Skip to main content
Log in

Causes Versus Background Conditions: A Double Negation Account

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Global Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I shall present in this article a double negation account of the distinction between causes and background conditions. Such an account will be based on the idea that, unlike causes, background conditions allow for certain effects by way of double prevention. In Sect. 1 I shall introduce objective and non-objective theories of the causes-background conditions distinction and I shall discuss and reject some non-objective theories. In Sect. 2 I shall examine some existing objective theories and argue that they need to be supplemented in two relevant respects. In Sect. 3 I shall present my double negation account. Background conditions will be taken to allow for their effects by acting as early double preventers, late double preventers or effect double preventers. In Sect. 4 I shall deal with two main problems, i.e., the possibility of interpreting background conditions as purely indirect causes and the introduction of negative entities in my account, and with further issues.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. My use of the “grounding” terminology here and elsewhere is non-committal. Namely, I am not committed to the truth of theories of metaphysical grounding (see Bliss and Trogdon 2021).

  2. See for example Psillos (2002), Beebee et al. (2009), Paul and Hall (2013) and Kutach (2014).

  3. Is it also exhaustive? This depends on the category to which both causes and background conditions are taken to belong. For example, if both causes and background conditions belonged to the category of entities responsible for the occurrence of an effect, then the distinction could be exhaustive, since everything that is responsible for the occurrence of an effect either is a cause or a background condition.

  4. I concede that, when one talks of in principle interventions—without restricting them to the physical capacities of human beings—the theory may turn out to be objective. However, this does not imply that the resulting distinction between causes and background conditions turns out to be adequate. For in principle interventions are possible both with respect to causes and with respect to background conditions. On interventionist theories of causation, see for example Woodward (2016).

  5. One may object that, if the epistemic interest of a knowing subject only consisted in knowing the truth about the external world, a real and objective way of distinguishing between causes and BG-conditions could turn out to be grounded on such an interest. Therefore, the resulting theory would turn out to be non-objective. I reply that this scenario is incoherent. If a knowing subject is only interested in knowing the truth about the external world, it is a real and objective way of distinguishing between causes and BG-conditions that grounds the fulfilment of that interest, not the other way round.

  6. Strevens (2008) treats BG-conditions as presuppositions behind explanatory frameworks. Unlike causes, BG-conditions do not act as difference-makers within those frameworks. Strevens’ theory may be interpreted either in the first way, or in the second way.

  7. This second interpretation is more in line with Dretske (2010).

  8. Skow fully endorses this claim in Skow (2018).

  9. In the neighbourhood of this theory and with respect to actions, Dancy (2006) distinguishes between favouring/disfavouring conditions, enabling/disabling conditions and intensifiers/attenuators. The former favour/disfavour actions. Enabling/disabling conditions enable/disable something else to/from be(ing) a favouring/disfavouring condition. Intensifiers/attenuators intensify/attenuate something else’s being a favouring/disfavouring condition. Austin (2019: 79–84) distinguishes between causal responsibility and causal relevance. Causally responsible items make it the case that the causally relevant factors are causally relevant and that they are causally relevant in specific ways.

  10. Of course, if by “preventer” we point to the actual occurring of the preventive action (e.g., that someone destroys the matches), then it turns out to be legitimate to talk of the absence of preventers. However, first, this does not grasp the intuitive idea behind preventers and double preventers. In order for double preventers to be in place, not only must their corresponding preventers be absent (i.e., non-occurring), but the latter must also be possibly occurring—were it not for double preventers. Secondly, talking of the absence of preventers restricts our field of investigation. On the contrary, it is also possible to single out positive BG-conditions—and positive (early) double preventers.

  11. Of course, the relevant “something else” which is prevented should be at least nomologically incompatible with the presence of the resources at stake. It may be objected that resources behave like causes. Indeed, even causes—like resources—should just be present in order for the effect to take place. But resources—unlike causes—need not ‘just be present’ in order for the effect to take place. Resources must be present beyond a certain threshold, i.e., they must be ‘no less than enough’ in order for the effect to take place—or, better, in order to prevent something else that could prevent the causal process/the cause/the effect.

  12. But see Paolini Paoletti (2021).

  13. A necessary condition for indirect causes to qualify as bona fide causes of their effect is the transitivity of causation, i.e., that if c causes d and d causes e, then c causes e. However, the transitivity of causation is not sufficient for having indirect causes. A certain cause by transitivity c may just qualify as a cause simpliciter of e, without the need to introduce any further distinction between direct and indirect causes. On the transitivity of causation, see for example Paul and Hall (2013) and Gallow (2022).

  14. Indeed, double preventers are mostly treated as bona fide causes of their effects (at least in some sense). For a discussion, see for example Hall (2004) and Paul and Hall (2013).

  15. For a discussion of negative entities (and more specifically of negative properties and facts) see Paolini Paoletti (2017).

  16. Negative effects may be made absent by the introduction of negative double causation. From my side, I am eager to accept negative entities and to attribute to them causal and determinative roles (see Paolini Paoletti 2014 and 2017).

  17. It may be argued that, in this scenario, the preventer (i.e., the sear’s being up) may also count as a cause of the spring’s being cocked. Therefore, it also counts as an indirect cause of the cocked spring’s getting uncoiled and of the bullet’s leaving the gun. However, this does not endanger our theory. For the double preventer (i.e., pulling the trigger) does not cause the sear’s being up, so that it cannot count as an indirect cause of the relevant effects.

  18. See for example McGrath (2005).

  19. I assume here, as I have done above, that the causal processes going from the direct causes to the effects do not contain further causes. Otherwise, the direct causes at stake would turn out to be indirect.

  20. On double prevention and its role in causation, see also Mumford and Anjum (2009) and Gibb (2013).

References

  • Austin CJ (2019) Essence in the age of evolution. A new theory of natural kinds. Routledge, London

  • Beebee H, Hitchcok C, Menzies P (eds) (2009) The Oxford handbook of causation. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Bigaj T (2005) Causes, conditions and counterfactuals. Axiomathes 15:599–619

  • Bliss R., Trogdon K. (2021) Metaphysical grounding. In: Zalta E. N. (ed), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/grounding/. Last visited on 2 Nov 2022

  • Dancy J (2006) Ethics without principles. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Dretske F (1988) Explaining behavior. Reasons in a world of causes. MIT Press, Cambridge

  • Dretske F (2010) Triggering and structuring causes. In: O’Connor T, Sandis C (eds) A companion to the philosophy of action. Wiley-Blackwell, London, pp 139–144

  • Gallow J. D. (2022) The metaphysics of causation. In: Zalta E. N. (ed), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/causation-metaphysics/. Last visited on 2 Nov 2022

  • Gibb SC (2013) Mental causation and double prevention. In: Gibb SC, Lowe EJ, Ingthorsson RD (eds) Mental causation and ontology. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 193–214

  • Hall N (2004) Two concepts of causation. In: Hall N, Paul LA, Collins J (eds) Causation and counterfactuals. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 181–204

  • Hart HLA, Honoré AM (1959) Causation in the Law. Clarendon, Oxford

  • Hauska J (2008) Dispositions and normal conditions. Philos Stud 139:219–232

  • Hitchcock C, Knobe J (2009) Cause and norm. J Philos 106:587–612

  • Klein C (2018) Mechanisms, resources, and background conditions. Biol Philos 33:36

  • Kutach D (2014) Causation. Polity, Cambridge

  • Mackie JL (1974) The cement of the universe. A study of causation. Clarendon, Oxford

  • McGrath S (2005) Causation by omission: a dilemma. Philos Stud 123:125–148

  • Mumford S, Anjum RL (2009) Double prevention and powers. J Crit Realism 8:277–293

  • Paolini Paoletti M (2014) Falsemakers: Something Negative about Facts. Grazer Philosophische Studien 90:169-182

  • Paolini Paoletti M (2017) From Falsemakers to Negative Properties. Theoria 83:53-77

  • Paolini Paoletti M (2021) Masks, Interferers, Finks, and Mimickers: A Novel Approach. Theoria 87:813-836

  • Paul LA, Hall N (2013) Causation. A user’s guide. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Psillos S (2002) Causation and explanation. Acumen, Stocksfield

  • Schaffer J (2000) Causation by disconnection. Philosophy of Science 67:285–300

  • Skow B (2016) Reasons why. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Skow B (2018) Causation, explanation and the metaphysics of aspect. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Strevens M (2008) Depth. An account of scientific explanation. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

  • Yablo S (2004) Advertisement for a sketch of an outline of a proto-theory of causation. In: Hall N, Paul LA, Collins J (eds) Causation and counterfactuals. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 119–137

  • Woodward J. (2016) Causation and Manipulability. In: Zalta E. N. (ed), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/causation-mani/. Last visited on 2 Nov 2022

Download references

Funding

Funding was provided by Ministero dell’Istruzione, dell’Università e della Ricerca (Grant No. PRIN 2017 "The Manifest Image and the Scientific Image").

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michele Paolini Paoletti.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Paolini Paoletti, M. Causes Versus Background Conditions: A Double Negation Account. glob. Philosophy 33, 1 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-023-09664-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-023-09664-4

Keywords

Navigation