mathrm{H}}) \, V_{\mathrm{L}}\bigl ) + (1-p^*)\, \delta \, \pi _{\mathrm{H}} \, V_{\mathrm{H}} \bigr )\Bigr ](1-h_0). \end{aligned} $$

For \(p^*< \pi _{\mathrm{H}}\), we obtain

$$\begin{aligned} W(p^*\mid p^*< \pi _{H})&= \Bigl (\pi _{\mathrm{H}} \, V_{\mathrm{H}} \bigl (g_0 + \delta \, (1-g_0)\bigr )\Bigr )h_0+ \Bigl [g_0 \, \pi _{\mathrm{H}} \, V_{\mathrm{H}} \, \Bigl (\frac{p^*}{\pi _{\mathrm{H}}} + \frac{\pi _{\mathrm{H}} - p^*}{\pi _{\mathrm{H}}}\, \delta \Bigr )\\&\quad +\,(1-g_0)\Bigl (p^*\bigl (\pi _{\mathrm{H}} \, V_{\mathrm{H}} + (1-\pi _{\mathrm{H}}) \, V_{\mathrm{L}}\bigr ) + (1-p^*) \, \delta \, \pi _{\mathrm{H}} \, V_{\mathrm{H}} \Bigr )\Bigr ](1-h_0). \end{aligned}$$

We observe that

$$\begin{aligned} W(p^*\mid p^*\ge \pi _{H}) |_{p^{*} = \pi _{\mathrm{H}}}=\mathop{lim}_{p\!*\rightarrow\pi_H}\,W(p^*\mid p^*<\pi_H) =:W(p^*=\pi _{\mathrm{H}}). \end{aligned}$$

Note that \(W(p^*\mid p^*\ge \pi _{H})\) is monotonically decreasing in \(p^*\) as we assumed that \(V_{\mathrm{H}}>0>V_{\mathrm{L}}\) and that (3) holds. Hence, we have

$$\begin{aligned} W(p^*\mid p^*> \pi _{H}) < W(p^*= \pi _{H}). \end{aligned}$$

Since \(W(p^*\mid p^*< \pi _{H})\) is linear in \(p^*\), the welfare-optimal mixing probabilities are either \(p^*= \pi _{\mathrm{H}}\) or \(p^*= g_0\, \pi _{\mathrm{H}}\). The probability \(p^*= g_0 \pi _{\mathrm{H}}\) is the smallest possible value for \(p^*\) occurring for \(\alpha = 0\).

\(W( p^*= \pi _{H}) < W(p^*= g_0 \pi _{\mathrm{H}})\) if and only if

$$\begin{aligned} g_0 \,\pi _{\mathrm{H}}\, V_{\mathrm{H}} \bigl [1-g_0 - (1-g_0) \, \delta \bigl ] + (1-g_0)^{2} \,\pi _{\mathrm{H}}\, \Bigl (\pi _{\mathrm{H}}\, V_{\mathrm{H}}\, (1-\delta ) + (1-\pi _{\mathrm{H}})\, V_{\mathrm{L}} \Bigr ) < 0 \end{aligned}$$

or equivalently, \(K{:=}\, V_{\mathrm{H}} \, \bigl [g_0\, (1-\delta )+(1-g_0) \, \pi _{\mathrm{H}} (1-\delta )\bigr ] +(1-\pi _{\mathrm{H}})\, V_{\mathrm{L}}\, (1-g_0) <0 \).

Hence, for \(K \le 0\), the optimal choice of the public is \(\alpha ^0 = 0\), inducing \(p^*=g_0\pi _{\mathrm{H}}\). For \(K >0\), the optimal choice of the public is

$$\begin{aligned} \alpha ^0 = \frac{(1-h_0)(1-g_0)}{(1-h_0)+g_0(h_0-g_0)}, \end{aligned}$$

which, using Equation (10), implies that \(p^*= \pi _{\mathrm{H}}\). This completes the proof. \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 4

Any equilibrium with a reelection scheme \(q(g_1, h_1)\) produces a probability—or several probabilities—that an office seeker will play I. The equilibrium probabilities are denoted by \({\hat{p}}\) and are determined by

$$\begin{aligned} \mathop {\mathrm{argmax}}\limits _{p} \Bigl \{ p \Bigl ( q \bigl (g_1 (I, {\hat{p}}), h_1 (I,{\hat{p}}) \bigr )\Bigr ) + (1-p) \Bigl ( q \bigl (g_1 (NI, {\hat{p}}), h_1 (NI, {\hat{p}}) \bigr )\Bigr ) \Bigr \} = {\hat{p}}. \end{aligned}$$

We next observe from the proof of Proposition 3 that welfare is a linear function of \({\hat{p}}\) and any reelection scheme affects welfare solely through its impact on \({\hat{p}}\). Since welfare is a first-order polynomial in \(p^*\), this implies that its extreme values are achieved at boundary points of the domain. Hence, the welfare-optimal mixing probabilities are either \(p^* = \pi _{\mathrm{H}}\) or \(p^* = \pi _{\mathrm{H}} g_0\). As the linear scheme can implement the welfare-optimal \(p^*\) in both possible cases, no other scheme can perform better. \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gersbach, H. Elections, the curse of competence and credence policies. Public Choice 186, 491–511 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-019-00753-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-019-00753-w

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation