Skip to main content

Pattern Two, Phase Two: State Sovereignty Preserved I

A New Interpretation Takes Shape in the Early 1980s

  • Chapter
The War Over Perpetual Peace
  • 66 Accesses

Abstract

The final historical period within which Kant’s Perpetual Peace has been utilized, takes us, and pattern formation, up to the present day. The last interpretation within this period given consideration comes from Harold Kleinschmidt’s The Nemesis of Power, published in 2000. The first within this period is by Michael Doyle, a leading “liberal peace” theorist, in a well-known 1983 article entitled “Kant, Liberal Legacies and Foreign Affairs.” Like F.H. Hinsley’s 1963 interpretation, Doyle provides us with a pivotal textual analysis of Perpetual Peace, the influence of which is seen throughout this final historical phase. The articles originality, exclusive focus on Perpetual Peace, and the idea and empirical proof of an ever-expanding zone of peace among liberal, sovereign states that it sets forth, make it an interpretation crucial to the development of themes in this chapter and in chapters 6, 7, and 9 to follow.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Dean Babst, “A Force for Peace,” Industrial Research (April 1972), pp. 55–58. Originally published as “Elective Governments—A Force for Peace,” The Wisconsin Sociologist, 3, No. 1 (1964), pp. 9–14. Other early studies include: R.J. Rummell, Understanding Conflict and War, Volumes 1–5 (Los Angeles: Sage, 1975–1981);

    Google Scholar 

  2. Bruce Russett and Harvey Starr, World Politics: The Menu for Choice (New York: W.H. Freeman, 1981);

    Google Scholar 

  3. Peter Wallensteen, Structure and War: On IR 1820–1968 (Stockholm: Raben and Sjogren, 1973).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Michael Doyle, “Kant, Liberal Legacies and Foreign Affairs, Parts 1 and 2,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 12, Nos. 3 and 4 (1983), pp. 205–35, 323–53. Howard Williams and Ken Booth note that this article, more than any other, “raised the profile of Kant’s work [on international relations].”

    Google Scholar 

  5. Howard Williams and Ken Booth, “Kant: Theorist Beyond Limits,” in Ian Clark and Iver B. Neumann, eds., Classical Theories of International Relations (Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire, and London: MacMillan Press, 1996), pp. 72–73.

    Google Scholar 

  6. To demonstrate the overflow of liberal peace scholarship over the recent past, included below is a pared down list of post-Doyle articles from the References section of Wade L. Huntley’s, “Kant’s Third Image: Systemic Sources of the Liberal Peace,” International Studies Quarterly, 40 (1996), pp. 45–76;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. B. Bueno de Mesquita, R. Siverson, and G. Woller, “War and the Fate of Regimes: A Comparative Analysis,” American Political Science Review, 86 (1992), pp. 638–46;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. S. Chan, “Mirror, Mirror on the Wall … Are the Freer Countries More Pacific?” Journal of Conflict Resolution, 28 (1984), pp. 617–48;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. N. Gleditsch, “Democracy and Peace,” Journal of Peace Research, 29 (1992), pp. 369–76;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. J.D. Hagan, “Domestic Political Systems and War Proneness,” Mershon International Studies Review, 38 (1994), pp. 183–207;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. D. Lake, “Powerful Pacifists: Democratic States and War,” American Political Science Review, 86 (1992), pp. 24–37;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. C. Layne, “Kant or Cant: The Myth of the Democratic Peace,” International Security, 19 (1994), pp. 5–49;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. J. Levy, “Domestic Politics and War,” Journal of Interdisciplinary History, 18 (1988), pp. 653–73;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Bruce Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace, Principles for a Post-Cold War Order (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993);

    Google Scholar 

  15. D. Spiro, “The Insignificance of the Liberal Peace,” International Security, 19 (1994), pp. 50–86;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. H. Starr, “Why Don’t Democracies Fight One Another?: Evaluating the Theory-Findings Feedback Loop,” Jerusalem Journal of International Relations, 14 (1992), pp. 41–59. With the proliferation of these studies over the past several years, several scholars have reached the conclusion that the existence of a liberal peace is “as close as anything we have to an empirical law in international relations.” Gleditsch, “Democracy and Peace,” p. 372 and Levy, “Domestic Politics and War,” pp. 661–62 in Huntley, “Kant’s Third Image,” p. 46.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Immanuel Kant, Perpetual Peace in Kant’s Political Writings, ed. Hans Reiss, trans. H.B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), p. 100.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Chris Brown, International Relations Theory (London: MacMillan Press, 1997), p. 36.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Doyle, “Kant, Liberal Legacies and Foreign Affairs, Part 1,” p. 229. As noted in note 1 from the Introduction, for purposes of uniformity throughout the book, any text quoted from Kant’s Perpetual Peace, excepting only that commentary by authors who may quote directly from other translations in their interpretation of the treatise, derives from the following translation: Immanuel Kant, Perpetual Peace in Kant’s Political Writings, ed. Reiss, trans. Nisbet. Here, as opposed to the Nisbet translation, Doyle chooses to use a translation of Perpetual Peace from Immanuel Kant, Perpetual Peace in The Enlightenment, ed. Peter Gay (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1974), pp. 790–92 Considering how central this passage is to Pattern Two, Phase Two interpretation, I believe it is helpful to my argument to demonstrate how similar the two translations are. Compare the above translation to the following translation by Nisbet of exactly the same passage: If, as is inevitably the case under this constitution, the consent of the citizens is required to decide whether or not war is to be declared, it is very natural that they will have great hesitation in embarking on so dangerous an enterprise. For this would mean calling down on themselves all the miseries of war, such as doing the fighting themselves, supplying the costs of the war from their own resources, painfully making good the ensuing devastation, and, as the crowning evil, having to takes upon themselves a burden of debt which will embitter peace itself and which can never be paid off on account of the constant threat of new wars. But under a constitution where the subject is not a citizen, and which is therefore not republican, it is the simplest thing in the world to go to war. For the head of state is not a fellow citizen, but the owner of the state, and a war will not force him to make the slightest sacrifice so far as his banquets, hunts, pleasure palaces and court festivals are concerned. He can thus decide on war, without any significant reason, as a kind of amusement, and unconcernedly leave it to the diplomatic corps (who are always ready for such purposes) to justify the war for the sake of propriety. (Kant, Perpetual Peace, ed. Reiss, trans. Nisbet, p. 100. A detailed comparison of both reveals little difference between the two)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Anthony Smith, “Kant’s Political Philosophy: Rechsstaat or Council Democracy?” Review of Politics, 47 (April 1985), p. 258.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Peter Calvocoresi, A Time for Peace: Pacifism, Internationalism and Protest Forces in the Reduction of War (London, Melbourne, Auckland, and Johannesburg: Hutchinson, 1987), p. 48.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Leslie A. Mulholland, “Kant on War and International Justice,” Kant-Studien, 78 (1987), p. 33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Thomas L. Carson, “Perpetual Peace: What Kant Should Have Said,” Social Theory and Practice, 14, No. 2 (Summer 1988), p. 184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Ian Clark, The Hierarchy of States: Reform and Resistance in the International Order (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), p. 55.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  25. Sissela Bok, A Strategy for Peace: Human Values and the Threat of War (New York: Pantheon Books, 1989), p. 32.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Copyright information

© 2004 Eric S. Easley

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Easley, E.S. (2004). Pattern Two, Phase Two: State Sovereignty Preserved I. In: The War Over Perpetual Peace. The Palgrave Macmillan History of International Thought Series. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781403978714_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics