Skip to main content
  • 81 Accesses

Abstract

The graphic reports in the last chapter of a Reality breaking in upon some people’s consciousness inevitably underscore the truth that others never have experiences of this kind. Many committed theists, perhaps, are unaware of any single occasion upon which “knowledge of God” was given to them, but the strength with which they hold their convictions is not less than those for whom some experience is epiphanic. The former are people who have always been theists, and know of no time in their lives when they were unsure of this belief. Intuitive knowledge is seemingly present in both experiences—the mundane and the dramatic—and the value of the dramatic experiences lies in their capacity not only to attract our attention, but also to allow the mundane states of mind to be more clearly seen for what they possibly are. Spiritual communities often include people whose dramatic experiences are not shared by others, and each group is suspicious of the other. In his groundbreaking work on religious experience, William James speaks of the “once-born” and the “twice-born” as a way of caricaturing the two.1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. William James (1960) The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human Nature (London: Collins), lec. 6 & 7.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Sir David Ross (1930) The Right and the Good (Oxford: Clarendon Press), Chapter 2.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Charles Taylor (2007) A Secular Age (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press), pp. 191–92.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Derek Parfit (1984) Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Oxford University Press), Appendix I.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Immanuel Kant (1993) Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, 3rd edn [1785] (trans. James W. Ellington) (Indianapolis: Hackett). pref.

    Google Scholar 

  6. David Hume (1967) A Treatise of Human Nature, L. A. Selby-Bigg (ed.) (Oxford: Clarendon Press), bk. 3, pt. 1, sec. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  7. The existence of a fact–value gap is a different matter than the inability to deduce an evaluative statement from a factual one, according to Julian Dodd, and Suzanne Stern-Gilley (1995) “The Is/Ought Gap, the Fact/Value Distinction and the Naturalistic Fallacy,” Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review, 34, 727–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. John Mackie (1977) Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (London: Penguin Books), p. 15.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Sir A. J. Ayer (1946) Language, Truth, and Logic, 2nd edn (London: Gollancz), is the best-known English exposition of positivism, which construes value judgments as having only emotive and/or prescriptive meaning.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Terence Cuneo (2003) “Reidian Moral Perception,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 33, 229–58.

    Google Scholar 

  11. See the defense of the cognitivity of theological statements in Theodore M. Drange (2005) “Is ‘God Exists’ Cognitive?” Philo: A Journal of Philosophy, 8, 137–50. This contradicts the famous positivist position on the topic, as in A. J. Ayer, Language, Truth, and Logic.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Carl Wellman (1968) “Emotivism and Ethical Objectivity,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 5, 90–99, concurs, published a decade later.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Positivism is evidently being reexamined, cf. Michael Friedman (1999) Reconsidering Logical Positivism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  14. Del Kiernan-Lewis (2007) “Naturalism and the Problem of Evil,” Philo: A Journal of Philosophy, 10, 125–35. A curious dilemma arises: either no evaluative facts exist, in which case the standard theistic explanations of creation fail, or such facts exist, in which case the problem of evil arises. I take it that theists should embrace such facts, and the problem of evil.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Gilbert Harman (1977) The Nature of Morality: An Introduction to Ethics (New York: Oxford University Press), Chapter 1.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Cf. Don Dedrick (1995) “Objectivism and the Evolutionary Value of Colour Vision,” Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review, 34, 35–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. See Vladimir Ilich (1966) The Emancipation of Women; From the Writings of V. I. Lenin (New York: International Publishers) for his articulation of the social and political equality of women as early as 1920.

    Google Scholar 

  18. David Hume (1966) An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, 2nd edn, reprint of 1777 edn (LaSalle, IL: Open Court), sec. 9, pt. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Rene Descartes (1960) Meditations on First Philosophy in Which are Demonstrated the Existence of God and the Distinction Between the Human Soul and Body (trans. Laurence J. LaFleur) (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill), meditation 2.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See Jasper Reid (2003) “Henry More on Material and Spiritual Extension,” Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review, 42, 531–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Carl Jung (1996) The Psychology of Kundalini Yoga: Notes of the Seminar Given in 1932, Sonu Shamdasani (ed.) (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press), p. 21.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Daniel Dennett (1992) “The Self as a Center of Narrative Gravity,” in Frank S. Kessel, Pamela Cole, and Dale L. Johnson (eds.) Self and Consciousness: Multiple Perspectives (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum), pp. 103–15.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Aristotle, Politics, in Richard McKeon (ed.) The Basic Works of Aristotle (New York: Random House, 1941), p. 1341a.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Gazzaniga has published widely on his research, including Michael S. Gazzaniga (1988) Mind Matters: How Mind and Brain Interact to Create our Conscious Lives (Boston: Houghton Mifflin).

    Google Scholar 

  25. W. M. Kelley, C. N. Macrae, C. L. Wyland, S. Caglar, S. Inati, and T. F. Heathertont (2002) “Finding the Self? An Event-Related fMRI Study,” Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 14, 785–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Phillip H. Wiebe (1997) Visions of Jesus: Direct Encounters from the New Testament to Today (New York: Oxford University Press), p. 85.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Plato, Republic in Francis M. Cornford (1945) (ed. and trans.) The Republic of Plato (London: Oxford University Press), p. 439.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Merton, Thomas (2003) The Inner Experience: Notes on Contemplation, William H. Shannon (ed.) (New York: HarperCollins Publishers), p. 10; ital. orig.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Plato, Phaedo, in B. Jowett (trans.) The Dialogues of Plato, 2 vols (New York: Random House, 1937), 78c.

    Google Scholar 

  30. I have discussed this in Wiebe, Visions of Jesus, pp. 95–98; cf. Carol Zaleski (1996) The Life of the World to Come: Near-Death Experience and Christian Hope (New York: Oxford University Press), pp. 58–64.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Aristotle, De Anima, in Richard McKeon (ed.) The Basic Works of Aristotle (New York: Random House, 1941), bk. 2, chap. 2ff.

    Google Scholar 

  32. See Karol Wojtyla (1979) The Acting Person: A Contribution to Phenomenological Anthropology (trans. Analecta Husserliana, and Andrezej Potocki) (Berlin: Springer), which reflects influences of Thomism, existentialism, and phenomenology. I owe this insight to Kian O’Higgins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  33. See Robert L. Vance (2006) “Moral Being in Contemporary Views of the Self,” Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review, 45, 713–29, for a discussion of recent analyses of the self.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Carl Jung (1972) Synchronicity: An Acausal Connecting Principle (trans. R. F. C. Hull) (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul). Perhaps a causal link does exist, but not one explicable only in physical terms.

    Google Scholar 

  35. These were explored a half-century ago in Carl G. Hempel (1943) “A Purely Syntactical Definition of Confirmation,” The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 8, 122–43,

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. and Carl Hempel (1965) “Studies in the Logic of Confirmation,” in Carl Hempel (ed.) Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science (New York: The Free Press), pp. 3–46.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Copyright information

© 2015 Phillip H. Wiebe

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Wiebe, P.H. (2015). Values. In: Intuitive Knowing as Spiritual Experience. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137543585_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics