Skip to main content

Autonomy, Evidence-Responsiveness, and the Ethics of Influence

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Law and Ethics of Freedom of Thought, Volume 1

Part of the book series: Palgrave Studies in Law, Neuroscience, and Human Behavior ((PASTLNHB))

Abstract

How might empirical research enrich our understanding of the nature of autonomy? This chapter sets out two main insights gleaned from our interdisciplinary work into this question. The first concerns critical reflection, a fundamental internalist condition for autonomy, and its relation to how a person's beliefs and values relate to reality. We set out a philosophical account of evidence-responsive critical reflection and suggest a neurobiological framework for it. The second insight is the introduction of a novel, internalist dimension of a classic externalist condition for autonomy—namely, how a person’s decision making is influenced by external factors and actors—which we call pre-authorization. In both cases, our analysis puts pressure on the idea that we can draw any clear distinction between internalist and externalist conditions for personal autonomy. This theoretical analysis is then applied to situations in which infringement of autonomy is a concern, such as nudging and persuasive technologies, to draw out its practical implications.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This is distinct from the metaphysical question asking whether neuroscientific experiments have shown that free will is an illusion. For those who understand “autonomy” as within the family of metaphysical freedom terms (e.g., Mele, 1995, 2012), this metaphysical question is the same as asking whether neuroscience has shown that there are no autonomous human beings. There has been a lively debate over this issue (see Lavazza, 2016). Yet, it is more common to make a distinction between personal autonomy and freedom, and we take this route. Freedom concerns the ability to act (and on some conceptions, “having sufficient resources and power to make one’s desires effective”); whereas autonomy concerns “the independence and authenticity of the desires (values, emotions, etc.) that move one to act in the first place” (Christman, 2015).

  2. 2.

    In our earliest studies of the relationship between the cognitive sciences and the concept of autonomy (Felsen & Reiner, 2011), we found that this philosophically defined hierarchical schema broadly aligns with our understanding of the fundamental neurobiology of the brain—in particular with executive control theory in which the prefrontal cortex exerts a top-down influence over other brain regions (Miller & Cohen, 2001).

  3. 3.

    Elsewhere within the philosophical debate over the nature of autonomy, what we are here labeling as a person’s set of pro-attitudes are referred to variously as her “motivational set” (Weimer, 2013), “psychological core” (Noggle, 2005), or “collection of values” (Mele, 1995).

  4. 4.

    Similar views can be found, more implicitly, in earlier accounts of autonomy. One example is Richard Arneson’s view, demonstrated by his claim that, “To live an autonomous life an agent must decide on a plan of life through critical reflection and in the process of carrying it out, remain disposed to subject the plan to critical review if […] unanticipated evidence indicates the need for such review” (Arneson, 1994).

  5. 5.

    There is a strand of autonomy theory which defines autonomous decision-making in terms of reasons-responsiveness. Without endorsing this theory, here we simply point out that evidence-responsiveness might plausibly be understood as a specific way of responding to reasons, namely responding to reasons-to-review or reasons-to-revise a pro-attitude that one currently holds (Niker et al., 2018b).

  6. 6.

    This maintenance may include engaging in evidence-responsive critical reflection in order to update the stringencies of the filters when appropriate, so that they don’t become “encrusted” in the way discussed in Section “Critical Reflection and Evidence-Responsiveness”.

  7. 7.

    Despite the initial equation of nudges with a form of paternalism, it is now well-established that nudging is a type of influence that can be used in service of different ends. While we may be motivated to nudge for paternalistic reasons, we might also use nudges for the purpose of promoting justice, utility, commercial profit, or so on.

  8. 8.

    Neurobiologically, this could be represented as shifting the starting point of the drift–diffusion process closer to one of the bounds (Felsen & Reiner, 2015). Often, as with encrusted values, bounds are set by internal biases. By changing the relative distances to bounds, nudges can be seen to counteract such internal biases in ways that are (more) consistent with the agent’s pro-attitudes.

  9. 9.

    We do recognize, though, that most of the worries about nudges to reason are diminished in the case of Momentum (vis-à-vis public policy nudges to reason) by the fact that a person has intentionally granted permission to the app to influence her decision-making in this way.

References

  • Adams, M., & Niker, F. (2021). Harnessing the epistemic value of crises for just ends. In Political Philosophy in a Pandemic: Routes to a More Just Future, F. Niker & A. Bhattacharya (Eds.), pp. 219-232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, S. (2010). The enforcement approach to coercion. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 5, 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arneson, R. (1994). Autonomy and preference formation. In In harm’s way: Essays in honor of Joel Feinberg, J. Feinberg, J. L. Coleman, & A. E. Buchanan (Eds). Cambridge University Press, pp. 42–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bagnoli, C. (2011). Morality and the emotions. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bessi, A., Zollo, F., Del Vicario, M., Puliga, M., Scala, A., Caldarelli, G., Uzzi, B., & Quattrociocchi, W. (2016). Users polarization on Facebook and Youtube, T. Preis (Ed.) PLoS ONE, 11: e0159641.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blöser, C., Schöpf, A., & Willaschek, M. (2010). Autonomy, experience, and reflection. On a neglected aspect of personal autonomy. Ethical Theory & Moral Practice, 13, 239–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bitzer, S., Hame, P., Felix, B., & Stefan, K. (2014). Perceptual decision making: Drift-diffusion model is equivalent to a Bayesian model. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 1-17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bode, S., Murawski, C., Soon, C. S., Bode, P., Stahl, J., & Smith, P. L. (2014). Demystifying “free will”: The role of contextual information and evidence accumulation for predictive brain activity. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 47, 636–645.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Buss, S., & Westlund, A. C. (2018). Personal autonomy. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calo, R. (2014). Digital market manipulation. Stanford Technology Law Review, 82, 995–1051.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castelo, N., Reiner, P. B., & Felsen, G. (2012). Balancing autonomy and decisional enhancement: An evidence-based approach. American Journal of Bioethics, 12, 30–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen-Wishart, M. (2006). Undue influence: Vindicating relationships of influence. Current Legal Problems, 59, 231–266.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christman, J. (2005). Autonomy, self-knowledge, and liberal legitimacy. In Autonomy and the challenges to liberalism: New essays, J. Christman & J. Anderson (Eds.). Cambridge University Press, pp. 330–358.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christman, J. (2010). The politics of persons: Individual autonomy and socio-historical selves. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christman, J. (2015). Autonomy in moral and political philosophy. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christman, J., & Anderson, J. (Eds.) (2005). Autonomy and the challenges to liberalism: New essays. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, M. (2006). Justice and legitimacy in upbringing. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coons, C., & Weber, M. (2013). Paternalism: Theory and practice. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coons, C., & Weber, M. (2014). Manipulation: Theory and practice. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S., & Changeux, J.-P. (2011). Experimental and theoretical approaches to conscious processing. Neuron, 70, 200–227.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S., Kerszberg, M., & Changeux, J. P. (1998). A neuronal model of a global workspace in effortful cognitive tasks. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 95, 14529–14534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Del Vicario, M., Bessi, A., Zollo, F., Petroni, F., Scala, A., Caldarelli, G., Stanley, H. E., & Quattrociocchi, W. (2016). The spreading of misinformation online. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 113, 554–559.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. M. (2002). Lack of character. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. M. (2015). Talking to our selves. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, G. (1988). The theory and practice of autonomy. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Engelen, B., & Nys, T. (2020). Nudging and autonomy: Analyzing and alleviating the worries. Review of Philosophy Psychology, 11, 137–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, M., & Willer, R. (2019). Moral reframing: A technique for effective and persuasive communication across political divides. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 13, e12501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Felsen, G., Castelo, N., & Reiner, P. B. (2013). Decisional enhancement and autonomy: Public attitudes towards overt and covert nudges. Judgment and Decision Making, 8, 202–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Felsen, G., & Reiner, P. B. (2011). How the neuroscience of decision making informs our conception of autonomy. AJOB Neuroscience, 2, 3–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Felsen, G., & Reiner, P. B. (2015). What can neuroscience contribute to the debate over nudging? Review of Philosophy Psychology, 6, 469–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitz, N. S., & Reiner, P. B. (2016). Perspective: Time to expand the mind. Nature, 531, S9–S9.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. G. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. The Journal of Philosophy, 68, 5–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (2003). Autonomy and social relationships: Rethinking the feminist critique. In Autonomy, gender, politics, M. Friedman (Ed.). Oxford University Press pp. 81–97.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Frischmann, B. M., & Selinger, E. (2018). Re-engineering humanity. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G., & Gaissmaier, W. (2011). Heuristic decision making. Annual Review of Psychology, 62, 451–482.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Gold, J. I., & Shadlen, M. N. (2007). The neural basis of decision making. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 30, 535–574.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin, T. (2012). Why We Should Reject “Nudge.” Politics, 32, 85–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grune-Yanoff, T. (2012). Old wine in new casks: Libertarian paternalism still violates liberal principles. Social Choice and Welfare, 38, 635–645.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gutchess, A. (2014). Plasticity of the aging brain: New directions in cognitive neuroscience. Science, 346, 579–582.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. (2011). The public ecology of responsibility. In Responsibility and distributive justice, C. Knight, & Z. Stemplowska (Eds.). Oxford University Press, pp. 187–217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jung, J. Y., & Mellers, B. A. (2016). American attitudes toward nudges. Judgment and Decision Making, 11, 62–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klinzing, J. G., Niethard, N., & Born, J. (2019). Mechanisms of systems memory consolidation during sleep. Nature Neuroscience, 35, 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knill, D. C., & Pouget, A. (2004). The Bayesian brain: The role of uncertainty in neural coding and computation. Trends in Neurosciences, 27, 712–719.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kosinski, M., Stillwell, D., & Graepel, T. (2013). Private traits and attributes are predictable from digital records of human behavior. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 110, 5802–5805.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Lavazza, A. (2016). Free will and neuroscience: From explaining freedom away to new ways of operationalizing and measuring it. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 10, 1-17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. (2017). Nudges in a post-truth world. Journal of Medical Ethics, 43, 495–500.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, C., & Stoljar, N. (2000). Relational autonomy: Feminist perspectives on automony, agency, and the social self. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matz, S. C., Kosinski, M., Nave, G., & Stillwell, D. J. (2017). Psychological targeting as an effective approach to digital mass persuasion. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 114, 12714–12719.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • May, J., & Kumar, V. (2018). Moral reasoning and emotion. In The Routledge Handbook of Moral Epistemology, pp. 139–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, R. (2020). Persuasion and epistemic paternalism. In Guy Axtell & Amiel Bernal (Eds.), Epistemic paternalism: Conceptions, justifications, and implications. Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 91-106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. R. (1995). Autonomous agents. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. R. (2012). Another scientific threat to free will? The Monist, 95, 422–440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meyers, D. T. (1989). Self, society, and personal choice. Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyniel, F., & Dehaene, S. (2017). Brain networks for confidence weighting and hierarchical inference during probabilistic learning. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 71, 201615773.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, E. K., & Cohen, J. (2001). An integrative theory of prefrontal cortex function. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 24, 167–202.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Moles, A. (2015). Nudging for liberals. Social Theory and Practice, 41, 644–667.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulder, M. J., Wagenmakers, E. J., Ratcliff, R., Beokel, W., & Forstmann, B. U. (2012). Bias in the brain: A diffusion model analysis of prior probability and potential payoff. Journal of Neuroscience, 32, 2335–2343.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Nader, K. (2015). Reconsolidation and the dynamic nature of memory. Cold Spring Harbor Perspectives in Biology, 7, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, S. K. (2015). When aid is a good thing: Trusting relationships as autonomy support in health care settings. The American Journal of Bioethics, 15, 49–51.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, S. K., & Reiner, P. B. (2013). Autonomy support to foster individuals’ flourishing. American Journal of Bioethics, 13, 36–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niker, F. (2018). Policy-led virtue cultivation: Can we nudge citizens towards developing virtues? In The theory and practice of virtue education, T. Harrison & D. Walker (Eds). Routledge, pp. 153–167.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niker, F., Reiner, P. B., & Felsen, G. (2016). Pre-authorization: A novel decision-making heuristic that may promote autonomy. American Journal of Bioethics, 16, 27–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niker, F., & Specker Sullivan, L. (2018). Trusting relationships and the ethics of interpersonal action. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 26, 173-186.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niker, F., Reiner, P. B., & Felsen, G. (2018a). Perceptions of undue influence shed light on the folk conception of autonomy. Frontiers in Psychology, 9, 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niker, F., Reiner, P. B., & Felsen, G. (2018b). Updating our selves: Synthesizing philosophical and neurobiological perspectives on incorporating new information into our worldview. Neuroethics, 11, 273–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noggle, R. (2005). Autonomy and the paradox of self-creation: Infinite regresses, finite selves, and the limits of authenticity. In New essays on personal autonomy and its role in contemporary moral philosophy, J. S. Taylor (Ed.). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nyhan, B., & Reifler, J. (2013). Which corrections work? Research results and practice recommendations. New America Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, O. (2018). Linking trust to trustworthiness. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 26, 1–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliff, R., & Rouder, J. N. (2016). Modeling response times for two-choice decisions. Psychological Science : A Journal of the American Psychological Society, 9, 347–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reeve, J. (1998). Autonomy support as an interpersonal motivating style: Is it teachable? Contemporary Educational Psychology, 23, 312–330.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Reiner, P. B., & Nagel, S. K. (2017). Technologies of the extended mind: Defining the issues. In Neuroethics: Anticipating the future, J. Illes (Ed.). Oxford University Press, pp. 111–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryan, R. M., & Deci, E. L. (2000). Intrinsic and extrinsic motivations: Classic definitions and new directions. Contemporary Educational Psychology, 25, 54–67.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Samanez-Larkin, G. R., & Knutson, B. (2015). Decision making in the ageing brain: Changes in affective and motivational circuits. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 16, 278–289.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Shadlen, M. N., & Roskies, A. L. (2012). The neurobiology of decision-making and responsibility: Reconciling mechanism and mindedness. Frontiers in Neuroscience, 6, 1-12.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. (1972). Theories of bounded rationality. In Decision and Organization, C. B. McGuire, & R. Radner (Eds.). North-Holland, pp. 161-176.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, P. L., & Ratcliff, R. (2004). Psychology and neurobiology of simple decisions. Trends in Neurosciences, 27, 161–168.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Specker Sullivan, L., & Niker, F. (2018). Relational autonomy, paternalism, and maternalism. Ethical Theory & Moral Practice, 21, 649–667.

    Google Scholar 

  • Specker Sullivan, L., & Reiner, P. B. (2019). Digital wellness and persuasive technologies. Philosophy & Technology, 34, 413–424.

    Google Scholar 

  • Squire, L. R. (2004). Memory systems of the brain: A brief history and current perspective. Neurobiology of Learning and Memory, 82, 171–177.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich, K. E., & West, R. F. (2000). Individual differences in reasoning: Implications for the rationality debate? The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23, 645–665.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. R. (2016). The ethics of influence: Government in the age of behavioral science. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Susser, D., Roessler, B., & Nissenbaum, H. F. (2019). Online manipulation: Hidden influences in a digital world. Georgetown Law Technology Review, 4, 1-45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tannenbaum, D., Fox, C. R., & Rogers, T. (2017). On the misplaced politics of behavioural policy interventions. Nature Human Behaviour, 1, 0130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R. H., & Sunstein, C. R. (2009). Nudge. Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tononi, G., & Cirelli, C. (2014). Sleep and the price of plasticity: From synaptic and cellular homeostasis to memory consolidation and integration. Neuron, 81, 12–34.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1981). The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science, 211, 453–458.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. (2014). It’s all for your own good. The New York Review of Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weimer, S. (2013). Evidence-responsiveness and autonomy. Ethical Theory & Moral Practice, 16, 621–642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weimer, S. (2017). Evidence-responsiveness and the ongoing autonomy of treatment preferences. HEC Forum, 13, 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, A. (2014). Coercion. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, T. M. (2013). Nudging and manipulation. Political Studies, 61, 341–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, J. (2018). Stand out of our light: Freedom and resistance in the attention economy. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yeung, K. (2012). Nudge as fudge. The Modern Law Review, 75, 122–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yeung, K. (2016). “Hypernudge”: Big data as a mode of regulation by design. The Information Society, 20, 118–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niker, F., & Specker Sullivan, L. (2018). Trusting relationships and the ethics of interpersonal action. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 26, 173-186.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adams, M., & Niker, F. (2021). Harnessing the epistemic value of crises for just ends. In Political Philosophy in a Pandemic: Routes to a More Just Future, F. Niker & A. Bhattacharya (Eds.), pp. 219-232. 

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Fay Niker .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Niker, F., Felsen, G., Nagel, S.K., Reiner, P.B. (2021). Autonomy, Evidence-Responsiveness, and the Ethics of Influence. In: Blitz, M.J., Bublitz, J.C. (eds) The Law and Ethics of Freedom of Thought, Volume 1. Palgrave Studies in Law, Neuroscience, and Human Behavior. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-84494-3_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics