Skip to main content

Abstract

The previous chapter has labored toward reconsidering the common morality by focusing on the posture of openness that cultivates a responsibility to, with, and for our fellows. Jacques Ellul and George Grant helped to assess the systems pertaining to the common morality, judging them to have taken on the form and function of a moral technique aimed at rendering efficient the processes of ethical decision-making in biomedical science and practice. Indeed, the previous chapter helped to diagnose the moral milieu in which the common morality has taken shape and effect as being committed to homogeneous moral reasoning, which is to be shared among all persons, in all places–rather, shared among those assessed as being capable of reasoning in such a manner. Moreover, Karl Barth helped to reimagine the practice of bioethics, offering an initial posture that destabilizes technique while introducing the ethical encounter of the “I” and “Thou” as an embodied practice of solidarity, such that the history of correlating human beings is made known as each one listens, hears, and exchanges speech. Gabriel Marcel added to the practice of openness by suggesting that such an encounter requires that we not only present ourselves available before but also faithful to the other. Indeed, availability and fidelity, for Marcel, are critical for the development of authentic relationships.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Gerald Dworkin, The Theory and Practice of Autonomy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), p. 6.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  2. For a brief survey of competing views, see James Stacey Taylor, Practical Autonomy and Bioethics (New York: Routledge, 2009), pp. 19–20.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Onora O’Neill, Autonomy and Trust in Bioethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), p. 23.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Daniel Callahan, “Can the Moral Commons Survive Autonomy?,” Hastings Center Report 26, no. 6 (1996): 41–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Daniel Callahan, “Autonomy: A Moral Good Not a Moral Obsession,” Hastings Center Report 14, no. 5 (1984): 40–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Paul Root Wolpe, “The Triumph of Autonomy in American Bioethics,” in Bioethics and Society: Constructing the Ethical Enterprise, ed. Raymond DeVries and Janardan Subedi (Upper Saddle River: Prentice-Hall, 1998), p. 43.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Tom L. Beauchamp and James F. Childress, Principles of Biomedical Ethics (New York: Oxford University Press, 6th ed., 2009), p. 99.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Bernard Gert, The Moral Rules (New York: Harper & Row, 1970), p. 20.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), p. 39.

    Google Scholar 

  10. John Stuart Mill, On Liberty (London: The Floating Press, 2009), p. 23.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Jacques Ellul, The Technological Society, trans. John Wilkinson (New York: Vintage Books, 1964), p. 133.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Jacques Ellul, On Freedom, Love, and Power, trans. William H. Vanderburg (Toronto: Toronto University Press, 2010), p. 70.

    Google Scholar 

  13. As Brian Brock comments, George Grant, too, reminds us that the “will [has become] the central feature of modern anthropology” (Brock, Christian Ethics, p. 73). Brock continues, “To will announces that we are serious, choosing to actualize ourselves and our view of the world against the one who simply thinks, or impo-tently desires without acting... [Willing intends] to bring into being a good future, by conquering an indifferent nature and making it good for us” (p. 74). For Grant’s original discussions regarding willing the good, see George Grant, “Time as History,” and “English Speaking Justice,” in Collected Works of George Grant, vol. 4, ed. Arthur Davis and Henry Roper (Toronto: Toronto University Press, 2009), pp. 3–78

    Google Scholar 

  14. Gabriel Marcel, Man Against Mass Society, trans. G. S. Fraser (South Bend: St. Augustine’s Press, 2008), p. 17

    Google Scholar 

  15. Nicholas Berdyaev, The Destiny of Man, trans. Natalie Duddington (San Rafael: Semantron Press, 2009), p. 10.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Pam McGrath, “Autonomy, Discourse, and Power: A Postmodern Reflection on Principlism and Bioethics,” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 23, no. 5 (1998): 523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Tom L. Beauchamp and James F. Childress, Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 6th ed. (New York: Oxford University Press, 2009), p. 25.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Tom L. Beauchamp and James F. Childress, Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 7th ed. (New York: Oxford University Press, 2013), p. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Berdyaev, Destiny of Man, p. 20; This “herd” element is a synonym for the tyranny of the technological society that conforms moral participants under the rule of moral technique. However, Friedrich Nietzsche, for example, would argue herd morality is a morality of selflessness—it is quite likely, Nietzsche would accuse the posture of openness as being such a morality. Thus, it will be important to clarify how openness and human agency are correlated in this chapter, so as to not fall subject to an equal charge of herd morality. Nevertheless, even for Nietzsche, the claim “herd” morality is relevant here: There remains a dependence upon external authority, pronouncement held within the strata and structure of the common morality, which relieves [if not actively prevents] each one of the need to make one’s own judgments, particularly in opposition to the abstract whole. To read further regarding Nietzsche’s herd mentality, see Friedrich Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future, trans. Helen Zimmern, Dover Thrift ed. (Mineola: Dover Publications, 1997).

    Google Scholar 

  20. Bernard Gert, Charles M. Culver, and K. Danner Clouser, Bioethics: A Return to Fundamentals (New York: Oxford University Press, 1997), p. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  21. CD, p. 593f; Daniel Migliore adds further comment, saying, “[Barth] emphasizes that the appropriate human response to God’s grace (charis) is action born not of duty or fear but of free thanksgiving (eu-charistia )” (Daniele L. Migliore, “Commanding Grace: Karl Barth’s Theological Ethics,” in Commanding Grace: Studies in Karl Barth’s Ethics, ed. Daniele L. Migliore [Grand Rapids: Wm. B. Eerdmans, 2010], p. 12).

    Google Scholar 

  22. “This is not to make moral action into a mere reflex; but it is to deny that moral authenticity has its ultimate ground in transcendent moral consciousness, in ‘the self-willed desire of man to know good and evil’” (John Webster, Barth’s Ethics of Reconciliation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), p. 56

    Google Scholar 

  23. Gerald McKenny, The Analogy of Grace: Karl Barth’s Moral Theology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), p. 274.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  24. Paul D. Matheny, Dogmatics and Ethics: The Theological Realism and Ethics of Karl Barth’s Church Dogmatics (Frankfurt am Main: Verlag Peter Lang, 1990), p. 63.

    Google Scholar 

  25. John Webster, Barth’s Moral Theology: Human Action in Barth’s Thought (London: T. & T. Clark, 2004), p. 109.

    Google Scholar 

  26. John Webster, “God and Conscience,” in The Doctrine of God and Theological Ethics, ed. Michael Banner and Alan Torrance (London: T. & T. Clark, 2006), p. 152.

    Google Scholar 

  27. William Stringfellow, Conscience and Obedience: The Politics of Romans 13 and Revelation 13 in Light of the Second Coming (Eugene: Wipf & Stock, 2004), p. 102.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Archibald James Spencer, Clearing a Space for Human Action: Ethical Ontology in the Theology of Karl Barth (New York: Peter Lang, 2003), p. 213.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Referring to a conscience that endures beyond context, and persons imposing its command upon others, C. S. Lewis writes, “Of all tyrannies, a tyranny sincerely exercised for the good of its victims may be the most oppressive. It would be better to live under robber barons than under omnipotent moral busybodies. The robber baron’s cruelty may sometimes sleep, his cupidity may at some points be satiated; but those who torment us for our own good will torment us without end for they do so with the approval of their own conscience” (C. S. Lewis, “The Humanitarian Theory of Punishment,” in God in the Dock, ed. Walter Hooper [Grand Rapids: Wm. B. Eerdmans, 1970], 292).

    Google Scholar 

  30. See the following critiques offered by Gustafson and Hauerwas here: James M. Gustafson, Can Ethics Be Christian? (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1975), p. 160

    Google Scholar 

  31. James M. Gustafson, Ethics from a Theocentric Perspective, Ethics and Theology, vol. 2 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), pp. 30–32

    Google Scholar 

  32. Stanley Hauerwas, Character and the Christian Life: A Study in Theological Ethics (San Antonio: Trinity University Press, 1975), pp. 142

    Google Scholar 

  33. Stanley Hauerwas, “On Honour: By Way of a Comparison of Barth and Trollope,” in Reckoning with Barth, ed. Nigel Biggar (Oxford: Mowbray, 1988), pp. 145–69.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Reinhold Niebuhr, The Nature and Destiny of Man, vol. 2: Human Destiny (Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press, 1996), p. 309

    Google Scholar 

  35. Reinhold Niebuhr, The Nature and Destiny of Man, vol. 1: Human Nature (Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press, 1996)

    Google Scholar 

  36. William Werpehowski, “Command and History in the Ethics of Karl Barth,” The Journal of Religious Ethics 9, no. 1 (2001): 301.

    Google Scholar 

  37. David Clough, Ethics in Crisis: Interpreting Barth’s Ethics (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2005), p. 12.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Copyright information

© 2015 Ashley John Moyse

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Moyse, A.J. (2015). The Isolated Will and the Freedom for Agency. In: Reading Karl Barth, Interrupting Moral Technique, Transforming Biomedical Ethics. Palgrave Macmillan’s Content and Context in Theological Ethics. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137534590_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics