Skip to main content
Log in

Descriptions and Tests for Polysemy

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Axiomathes Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Viebahn (Pac Philos Q 99:749–762, 2018. https://doi.org/10.1111/papq.1222) has recently argued that several tests for ambiguity, such as the conjunction-reduction test, are not reliable as tests for polysemy, but only as tests for homonymy. I look at the more fine-grained distinction between regular and irregular polysemy and I argue for a more nuanced conclusion: the tests under discussion provide systematic evidence for homonymy and irregular polysemy but need to be used with more care to test for regular polysemy. I put this conclusion at work in the context of the debate over the alleged referential-attributive ambiguity of the definite article. In reply to various criticisms, defenders of the ambiguity view argue that this is a case of polysemy. But opponents object that the dual use of the definite article fails tests for ambiguity. The debate seems to have come to stalemate, unless the relevance of the tests is determined for cases of alleged polysemy. I conclude that the balance of considerations incline towards rejecting the ambiguity thesis.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Donnellan (1966) includes in his discussion cases of misdescription, in which the speaker has in mind and intends to talk about an object that does not satisfy the DD she uses. The use is still referential, but on Reimer’s (1998) and Devitt’s (2004, 2007) version of Referentialism the object is not the semantic referent of the DD. There are other versions of Referentialism, such as Marti’s (2008), which takes the intended object to be the semantic referent even if it does not satisfy the descriptive content uniquely.

  2. Bach’s and Kripke’s arguments make use of empirical claims, which, although plausible, are not supported by empirical investigation. Thus, Elbourne’s (2013: 109) question is to the point: “And just how many languages has Bach surveyed in establishing his generalization? We are not told.”. In fact, Amaral (2008: 294–295) writes, it is not true that there are no languages that remove the ambiguity of the definite article: Amaral cites evidence concerning Malagasy, an Austronesian language, and Mönchengladbach, a Low Franconian dialect spoken in the northwest of Germany, where there are two definite articles, corresponding to the two uses.

  3. Actually, Kripke (1977) goes a long a way towards acknowledging this point (although he does not explicitly mention the distinction between homonymy and polysemy): “The more we can explain relations among senses, and the more “natural” and “inevitable” the relationship, the more we will expect the different senses to be preserved in a wide variety of other languages” (1977: 275). However, Kripke does not formulate the polysemy hypothesis.

  4. When applied to predicates, the test is sometimes discussed in the literature under the names “the antagonism test” (Cruse 1986: 61–62), “the copredication test” (Asher 2011: 65), or as “the predicate coordination test” (Gillon 2004: 176).

  5. See the discussion in Sennet (2015: §4) concerning this point.

  6. Sennet also notes that “the conjunction reduction test assumes that the following cannot serve as legitimate implicature cancellation: “Jim and Steve own bats, but Jim’s has wings and Steve’s is made of wood”” (Sennet 2002: 93).

  7. One famous example of zeugma is Chomsky’s (1957) ‘Colorless green ideas sleep furiously’. The sentence is grammatically correct but nonsensical.

  8. Although Sennet (2002) invokes the “conjunction and reduction test”, he in fact uses the version of the test designed for argument-taking expressions, i.e. “the argument coordination test”.

  9. Sennet (2002: 87) and Koralus (2013: 283) both argue that the DD ‘the prince and queen’ could not be used attributively with respect to the prince. However, I do not find their arguments compelling. According to Sennet (2002: 87), an attributive use of ‘the prince’ “requires that there is a change of meaning” as between the first use of ‘the prince’ in (11), where it is used referentially, and the second use in (13). Sennet comments: “To posit any such inscrutable change of meaning is at best a desperate move. Desperate moves are a sign of a bad view” (2002: 87). But this argument is problematic: even if the use in (11) is referential and in (13) is attributive this does not mean there is a change in the meaning of the DD between the two sentences, given that at this point of the argument it cannot be assumed that DDs have two meanings. At this point we are only checking whether the cross interpretation is available. If it is, this is a reason to think it does not have two meanings. In turn, Koralus (2013: 283), who also discusses the example, takes ‘the prince’, when used referentially in (11), to be a misdescription of some individual in the palace that looked like a prince without being one, while there is no actual price. Consequently, he argues that if we were to interpret both ‘the prince’ and ‘<the> queen’ attributively, then (13) would turn out false, contrary to intuition. But if ‘the prince’ is a misdescription and there is no unique prince, then (13) is semantically false, according to both Russellians and most Referentialists (see also footnote 1). Cases of misdescriptions introduce further unnecessary complications, so it is better to leave them out of the discussion.

  10. See the discusses in Gillon (2004) for the technical details.

  11. Koralus (2013: 283) applies this test to DDs, but his example is rather cumbersome and involves intensional contexts, which introduce further complications (such as scope ambiguities) that I wish to avoid here.

  12. Viebahn comment that the lack of zeugmaticity in (23) to (25) “presumably has to do with the fact that these cases involve polysemous target expressions and only subtle differences in meaning—differences that are hard to detect without careful reflection” (2018: 6). But, this cannot be the whole explanation, given the presence of zeugma in sentences (26) and (28). I come back to this point in Sect. 4.

  13. These examples are from Ruhl (1989: 84, 99). See Ruhl (1989: 286) for a list of types of metonymic relations.

  14. See Pethö (2007: 3). Ravin and Leacock (2000: 10) also write that “Regular polysemy is governed by processes which are productive, rule-governed and predictable, very much like processes of word formation”. See also Brocher et al. (2016: 4).

  15. As Vicente (2015: 58) writes, “In these cases (i.e. regular polysemy), non-zeugmatic co-predication is typically possible, as in ‘the book is heavy but very entertaining’”.

  16. This is not a surprising result, given that irregular polysemic words lead to similar experimental results to those obtained for homonymic words for various psycholinguistic phenomena, as Rabagliati and Snedeker (2013: 1355) and Eddington and Tokowicz (2015: 23) show.

  17. Asher (2011: 102) writes: “accidental and logical polysemy differ in several linguistically discernible ways—for instance, the copredication and anaphora tests”. See also Vicente and Falkum (2017: 8).

  18. I leave out a discussion of the referential-attributive uses of pronouns and proper names for the reason that they are not determiner phrases.

  19. See also the discussion of this proposal in Elbourne (2013: 110–112).

  20. The truth-conditions resulting from the Gödelian completion are slightly different from those the Referentialist postulates in that the latter takes the semantic content to be Ga, and the presupposition to be that there is a unique x such that Fx and x = a. See Reimer (1998: 93) and Devitt (2004: 282).

  21. See also Ruhl (1989: 97) for a discussion of the related distinction between semantics and pragmatic metonymy.

References

  • Amaral FS (2008) Definite descriptions are ambiguous. Analysis 68(300):288–297

    Google Scholar 

  • Apresjan JUD (1974) Regular polysemy. Linguistics Interdiscip J Lang Sci 12(142):5–32

    Google Scholar 

  • Asher N (2011) Lexical meaning in context: a web of words. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach K (1998) Ambiguity. In: Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy. http://online.sfsu.edu/~kbach/ambguity.html. Cited 1 Nov 2018

  • Bach K (2004a) Descriptions: points of reference. In: Reimer M, Bezuidenhout A (eds) Descriptions and beyond. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 189–229

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach K (2004b) On referring and not referring. In: Gundel Jeanette K, Hedberg Nancy (eds) Reference: interdisciplinary perspectives. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 13–58

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach K (2007) Referentially used descriptions: a reply to Devitt. Eur J Anal Philos 3(2):33–48

    Google Scholar 

  • Bezuidenhout A (1997) Pragmatics, semantic undetermination and the referential/attributive distinction. Mind 106(423):375–409

    Google Scholar 

  • Bontly TD (2005) Modified occam’s razor: parsimony, pragmatics, and the acquisition of word meaning. Mind Lang 20(3):288–312

    Google Scholar 

  • Brocher A, Foraker S, Koenig J-P (2016) Processing of irregular polysemes in sentence reading. J Exp Psychol Learn Mem Cogn 42(11):1798–1813

    Google Scholar 

  • Chastain C (1975) Reference and context. In: Gunderson Keith (ed) Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science: language mind and knowledge, vol 7. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp 194–269

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky N (1957) Syntactic structures. Mouton, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Cruse DA (1986) Lexical semantics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dever J (2001) Complex demonstratives. Linguist Philos 24(3):271–330

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt M (1981) Donnellan’s distinction. Midwest Stud Philos 6(1):511–526

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt M (2004) The case for referential descriptions. In: Reimer M, Bezuidenhout A (eds) Descriptions and beyond. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt M (2007) Referential descriptions and conversational implicatures. Eur J Anal Philos 3(2):7–32

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt M (2013) What makes a property “semantic”? In: Capone A, Franco LP, Carapezza M (eds) Perspectives on pragmatics and philosophy. Springer, New York, pp 87–112

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan KS (1966) Reference and definite descriptions. Philos Rev 75(3):281–304

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan KS (1978) Speaker reference, descriptions, and anaphora. In: Cole P (ed) Syntax and semantics 9: pragmatics. Academic Press, New York, pp 47–68

    Google Scholar 

  • Eddington CM, Tokowicz M (2015) How meaning similarity influences ambiguous word processing. Psychon Bull Rev 22:13–37

    Google Scholar 

  • Elbourne P (2013) Definite descriptions. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor JD, Sag IA (1982) Referential and quantificational indefinites. Linguist Philos 5(3):355–398

    Google Scholar 

  • Geeraerts D (1993) Vagueness’s puzzles, polysemy’s vagaries. Cogn Linguist 4(3):223–272

    Google Scholar 

  • Georgi G (2012) Reference and ambiguity in complex demonstratives. In: Kabasenche WP, O’Rourke M, Slater MH (eds) Reference and referring. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 357–384

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillon BS (2004) Ambiguity, indeterminacy, deixis, and vagueness: evidence and theory. In: Davis S, Gillon BS (eds) Semantics: a reader. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 157–190

    Google Scholar 

  • Gomez-Torrente M (2015) Quantifiers and referential use. In: Torza A (ed) Quantifiers, quantifiers, and quantifiers: themes in logic, metaphysics, and language. Springer, New York, pp 97–124

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice PH (1969) Vacuous Names. In: Davidson D, Hintikka J (eds) Words and objections. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 118–145

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff R (2002) Foundations of language: brain, meaning, grammar, evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamp H, Reyle U (1993) From discourse to logic: introduction to model-theoretic semantics of natural language, formal logic and discourse representation theory. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan D (1977) Demonstrative. In: Almog J et al (eds) Themes from Kaplan. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 481–563

    Google Scholar 

  • King JC (1988) Are indefinite descriptions ambiguous? Philos Stud 53:417–440

    Google Scholar 

  • King JC (2001) Complex demonstratives: a quantificational account. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Koralus P (2013) Descriptions, ambiguity, and representationalist theories of interpretation. Philos Stud 162(2):275–290

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke S (1977) Speaker’s reference and semantic reference. Midwest Stud Philos 2:255–276

    Google Scholar 

  • Ludlow P, Neale S (1991) Indefinite descriptions: in defense of Russell. Linguist Philos 14:171–202

    Google Scholar 

  • Marti G (2008) Direct reference and definite descriptions. Dialectica 62(1):43–57

    Google Scholar 

  • Mckinsey M (1979) The ambiguity of definite descriptions. Theoria 45(2):78–89

    Google Scholar 

  • Neale S (1990) Descriptions. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Neale S (2004) This, that, and the other. In: Reimer M, Bezuidenhout A (eds) Descriptions and beyond. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Nowak E (2014) Demonstratives without rigidity or ambiguity. Linguist Philos 37(5):409–436

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke C (1975) Proper names, reference and rigid designation. In: Blackburn S (ed) Meaning, reference and necessity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Pethö G (2007) On irregular polysemy. In: Rakova M, Pethö G, Rákosi C (eds) The cognitive basis of polysemy: new sources of evidence for theories of word meaning. Peter Lang, Bern

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky J (1995) The generative lexicon. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Rabagliati H, Snedeker J (2013) The truth about chickens and bats: ambiguity avoidance distinguishes types of polysemy. Psychol Sci 24(7):1354–1360

    Google Scholar 

  • Ravin Y, Leacock C (2000) Polysemy: theoretical and computational approaches. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Reimer M (1992) Incomplete descriptions. Erkenntnis 37(3):347–363

    Google Scholar 

  • Reimer M (1998) Donnellan’s distinction/Kripke’s test. Analysis 58:89–100

    Google Scholar 

  • Rouchota V (1992) On the referential/attributive distinction. Lingua 87:137–167

    Google Scholar 

  • Rouchota V (1994) On indefinite descriptions. J Linguist 30(2):441–475

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruhl C (1989) On monosemy—a study in linguistic semantics. State University of New York Press, Albany

    Google Scholar 

  • Sainsbury RM (1979) Russell. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Schoubye AJ (2012) Against the argument from convention. Linguist Philos 35(6):515–532

    Google Scholar 

  • Sennet A (2002) An ambiguity test for definite descriptions. Philos Stud 111(1):81–95

    Google Scholar 

  • Sennet A (2015) Ambiguity. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/ambiguity. Cited 1 Nov 2018

  • Sperber D, Wilson D (1995) Relevance. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Vicente A (2015) The green leaves and the expert: polysemy and truth-conditional variability. Lingua 157:54–65

    Google Scholar 

  • Vicente A, Falkum IL (2017) Polysemy. In: Oxford research encyclopedia of linguistics. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acrefore/9780199384655.013.325

  • Viebahn E (2018) Ambiguity and zeugma. Pac Philos Q 99:749–762. https://doi.org/10.1111/papq.12229

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wettstein HK (1981) Demonstrative reference and definite descriptions. Philos Stud 40(2):241–257

    Google Scholar 

  • Zacharska B (2010) Definite descriptions: semantic or pragmatic polysemy? Univ Coll Lond Work Pap Linguist 22:56–63

    Google Scholar 

  • Zwicky AM, Sadock MS (1975) Ambiguity tests and how to fail them. In: Kimball JP (ed) Syntax and semantics, vol 4. Academic Press, New York, pp 1–36

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Funding was provided by Ministerio de Economía, Industria y Competitividad, Gobierno de España (ES) (Grant No. FFI2016-80636-P).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrei Moldovan.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Moldovan, A. Descriptions and Tests for Polysemy. Axiomathes 31, 229–249 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-019-09445-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-019-09445-y

Keywords

Navigation