Skip to main content
Log in

Equilibrium selection through \(\mathbf {p}_{u}\)-dominance

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Economic Theory Bulletin Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The paper introduces and discusses the concept of \(\mathbf {p}_{u}\)-dominance in the context of finite games in normal form. It then presents the \(\mathbf { p}_{u}\)-dominance criterion for equilibrium selection. The \(\mathbf {p}_{u}\)-dominance criterion is inspired by and closely related to the \(\mathbf {p}\)-dominance criterion originally proposed by Morris et al. (Econometrica 63:145–157, 1995). However, there are games in which the two criteria lead to different refinements. We provide sufficient conditions under which equilibrium selection through \(\mathbf {p}_{u}\)-dominance is weakly finer (respectively, coarser) than equilibrium selection through \(\mathbf {p}\)-dominance.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The fact that the conjecture posits that players use a uniform distribution to randomize over the actions that do not belong to the profile under scrutiny explains the subscript “\(u\)” in the term “\(\mathbf {p}_{u}\)-dominance”. This should not be confused with the concept of \(u\)-dominance Kojima (2006) that has been proposed as a criterion for equilibrium selection based on perfect foresight dynamics and that assumes that the number of opponents adopting a certain strategy follows a uniform distribution.

  2. Tercieux (2006a, b) further extends the concept of \(\mathbf {p}\)-dominance by introducing the notion of \(\mathbf {p}\)-best response set: a set profile \(S=(S_{1},\ldots ,S_{n})\) is a \(\mathbf {p}\)-best response set if for every \(i\) the set \(S_{i}\) contains an action that best responds to any conjecture that assigns probability of at least \(p_{i}\) to the event that other players select their action from \(S_{-i}\).

  3. Notice that the actions that the \(\mathbf {p}\)-dominance conjecture disregards are not necessarily dominated (see for instance action \(M\) in the game in Example 1). Notice also that the \(\mathbf {p}_{u}\)-dominance conjecture suffers instead from the opposite problem as it assigns positive probability to the event that the opponents play strictly dominated actions (if these exist). Still, this shortcoming can be easily fixed by applying the \(\mathbf {p}_{u}\)-dominance criterion only after the elimination of all strictly dominated actions.

  4. If an undominated action does not exist then \(a^{*}\) is \(\mathbf {p}_{u}\)-dominant as well \(\mathbf {p}\)-dominant with \(\bar{\mathbf {p}}_{u}\left( a^{*}\right) =\bar{\mathbf {p}}\left( a^{*}\right) =(0,\ldots ,0)\).

References

  • Harsanyi, J., Selten, R.: A General Theory of Equilibrium Selection in Games. MIT Press, Cambridge (1988)

    Google Scholar 

  • Haruvy, E., Stahl, D.O.: Equilibrium selection and bounded rationality in symmetric normal-form games. J. Econ. Behav. Org. 62, 98–119 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kajii, A., Morris, S.: The robustness of equilibria to incomplete information. Econometrica 65, 1283–1309 (1997)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, Y.: Equilibrium selection in n-person coordination games. Games Econ. Behav. 15, 203–227 (1996)

  • Kojima, F.: Risk-dominance and perfect foresight dynamics in n-player games. J. Econ. Theory 128, 255–273 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morris, S., Rob, R., Shin, H.S.: \(p\) -Dominance and belief potential. Econometrica 63, 145–157 (1995)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stahl, D.O., Wilson, P.W.: On players’ models of other players: theory and experimental evidence. Games Econ. Behav. 10, 218–254 (1995)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tercieux, O.: \(p\)-Best response set. J. Econ. Theory 131, 45–70 (2006a)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tercieux, O.: \(p\)-Best response set and the robustness of equilibria to incomplete information. Games Econ. Behav. 56, 371–384 (2006b)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weizsäcker, G.: Ignoring the rationality of others: evidence from experimental normal-form games. Games Econ. Behav. 44, 145–171 (2003)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrea Gallice.

Appendix

Appendix

1.1 Proof of Proposition 2

If \(a^{*}\) is a Nash equilibrium of \(G,\) then there exists at least one vector for which \(a^{*}\) is \(\mathbf {p}\)-dominant. In particular, \( a^{*}\) is certainly \(\mathbf {p}\)-dominant for \(\mathbf {p}( a^{*}) =(1,\ldots ,1)\). It follows that the vector \(\bar{\mathbf {p}}( a^{*}) =( \bar{p}_{1}(a^{*}),\ldots ,\bar{p}_{n}(a^{*})) \) also exists where, for any \(i\) and any \(j\ne i\), \(\bar{p} _{i}(a^{*})\) is the smallest probability for which action \(a_{i}^{*}\) best responds to any conjecture \(\lambda (a^{*}) \in \Delta ( A_{-i}) \) according to which \(\lambda (a_{j}^{*}) \ge \bar{p}_{i}(a^{*})\) while the remaining probability \(( 1-\lambda ( a_{j}^{*}) ) \) can follow any distribution on actions \(a_{j}\ne a_{j}^{*}\). The conjecture thus includes the situation in which \(\lambda (a_{j}) =\frac{( 1-\lambda ( a_{j}^{*}) ) }{k_{j}-1}\) for any \(j\ne i\), \(a_{j}\ne a_{j}^{*}\) and \(k_{j}=\left| A_{j}\right| \). Therefore, if \(a^{*}\) is \(\mathbf {p}\)-dominant with \(\bar{\mathbf {p}} ( a^{*}) \) then \(a^{*}\) is also \(\mathbf {p}_{u}\)-dominant with \(\mathbf {p}_{u}( a^{*}) =\bar{\mathbf {p}}( a^{*}) \). Notice that if \(k_{j}=2\) for any \(j\in N\), then \(\bar{\mathbf {p}} _{u}(a^{*}) =\bar{\mathbf {p}}( a^{*}) \) as both \(\mathbf {p}\)-dominance and \(\mathbf {p}_{u}\)-dominance assign probability \(( 1-\lambda ( a_{j}^{*})) \) to the event of \(j\) playing action \(a_{j}\ne a_{j}^{*}\). Now consider the case in which \(k_{j}>2\) for some \(j\). Assume there exists at least one action \( a_{i}\in A_{i}\) that is not (weakly or strictly) dominated by \(a_{i}^{*}\) .Footnote 4 Let \( \tilde{a}(a_{i})=(a_{i},\tilde{a}_{-i})\) be the action profile that supports the (non-necessarily unique) outcome for which \( u_{i}(a_{i},a_{-i})-u_{i}(a_{i}^{*},a_{-i})>0\) is maximal. Given that \( u_{i}(a_{i},a_{-i}^{*})-u_{i}(a_{i}^{*},a_{-i}^{*})\le 0\) (\( a^{*}\) is a Nash equilibrium), it must be the case that in \(\tilde{a} (a_{i})\) there is at least one player \(j\ne i\) that plays \(\tilde{a} _{j}\ne a_{j}^{*}\). The equilibrium \(a^{*}\) is \(\mathbf {p}\)-dominant with \(\bar{\mathbf {p}}\left( a^{*}\right) =\left( \bar{p} _{1}(a^{*}),\ldots ,\bar{p}_{n}(a^{*})\right) \) if \(a_{i}^{*}\) dominates any \(a_{i}\) even under the specific conjecture that assigns probability \(\left( 1-\bar{p}_{i}(a^{*})\right) \) to the event of \(j\) playing \(\tilde{a}_{j}\ne a_{j}^{*}\). On the other hand, \(a^{*}\) is \(\mathbf {p}_{u}\)-dominant with \(\bar{\mathbf {p}}_{u}\left( a^{*}\right) =\left( \bar{p}_{1}^{\prime }(a^{*}),\ldots ,\bar{p}_{n}^{\prime }(a^{*})\right) \) if \(a_{i}^{*}\) dominates any \(a_{i}\) under the conjecture that assigns probability \(\left( \frac{1-\bar{p}_{i}^{\prime }(a^{*})}{ k_{j}-1}\right) \) to the event of \(j\) playing \(\tilde{a}_{j}\ne a_{j}^{*}\). Equilibrium \(a^{*}\) cannot be \(\mathbf {p}\)-dominant with \(\mathbf {p} \left( a^{*}\right) =\bar{\mathbf {p}}_{u}\left( a^{*}\right) \) given that \(( 1-\bar{p}_{i}^{\prime }(a^{*})) > \left( \frac{1-\bar{p }_{i}^{\prime }(a^{*})}{k_{j}-1}\right) \) and the conjecture would thus assign too much probability to the occurrence of the profile \(\tilde{a} (a_{i})\). It then must be the case that \(\bar{p}_{i}^{\prime }(a^{*})< \bar{p}_{i}(a^{*})\). We can thus conclude that \(\bar{\mathbf {p}} _{u}\left( a^{*}\right) \le \bar{\mathbf {p}}\left( a^{*}\right) \).

1.2 Proof of Lemma 1

Without loss of generality, assume the \(\mathbf {p}_{u}\)-dominance criterion selects two equilibria, i.e., let \(A^{**}=\{a^{**1},a^{**2}\} \). By expression (2) this means:

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{i=1}^{n}\bar{p}_{i}(a^{**1})=\sum _{i=1}^{n}\bar{p}_{i}(a^{**2}) \end{aligned}$$
(3)

The fact that \(G\) is symmetric implies that (3) reduces to \( \bar{\mathbf {p}}_{u}(a^{**1})=\bar{\mathbf {p}}_{u}(a^{**2})\), i.e., \(\bar{p}_{i}(a^{**1})=\bar{p}_{i}(a^{**2})\) for any \( i\in N\). Now define the conjecture \(\bar{\lambda }( a^{**\phi }) \) with \(\phi \in \left\{ 1,2\right\} \) such that \(\bar{\lambda } ( a_{j}^{**\phi }) =\bar{p}_{i}(a^{**\phi })\) and \(\bar{\lambda }( a_{j}) =\frac{( 1-\bar{p}_{i}(a^{**\phi }) ) }{k-1}\) for all \(a_{j}\ne a_{j}^{**\phi } \) and for \(j\in N_{-i}\). Let \(\lambda ^{(\phi )}( a_{-i}) =\times _{j\in N_{-1}}\bar{\lambda }( a^{**\phi }) \). With the probability distribution \(\lambda ^{(\phi )}\), any player is by construction indifferent between playing action \(a_{i}^{**\phi }\) and action \(a_{i}^{**\xi }\) with \(\xi \in \{ 1,2\} \) and \( \xi \ne \phi \). This implies that the following two conditions must simultaneously hold:

$$\begin{aligned} \sum \limits _{a_{-i}\in A_{-i}}\lambda ^{(1)}\left( a_{-i}\right) u_{i}\left( a_{i}^{**1},a_{-i}\right) =\sum \limits _{a_{-i}\in A_{-i}}\lambda ^{(1)}\left( a_{-i}\right) u_{i}\left( a_{i}^{**2},a_{-i}\right) \end{aligned}$$
(4)
$$\begin{aligned} \sum \limits _{a_{-i}\in A_{-i}}\lambda ^{(2)}\left( a_{-i}\right) u_{i}\left( a_{i}^{**2},a_{-i}\right) =\sum \limits _{a_{-i}\in A_{-i}}\lambda ^{(2)}\left( a_{-i}\right) u_{i}\left( a_{i}^{**1},a_{-i}\right) \end{aligned}$$
(5)

Therefore, the following condition also holds:

$$\begin{aligned}&\sum \limits _{a_{-i}\in A_{-i}}\lambda ^{(1)}\left( a_{-i}\right) u_{i}\left( a_{i}^{**1},a_{-i}\right) -\sum \limits _{a_{-i}\in A_{-i}}\lambda ^{(1)}\left( a_{-i}\right) u_{i}\left( a_{i}^{**2},a_{-i}\right) \nonumber \\&\quad =\sum \limits _{a_{-i}\in A_{-i}}\lambda ^{(2)}\left( a_{-i}\right) u_{i}\left( a_{i}^{**1},a_{-i}\right) -\sum \limits _{a_{-i}\in A_{-i}}\lambda ^{(2)}\left( a_{-i}\right) u_{i}\left( a_{i}^{**2},a_{-i}\right) \end{aligned}$$
(6)

Now notice that, given that by assumption \(A^{**}=\{ a^{**1},a^{**2}\} \) then it must be the case that \( \bar{p}_{i}(a^{**1})=\bar{p}_{i}(a^{**2})\) for any \(i\in N\). Therefore, \(\frac{\left( 1-\bar{p}_{i}\left( a^{**1}\right) \right) }{ k-1}=\frac{\left( 1-\bar{p}_{i}\left( a^{**2}\right) \right) }{k-1}\) for any \(i\in N\). Expression (6) thus boils down to:

$$\begin{aligned}&\left( \left( \bar{p}_{i}(a^{**1})\right) ^{n-1}-\left( \frac{ \left( 1-\bar{p}_{i}\left( a^{**1}\right) \right) }{k-1}\right) ^{n-1}\right) \left( u_{i}\left( a_{i}^{**1},a_{-i}^{**1}\right) -u_{i}\left( a_{i}^{**2},a_{-i}^{**1}\right) \right) \nonumber \\&\quad =\left( \!\!\left( \bar{p}_{i}(a^{**1})\right) ^{n-1}-\left( \frac{\left( 1-\bar{p} _{i}\left( a^{**1}\right) \right) }{k-1}\right) ^{n-1}\right) \left( u_{i}\left( a_{i}^{**1},a_{-i}^{**2}\right) -u_{i}\left( a_{i}^{**2},a_{-i}^{**2}\!\right) \!\right) \nonumber \\ \end{aligned}$$
(7)

The fact that \(a^{**1}\) and \(a^{**2}\) are Nash equilibria implies that \(( u_{i}( a_{i}^{**1},a_{-i}^{**1}) -u_{i}( a_{i}^{**2},a_{-i}^{**1}) ) \ge 0\) and \((u_{i}( a_{i}^{**1},a_{-i}^{**2}) -u_{i}( a_{i}^{**2},a_{-i}^{**2}) ) \le 0\) with at least one strict inequality if at least one equilibrium is strict. Then, for expression (7) to always hold [notice that both \(\bar{p}_{i}(a^{**1})\) and \(\left( \frac{1-\bar{p}_{i}(a^{**1})}{k-1}\right) \) are non-negative and cannot be simultaneously equal to zero], it must be the case that \(\bar{p}_{i}(a^{**1})=\left( \frac{1-\bar{p}_{i}(a^{**1})}{k-1}\right) \). But since \( \bar{p}_{i}(a^{**1})=\bar{p}_{i}(a^{**2})\) then the following result holds:

$$\begin{aligned} \bar{p}_{i}(a^{**\phi })=\left( \frac{1-\bar{p}_{i}(a^{**\phi })}{k-1}\right) \quad \text { for }\phi \in \left\{ 1,2\right\} \end{aligned}$$
(8)

which implies \(\bar{p}_{i}(a^{**\phi })=\frac{1}{k}\) for any \(\phi \in \left\{ 1,2\right\} \). Given that the choice of \(\left| A^{**}\right| =2\) was made without loss of generality as one can replicate the passages above for any possible couple of equilibria that belong to \(A^{**}\), the more general result that \(\bar{\mathbf {p}} _{u}(a^{**\phi })=\left( \frac{1}{k},\ldots ,\frac{1}{k}\right) \) for any \(a^{**\phi }\in A^{**}=\left\{ a^{**1},\ldots ,a^{**\Phi }\right\} \) and \(\Phi \ge 2\) easily follows.

1.3 Proof of Proposition 3

Assume the \(\mathbf {p}_{u}\)-dominance criterion selects multiple equilibria. Without loss of generality, let \(A^{**}=\left\{ a^{**1},a^{**2}\right\} \) be the set of selected equilibria. Then:

$$\begin{aligned} \sum \limits _{a_{-i}\in A_{-i}}\lambda ^{(1)}\left( a_{-i}\right) u_{i}\left( a_{i}^{**1},a_{-i}\right) =\sum \limits _{a_{-i}\in A_{-i}}\lambda ^{(1)}\left( a_{-i}\right) u_{i}\left( a_{i}^{**2},a_{-i}\right) \end{aligned}$$
(9)

where \(\lambda ^{(1)}\left( a_{-i}\right) =\times _{j\in N_{-1}}\lambda ^{1}\left( a_{j}\right) \) and \(\lambda ^{1}\left( a_{j}\right) =\bar{p} _{i}(a^{**1})\) if \(a_{j}=a_{j}^{**1}\) while \(\lambda ^{1}\left( a_{j}\right) =\frac{\left( 1-\bar{p}_{i}\left( a^{**1}\right) \right) }{k-1}\) if \(a_{j}\ne a_{j}^{**1}\) for any \(j\in N_{-i}\). But given that \(a^{**1}\in A^{**}\) and \(\left| A^{**}\right| >1\), Lemma 1 implies that \(\bar{p}_{i}(a^{**1})=\frac{\left( 1-\bar{p}_{i}\left( a^{**1}\right) \right) }{ k-1}=\frac{1}{k}\). Therefore, (9) becomes:

$$\begin{aligned} \left( \frac{1}{k}\right) ^{n-1}\sum _{a_{-i}\in A_{-i}}u_{i}(a_{i}^{**1},a_{-i})=\left( \frac{1}{k}\right) ^{n-1}\sum _{a_{-i}\in A_{-i}}u_{i}(a_{i}^{**2},a_{-i}) \end{aligned}$$
(10)

which necessarily requires:

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{a_{-i}\in A_{-i}}u_{i}(a_{i}^{**1},a_{-i})=\sum _{a_{-i}\in A_{-i}}u_{i}(a_{i}^{**2},a_{-i}). \end{aligned}$$
(11)

It follows that if the above condition does not hold then \(a^{**1}\) and \(a^{**1}\) cannot simultaneously belong to \(A^{**}\). Therefore, a sufficient condition for the \(\mathbf {p}_{u}\)-dominance criterion to select a unique equilibrium is that the sum of an agent’s individual payoffs across any equilibrium action differs. More formally:

$$\begin{aligned} \sum \limits _{a_{-i}\in A_{-i}}u_{i}(a_{i}^{*\psi },a_{-i})\ne \sum \limits _{a_{-i}\in A_{-i}}u_{i}(a_{i}^{*\xi },a_{-i})\quad \text { for any } a_{i}^{*\psi },a_{i}^{*\xi }\in A^{*}\text { and }a_{i}^{*\psi }\ne a_{i}^{*\xi } \end{aligned}$$

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gallice, A. Equilibrium selection through \(\mathbf {p}_{u}\)-dominance. Econ Theory Bull 3, 53–64 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40505-015-0069-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40505-015-0069-5

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation