Skip to main content

Phenomenology as Description and as Explanation: The Case of Schizophrenia

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Handbook of Phenomenology and Cognitive Science

Abstract

The phenomenological approach in both philosophy and psychiatry has often been characterized as a descriptive rather than an explanatory enterprise. One can understand this statement in various ways. The general idea, however, is that the purpose of phenomenology is to describe and define the nature and varieties of human experience rather than to give an account of the causal mechanisms or efficacious processes that bring it about.

At an early phase of his work, Edmund Husserl (1859-1938) - phenomenology’s founder - did indeed present phenomenology as a purely descriptive approach that excludes all concern with both genesis and causation (Bernet et al. 1993, p. 195). In the classic preface to his Phenomenology of Perception, Maurice Merleau-Ponty (1962, pp. vii-viii) characterizes phenomenology as “a matter of describing, not of explaining or analyzing … (as an attempt) to give a direct description of experience as it is without taking account of its psychological origin and the causal explanations which the scientist, the historian, or the sociologist may be able to provide.” Similar views are common in phenomenological psychiatry and psychopathology. The phenomenological psychiatrist, Wolfgang Blankenburg (1971/1991, p. 4, 27), e.g., explicitly denies that his account of the “basic disorder” (Grundstörung) in schizophrenia is intended to have any etiologic significance; he aims, he says, only to capture the “essence” of typically schizophrenic abnormalities (see also Buytendijk 1987, p. 130).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 259.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

     See, e.g., Simon (2000, p. 25): “The line between descriptive and explanatory laws is not a sharp one, for we may find all kinds of intermediate cases - especially for qualitative explanations.” As Simon points out, both “causal” and “explanation” are terms “gravid with implications” and highly “problematic” (p. 22). See Michotte (1963) for an experimental demonstration of the difficulty of separating perceptual observation from causal attribution.

  2. 2.

     The present chapter overlaps considerably with another, rather longer paper: Sass and Parnas (2007).

  3. 3.

     It is not easy to provide a succinct précis of Husserl’s complex views on genetic phenomenology and motivational relationships. On these difficulties, see Bernet et al. (1993, p. 196). For attempts to clarify these issues, see Steinbock (1995), Depraz (2001).

  4. 4.

     Motivation can operate through associative and other links among the contents of awareness. These would have some analogies with the kinds of links emphasized by analytic philosophers who speak of “mental causation” or the “practical syllogism” - see Section on Explanatory Relevance of the Mental or Subjective Domain: Preliminary Considerations below. Motivation (in Husserl’s sense) can, however, also operate through formal or structural aspects of the (noetic) act of consciousness itself - as, e.g., when inner time consciousness serves as a necessary condition for the unity of the flux of experiences, or when a distorted mode of self-experience is expressed in specific kinds of delusional beliefs (see Section on Expressive Relationships below) (Husserl 1989, p. 238).

  5. 5.

     I am aware that, according to many philosophers, a cause can be simultaneous with its effect (Mackie 1974, p. 161). A future, more fully adequate taxonomy will doubtless need to take this into account.

  6. 6.

     The term “affection” in the phrase “self-affection” is intended to suggest a quality of passivity and also affinity with the affects; this contrasts with mental processes or events that have a more active and purely cognitive nature. To be affected by something means to be touched, moved, or motivated by it - a process that is primordially linked to emotionality (Henry 1973; Parnas 2003).

  7. 7.

     Maximal “grip” or “hold” on the world requires a “certain balance between the inner and outer horizon.” If seen from too close, a living body, now divorced from its background, can seem an outlandish “mass of matter”; if seen from too far away, it may lose its “living value” and appear as a puppet or automaton (Merleau-Ponty 1962, p. 302).

  8. 8.

     Contrast this with the kind of awareness we normally have of our bodies: “not … knowledge in thematized form. [Rather] an inarticulate and indistinct familiarity completely devoid of positional and disclosing consciousness” (Gurwitsch 1964, p. 302, describing Merleau-Ponty’s views).

  9. 9.

     For critiques of Davidson, see (Evnine 1991; Sass 2001b, pp. 264-274).

  10. 10.

     Actually, Davidson’s position on the causal efficacy of mental contents is very difficult to pin down, as various commentators have remarked (see Sass 2001b, pp. 287-290, for discussion and various references, including Kim 1985). Wakefield and Eagle (1997) offer a clear example of a reading that interprets Davidson as ascribing real causal efficacy to “mental representations” existing “in the head” (p. 323). Sass (2001b) criticizes the coherence of Davidson’s position and questions its actual relevance for psychological explanation.

  11. 11.

     Griffiths (1997, p. 244) argues that “many problems in the philosophy of mind have been occasioned by the loss of … flexibility in our thought about mental contents” that was occasioned by adoption of the philosophical “propositional attitude” theory. As Griffiths points out, the latter approach (exemplified by Donald Davidson) derives from Aristotle’s formalized model of action explanation via the “practical syllogism.”

  12. 12.

     Jaspers (1963, p. 59): “… from the phenomenological point of view, it is only the form that interests us.”

  13. 13.

     See Sass (1998b) for an introduction to hermeneutic phenomenology, where the emphasis is on background or “horizonal” aspects of existence.

  14. 14.

     This distinction between synchronic and diachronic dimensions is a simplifying abstraction, not meant to be taken too literally. All conscious processes are, in some sense, intrinsically temporal in nature.

    There is at least a rough correspondence between my synchronic-diachronic distinction and Husserl’s distinction between static and genetic phenomenology (see Husserl 1999, pp. 144, 319).

    Philosophers have debated the question of the relationship between causation and temporal sequence, with some pointing out that a cause can sometimes be simultaneous with its effect. In this paper, however, I focus on possible causal sequences.

  15. 15.

     Obviously, I am not using “causal” here in the narrow sense of mechanical efficient causality.

  16. 16.

     The term “equiprimordial” is taken from Heidegger (1962).

  17. 17.

     In this respect, I follow Husserl rather than Heidegger. Heidegger conceived of human existence as a condition of being there (Dasein) and questioned what he saw as his mentor, Husserl’s, overly subjectivist and Cartesian conception of mind as constituting the experiential world. Although Husserl fully recognized there is no noesis (act of consciousness) without a correlative noema (object of consciousness), he nevertheless gives a special status to the noetic acts, which he describes as “animating construals” or “apprehensions” that are responsible for the transcendental constituting of the objects and field of our awareness (Husserl 1983, pp. 226, 238, 277). One may certainly debate the merits of a Heideggerian versus a Husserlian approach (Tatossian 1997, p.12). It is worth noting, however, that the Husserlian interest in constituting mental processes and the genesis of experiential worlds is more obviously congruent with the aspirations of contemporary psychology and cognitive science, which seek to identify mental processes that underlie and in this sense account for the experiential abnormalities.

  18. 18.

     See Dworkin et al (1998, pp. 390, 412) re role of the individual’s “concerns” in determining the emotional meaning and general significance of events.

  19. 19.

     Other types also fall outside this dualism of explanatory types; see below.

  20. 20.

     Merleau-Ponty (1962) uses the concept of “reciprocal expression” in a broad way - to refer to “internal links” between whole modes of experience: “Thus sexuality is not an autonomous cycle. It has internal links with the whole of active and cognitive being, these three sectors of behavior [sexuality, action, cognition] display one typical structure, and stand in a relationship to each other of reciprocal expression” (p. 157).

  21. 21.

     McClamrock (1995) describes “the characterizations of the world under which behavior is systematic with respect to it” (p. 4) as “distal causes”, and states that, in causal analysis, these may “screen off” (i.e., render less relevant) more proximal causes (p. 54). See also pp. 45-53, 178, 187 and passim for arguments from philosophy and cognitive science. For related discussion, see Searle (1983), espec. pp. 112-140.

References

  • Artaud A (1965) In: Jack H (ed) Antonin Artaud anthology. City Lights Books, San Francisco, CA

    Google Scholar 

  • Artaud A (1976) In: Sontag S (ed) Antonin Artaud: selected writings (trans: Weaver H). Farrar, Straus, & Giroux, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi R (ed) (1999) The Cambridge dictionary of philosophy, 2nd edn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernet R, Kern I, Marbach E (1993) An introduction to Husserlian phenomenology. Northwestern University Press, Evanston, IL

    Google Scholar 

  • Blankenburg W (1971) Der Verlust der Natürlichen Selbstverständlichkeit: Ein Beitrag zur Psychopathologie Symptomarmer Schizophrenien. Ferdinand Enke Verlag, Stuttgart. French translation (1991): La Perte de L’Évidence Naturelle: Une Contribution à la Psychopathologie des Schizophrénies Pauci-Symptomatiques (trans: Azorin J-M, Totoyan Y). Presses Universitaires de France, Paris (Note: Both versions are cited in text above)

    Google Scholar 

  • Bovet P, Parnas J (1993) Schizophrenic delusions: a phenomenological approach. Schizophrenia Bul 19:579-597

    Google Scholar 

  • Buytendijk FJJ (1987) The phenomenological approach to the problem of feelings and emotions. In: Kockelmans JJ (ed) Phenomenological psychology: the Dutch school. Martinus Nijhoff, Dordrecht, pp 195-207

    Google Scholar 

  • Carman T (2005) On the inescapability of phenomenology. In: David WS, Amie LT (eds) Phenomenology and the philosophy of mind. Clarendon, Oxford, pp 67-89

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane T (1995) Causation. In: Grayling AC (ed) Philosophy: a guide through the subject. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 184-194

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins R (2000) How does it work? Versus what are the leaps?: two conceptions of psychological explanation. In: Keil FD, Wilson RA (eds) Explanation and cognition. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D (1980) Essays on actions and events. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Depraz N (2001) Lucidité du corps. Kluwer, Dordrecht/Holland

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus H (2002) Intelligence without representation - Merleau-Ponty’s critique of mental representation. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 1:367-383

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus H, Wakefield J (1988) From depth psychology to breadth psychology: a phenomenological approach to psychopathology. In: Messer S, Sass L, Woolfolk R (eds) Hermeneutics and psychological theory. Rutgers University Press, New Brunswick NJ, pp 272-288

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin RH, Oster H, Clark SC, White SR (1998) Affective expression and affective experience in schizophrenia. In: Lenzenweger MF, Dworkin RH (eds) Origins and development of schizophrenia. American Psychiatric, Washington, DC, pp 385-424

    Google Scholar 

  • Evnine S (1991) Donald Davidson. Stanford University Press, Stanford, CA

    Google Scholar 

  • Geertz C (1973) The interpretation of cultures. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray JA, Feldon J, Rawlins JN, Hemsley DR, Smith AD (1991) The neuropsychology of schizophrenia. Behav Brain Sci 14:1-20

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE (1997) What emotions really are. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL

    Google Scholar 

  • Grunbaum A (1993) Validation in the clinical theory of psychoanalysis. International Universities Press, Madison, CN

    Google Scholar 

  • Gurwitsch A (1964) The field of consciousness. Duquesne University Press, Pittsburgh, PA

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger M (1962) Being and time (trans: Macquarrie J, Robinson E). Harper & Row, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Heil J, Mele A (eds) (1993) Mental causation. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hemsley DR (2005) The development of a cognitive model of schizophrenia: Placing it in context. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews 29:977-988

    Google Scholar 

  • Henry M (1973) The essence of manifestation (trans: Etzkorn G). Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague. Original in1963: L’essence de la manifestation. P.U.F., Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl E (1977) Phenomenological psychology (lectures, summer semester, 1925) (trans: Scanlon J). Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl E (1983) Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy: first book (trans: Kersten F). Kluwer, Dordrecht/Holland

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl E (1989) Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy: second book: studies in the phenomenology of constitution (trans: Rojcewicz R, Schuwer A). Kluwer, Dordrecht/Holland

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl E (1999) In: Welton D (ed) The essential Husserl. Indiana University Press, Bloomington, IN

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaspers K (1963) General psychopathology (trans: Hoenig J, Hamilton MW). University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim J (1985) Psychophysical laws. In: LePore E, McGlaughin B (eds) Actions and events: perspectives on the philosophy of Donald Davidson. Oxford University Press, Blackwell

    Google Scholar 

  • Klosterkötter J, Schultze-Lutter F, Gross G, Huber G, Steinmeyer EM (1997) Early self-experienced neuropsychological deficits and subsequent schizophrenic diseases: an 8-year average follow-up prospective study. Acta Psychiatr Scand 95:396-404

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lawson-Tancred H (1995) Ancient Greek philosophy II: Aristotle. In: Grayling AC (ed) Philosophy: a guide through the subject. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 398-439

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie JL (1974) The cement of the universe: a study of causation. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Marbach E (1993) Mental representation and consciousness. towards a phenomenological theory of representation and reference. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • McClamrock R (1995) Existential cognition: computational minds in the world. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty M (1962) The phenomenology of perception (trans: Smith C). Routledge & Kegan Paul , New York (reissued 2002). Orig: (1945). Phénomenologie de la Perception. Gallimard, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty M (1968) The visible and the invisible (trans: Lingis A). Northwestern University Press, Evanston IL

    Google Scholar 

  • Michotte A (1963) The perception of causality. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Minkowski E (1997) Au-Delà du rationalisme morbide. Harmattan, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Moran D (2000) Introduction to phenomenology. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Parnas J (2000) The self and intentionality in the pre-psychotic stages of schizophrenia. In: Zahavi D (ed) Exploring the self: philosophical and psychopathological perspectives on self-experience. John Benjamins, Amsterdam, pp 115-147

    Google Scholar 

  • Parnas J (2003) Self-disorders in schizophrenia: a clinical perspective. In: Kircher T, David A (eds) The self and schizophrenia: a neuropsychological perspective. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Parnas J, Zahavi D (2002) The role of phenomenology in psychiatric classification and diagnosis. In: Maj M, Gaebel W, Lopez-Ibor JJ, Sartorius N (eds) Psychiatric diagnosis and classification (World Psychiatric Association Series). Wiley, New York, pp 137-162

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips WA, Silverstein SM (2003) Convergence of biological and psychological perspectives on cognitive coordination in schizophrenia. Behav Brain Sci 26:65-137

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi M (1964) Personal knowledge. Harper Torchbooks, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi M (1967) The tacit dimension. Anchor Books, Garden City, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur P (1992) Oneself as another (trans: Blamey K). University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass L (1992a) Madness and modernism: insanity in the light of modern art, literature, and thought. Basic Books, New York (Harvard Paperback 1994)

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass L (1992b) Heidegger, schizophrenia, and the ontological difference. Philos Psychol 5:109-132

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sass L (1994) The paradoxes of delusion: Wittgenstein, Schreber, and the schizophrenic mind. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass L (1998a) Schizophrenia, self-consciousness, and the modern mind. J Conscious Stud 5:543-565

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass L (1998b) Ambiguity is of the essence: the relevance of hermeneutics for psychoanalysis. In: Marcus P, Rosenberg A (eds) Psychoanalytic versions of the human condition and clinical practice. New York University Press, New York, pp 257-305

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass L (2001a) Self and world in schizophrenia: three classic approaches in phenomenological psychiatry 8:251-270

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass L (2001b) Wittgenstein, Freud, and the nature of psychoanalytic explanation. In: Allen R, Turvey M (eds) Wittgenstein, theory, and the arts. Routledge, London, pp 253-295

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass L (2003a) Negative symptoms, schizophrenia, and the self. International Journal of Psychology and Psychological Therapy 3:153-180

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass L (2003b) Schizophrenia and the self: hyperreflexivity and diminished self-affection. In: Kircher T, David A (eds) The self in schizophrenia: neuropsychological perspectives. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 242-271

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass L, Parnas J (2003) Schizophrenia, consciousness, and the self. Schizophr Bull 29:427-444

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass L, Parnas J (2007) Explaining schizophrenia: the relevance of phenomenology. In: Chung MC, Fulford KWM, Graham G (eds) Reconceiving schizophrenia. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 63-95

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (1983) Intentionality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (2000) Discovering explanations. In: Keil FC, Wilson RA (eds) Explanation and cognition. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 21-60

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokolowski R (2000) Introduction to phenomenology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinbock AJ (1995) Home and beyond. Northwestern University Press, Evanston, IL

    Google Scholar 

  • Störring G (1987) Perplexity. In: Cutting J, Shepherd M (eds) The clinical roots of the schizophrenia concept. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 79-82 (orig. published 1939)

    Google Scholar 

  • Tatossian A (1997) La Phénomenologie des Psychoses. L’Art du Comprendre, Paris (Juillet 1997, Numéro double, hors série)

    Google Scholar 

  • Tausk V (1933) On the origin of the “influencing machine” in schizophrenia. Psychoanal Q 2:529-530 (orig. published 1919)

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor C (1993) Engaged agency and background in Heidegger. In: Guignon C (ed) The Cambridge companion to Heidegger. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 317-336

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Wright GH (1971) Explanation and understanding. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield J, Eagle M (1997) Psychoanalysis and Wittgenstein: a reply to Richard Allen. Psychoanal Contemp Though 20:323-351

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson RA, Keil FC (2000) The shadows and shallows of explanation. In: Keil FC, Wilson RA (eds) Explanation and cognition. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 87-114

    Google Scholar 

  • Wrathall MA (2005) Motives, reasons, and causes. In: Carman T, Hansen MBN (eds) The Cambridge companion to Merleau-Ponty. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 111-128

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (1999) Self-awareness and alterity: a phenomenological investigation. Northwestern University Press, Evanston, IL

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Sass, L.A. (2010). Phenomenology as Description and as Explanation: The Case of Schizophrenia. In: Schmicking, D., Gallagher, S. (eds) Handbook of Phenomenology and Cognitive Science. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-2646-0_31

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics