Skip to main content
Log in

Fragment answers and movement

A superlative argument

  • Published:
Natural Language & Linguistic Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The nature of fragment answers has been under debate for the past 40 years. Most of the arguments have focused on the mobility and island-(in)sensitivity of the fragments. This paper offers a new empirical domain of investigation: interpretative differences between fragment answers and their full sentence counterparts. I present data regarding an interpretation of superlative expressions that is available only with overt movement but not covert movement, and show that fragment answers allow the reading while their full sentence counterparts do not. Thus I argue that in some cases fragment answers must involve movement in the narrow syntax. Approaches to fragment answers that exclusively involve PF movement of the fragments or in situ fragment answers are challenged.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See fn. 13 for a brief discussion of approaches that do not involve underlying structures.

  2. Nishigauchi and Fujii (2006) made a case of this nature which involves an interpretation of Japanese anaphora that is possible in clefts and fragment answers but not in full answers.

  3. Note that here I modified Szabolczi’s original examples ‘take the best picture of’ to ‘take the largest photo of.’ The motivation for this change is that the sentences that allow the Rin also allow the absolute reading. To make sure the Rin is being probed, the sentences need to be judged under an unambiguous scenario where the absolute reading is false and the Rin is true (as in Fig. 1). Such scenarios work the best when concrete properties (e.g. sizes of the photos) are being compared rather than abstract or subjective properties (e.g. goodness of the photos).

  4. If not specified otherwise, the judgements reported in this paper come from a survey I conducted with seven native English speakers including North American, British, and Trinidad and Tobago varieties of English. If not specified, all seven speakers agree on the judgements.

  5. The relevant foci are Ben in (9a), who in (9b) and (9d), and the boy in (9c).

  6. As Shen (2015) and an NLLT reviewer pointed out, topicalization of Ben does not make the Rin possible in (i). This is expected because the semantics of the Rin requires Ben to be the focus. Since an element that bears focus cannot be topic at the same time, topicalization does not make the Rin available. See Pancheva and Tomaszewicz (2012) and discussion following (11) for the semantics of the Rin.

    1. i.

      Ben, Sally took the largest photo of. (# Rin)

  7. Thanks to Patrick Elliott for pointing this out.

  8. The syntactic identity theories of ellipsis have been argued for in Chomsky (1965), Ross (1967), Sag (1976), Chung et al. (1995), Lasnik (1995), Fox (2000), Tomioka (2008), Merchant (2013a) among others.

  9. For semantic identity theories, see Ginzburg and Sag (2000), Merchant (2001, 2004), Reich (2007), AnderBois (2011), Barker (2013), Weir (2014), Barros (2014). For hybrid theories, see Rooth (1992), Chung and Ladusaw (2006), Chung (2013), Merchant (2008), van Craenenbroeck (2012), Merchant (2013b).

  10. Note that ‘a photo of no one’ can be interpreted to mean a blank photo. This interpretation is not relevant to the current discussion.

  11. In what follows, I use the in situ approach for demonstration. The alternative source argument as well as the upcoming argument against it also goes to the PF movement approach.

  12. Note the judgements of (25) involving reciprocals are less clear than those of (21) and (22) involving negative quantifiers. That being said, at least four native English speakers in my survey showed the reported judgements.

  13. Note that the argument presented here is an argument for movement (in particular, for movement in the narrow syntax), not one for deletion. Apart from the approaches to fragment answers discussed so far, there is a non-movement, non-deletion approach in the literature (see Riemsdijk 1978; Ginzburg and Sag 2000; Stainton 2006; Valmala 2007; Jacobson 2016). In this approach, fragment answers do not have an underlying full-sentence structure. Under this approach, the fragment answer trivially allows the Rin as long as the question allows it due the question-answer congruence conditions. Thus the existence of the Rin is not an argument for or against the non-deletion approach. See Merchant (2004) for arguments against this approach.

References

  • Abe, Jun. 2016. Make short answers shorter: Support for the in-situ approach. Syntax 19(3): 223–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • AnderBois, Scott. 2011. Issues and alternatives. PhD diss., UCSC.

  • Barker, Chris. 2013. Scopability and sluicing. Linguistics and Philosophy 36 (3): 187–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barros, Matthew. 2014. Sluicing and identity in ellipsis. PhD diss., Rutgers University.

  • Bruening, Benjamin. 2001. QR obeys superiority: Frozen scope and ACD. Linguistic Inquiry 32(2): 233–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruening, Benjamin. 2015. Non-constituent coordination: Prosody, not movement. University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics 21(1).

  • Chomsky, Noam. 1965. Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam, and Howard Lasnik. 1993. Principles and parameter theory. In Syntax: An international handbook of contemporary research, eds. Arnim von Stechow, Wolfgang Sternefeld, and Theo Vennemann, 506–569. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chung, Sandra. 2013. Syntactic identity in sluicing: How much and why. Linguistic Inquiry 44(1): 1–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chung, Sandra, and William A. Ladusaw. 2006. Chamorro: Evidence for compositional asymmetry. Natural Language Semantics 14(4): 325–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chung, Sandra, William A. Ladusaw, and James McCloskey. 1995. Sluicing and Logical Form. Natural Language Semantics 3(3): 239–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dikken, Marcel den, André Meinunger, and Chris Wilder. 2000. Pseudoclefts and ellipsis. Studia Linguistica 54(1): 41–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farkas, Donka F., and Katalin E. Kiss. 2000. On the comparative and absolute readings of superlatives. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 18(3): 417–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, Danny. 2000. Economy and semantic interpretation. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox, Danny. 2014. Cancelling the maxim of quantity: Another challenge for a Gricean theory of scalar implicatures. Semantics and Pragmatics 7: 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ginzburg, Jonathan, and Ivan Sag. 2000. Interrogative investigations. Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hankamer, Jorge. 1979. Deletion in coordinate structures. New York: Garland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, Irene. 1999. Notes on superlatives. Ms., MIT.

  • Jacobson, Pauline. 2016. The short answer: Implications for Direct Compositionality (and vice-versa). Language 92(2): 331–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lasnik, Howard. 1995. Case and expletives revisited: On greed and other human failings. Linguistic Inquiry 26(4): 615–634.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipták, Anikó. 2015. Identity in ellipsis: An introduction. Lingua 166: 155–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merchant, Jason. 2001. The syntax of silence: Sluicing, islands, and the theory of ellipsis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merchant, Jason. 2004. Fragments and ellipsis. Linguistics and philosophy 27(6): 661–738.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merchant, Jason. 2008. Variable island repair under ellipsis. In Topics in ellipsis, ed. Kyle Johnson, 132–153. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merchant, Jason. 2013a. Polarity items under ellipsis. In Diagnosing Ellipsis, eds. Lisa Cheng and Norbert Corver, 441–462. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merchant, Jason. 2013b. Voice and ellipsis. Linguistic Inquiry 44: 77–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, Jerry. 1973. Sentence fragments and the notion “sentence”. In Cls 25, parasession on language in context, eds. Braj Kachru, Robert Lees, Yakov Malkiel, Angelina Pietrangeli, and Sol Saporta. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Napoli, Donna. 1982. Initial material deletion in English. Glossa 16: 85–111.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nishigauchi, Taisuke, and Tomohiro Fujii. 2006. Short answers: Ellipsis, connectivity, and island repair. Ms., Kobe Shoin Graduate School and University of Maryland.

  • Ott, Dennis, and Volker Struckmeier. 2016. Deletion in clausal ellipsis: Remnants in the middle field. University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics 22(1).

  • Pancheva, Roumyana, and Barbara Tomaszewicz. 2012. Cross-linguistic differences in superlative movement out of nominal phrases. In 30th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics (WCCFL), eds. Nathan Arnett and Ryan Bennett, 292–302. Somerville: Cascadilla Proceedings Project.

    Google Scholar 

  • Postal, Paul. 1993. Some defective paradigms. Linguistic Inquiry 24(2): 347–364.

    Google Scholar 

  • Progovac, Ljiljana. 2013. Non-sentential vs. ellipsis approaches: Review and extensions. Language and Linguistics Compass 7(11): 597–617.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reeve, Matthew. 2011. The syntax structure of English cleft. Lingua 121(2): 142–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reich, Ingo. 2007. Toward a uniform analysis of short answers and gapping. In On information structure, meaning and form, eds. Kerstin Schwabe and Susanne Winkler. Amsterdam: Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, Norvin. 2001. Movement in language: Interactions and architectures. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riemsdijk, Henk van. 1978. A case study in syntactic markedness. Dordrecht: Foris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rooth, Mats. 1992. A theory of focus interpretation. Natural Language Semantics 1(1): 117–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, John. 1967. Constraints on variables in syntax. PhD diss., Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

  • Sag, Ivan. 1976. Deletion and logical form. PhD diss., Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

  • Sharvit, Yael, and Penka Stateva. 2002. Superlative expressions, context, and focus. Linguistics and Philosophy 25(4): 245–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shen, Zheng. 2014. On the relative readings with NP internal focus of superlatives. In 31st West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics (WCCFL), ed. Robert E. Santana-LaBarge, 409–418. Somerville: Cascadilla Proceedings Project.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shen, Zheng. 2015. The third reading of the most expensive photo of Abby. University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics 21(1).

  • Stainton, Robert J. 2006. Words and thoughts: Subsentences, ellipsis, and the philosophy of language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Szabolcsi, Anna. 1986. Comparative superlatives. In MIT working papers in linguistics, Vol. 8, eds. Naoki Fukui, Tova Rapoport, and Elizabeth Sagey. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomaszewicz, Barbara M. 2015. Superlative ambiguity: A comparative perspective. PhD diss., University of Southern California.

  • Tomioka, Satoshi. 2008. A step-by-step guide to ellipsis resolution. In Topics in ellipsis, ed. Kyle Johnson, 210–228. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valmala, Vidal. 2007. The syntax of little things. Talk at the 17th Colloquium on Generative Grammar, Girona, Spain.

  • van Craenenbroeck, Jeroen. 2012. Ellipsis, identity and accommodation. Ms., CRISSP/Hogeschool-Universiteit Brussel.

  • Weir, Andrew. 2014. Fragments and clausal ellipsis. PhD diss., University of Massachusetts at Amherst.

  • Weir, Andrew. 2015. Fragment answers and exceptional movement under ellipsis: A PF-movement account. Talk at the 89th Annual Meeting of the Linguistic Society of America (LSA), Portland, Oregon.

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank Susi Wurmbrand, Jonathan Bobaljik, Željko Bošković, Jon Gajewski, Jason Merchant, Troy Messick, Ian Roberts, Marcin Dadan, three anonymous reviewers and the managing editor Jason Merchant at NLLT for their insightful comments and suggestions. Earlier versions of this work were presented at Ling Lunch at University of Connecticut (2015), the 2015 Annual Meeting of the Linguistic Association of Great Britain, and the 2016 Annual Meeting of the Linguistic Society of America. Thanks to the reviewers and audience at these conferences especially Klaus Abels, Patrick David Elliott, and Andrew Weir for valuable comments. I also thank all the native speakers who have provided me with their judgements. All errors are mine.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Zheng Shen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Shen, Z. Fragment answers and movement. Nat Lang Linguist Theory 36, 309–321 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-017-9369-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-017-9369-9

Keywords

Navigation