Skip to main content
  • 177 Accesses

Abstract

In Chapter 1, it was suggested that the melancholy science of natural history can be understood as a philosophy of waiting-expression. The retrospective projection of Adorno’s reflections on ‘waiting in vain’ back onto the earlier work (including the 1932 lecture) is philologically justified by the reappearance of the idea of natural history in the later work itself. Indeed, the English-language translator of ‘The Idea of Natural History’ observes that Negative Dialectics follows ‘precisely the same plan’ as the lecture — ‘a critique of Heidegger is followed by the presentation of the central concepts of the form of the critique’. This parallel is nevertheless limited by the fact that the last ‘model’ of Negative Dialectics was motivated by the event of a genocide surely not expected back in July of 1932. Adorno’s ‘Meditations on Metaphysics’ — ‘after Auschwitz’ — immediately follow the two sub-sections on natural history.1 The last part of Negative Dialectics is in this sense not prefigured in the lecture, but rather can be said to begin where the lecture left off.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Robert Hullot-Kentor, ‘Introduction to Adorno’s “Idea of Natural History”’, in Theodor W. Adorno, ‘The Idea of Natural history’, trans. by Robert Hullot-Kentor, Telos, 1984, p. 103.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Theodor W. Adorno, History and Freedom, trans. by Rodney Livingstone (Cambridge: Polity, 2006), p. 124. Hullot-Kentor is thus wrong to suggest, on the basis that it was published posthumously, that Adorno had disowned the lecture.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Theodor W. Adorno, Negativ Dialektik (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1966), p. 353.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Theodor W. Adorno, Metaphysics: Concept and Problems, trans. by Rolf Tiedemann (Polity Press, 2001), pp. 101, 130.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Cf. Anson Rabinovich, ‘Why Were the Jews Sacrificed? The Place of Anti-Semitism in Dialectic of Enlightenment’, New German Critique, 81 (2000), pp. 49–64.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe, Heidegger, Art and Politics: The Fiction of the Political, trans. by Chris Turner (Oxford: Blackwell, 1990), p. 43.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), p. 546.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. by Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), pp. 43–4.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Theodor W. Adorno, Minima Moralia: Reflections on a Damaged Life, trans. by Edmund Jephcott (London & New York: Verso Books, 1978), p. 175.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Jacob Taubes found Adorno’s ‘Finale’ to Minima Moralia ‘wonderful, but finally empty’. This forms the basis for Giorgio Agamben’s claim, cited in Chapter 1, that ‘negative dialectics is an absolutely non-messianic form of thought.’ Jacob Taubes, The Political Theology of Paul, trans. by Dana Hollander (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2004), p. 74.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Walter Benjamin, ‘On the Concept of History’, in Selected Writings, Volume 4, trans. by Harry Zohn, Howard Eiland, and Michael W. Jennings (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), p. 389.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Martin Heidegger, The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics: World, Finitude, Solitude, trans. by William McNeill and Nicholas Walker (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2001), p. 74.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. by John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson (Oxford: Blackwell, 2000), p. 228. Translation amended.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Cited in, Rüdiger Safranski, Martin Heidegger: Between Good and Evil, trans. by Ewald Oders (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998), p. 190.

    Google Scholar 

  15. De Beistegui flags-up the central ‘tension’ of the lecture course, between a concept of existence, whose essence is ‘pure time’, and one whose essence is already ‘subordinated to a task which is historical in nature’. For, ‘insofar as Being and Time has already identified the “fundamental meaning” of Dasein as temporality … why must we begin to search for the fundamental meaning of our contemporary Dasein?’. De Beistegui acknowledges that ‘the solution to this tension … will be found only when Heidegger will reformulate the project of the question concerning the sense of being and transform it into the question concerning the history of being.’ The demonstration of this move is ultimately confused, however. As with Löwith’s critique of Heidegger, de Beistegui tends to side with the individual and apolitical Dasein of Being and Time, against any collective or political Dasein whatever — since such a move must be ‘at once too ambitious and naive, too theological and messianic’. In place of messianism, the transition to the history of Being is instead secured for de Beistegui by way of ‘the great works and lecture-courses of the 1930s’ (including, it should be noted, the ‘messianic’ interpretations of Hölderlin). These works seek to reawaken the ‘wonder’ of the Greek Dasein. But such ‘wonder’ already privileges a particular history in a manner that does not account for this privilege with any philosophy of history. Miguel De Beistegui, ‘Boredom: Between Existence and History’, in Thinking With Heidegger (Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 2003), pp. 61–82.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Heidegger’s 1931 lectures on the Phenomenology are actually directed against interpretations of ‘absolute knowing’ as a totality of knowledge, in favour of ‘ab-solving’. Heidegger relinquishes Hegelian mediation in a manner that will increasingly become a problem for him. Cf. Martin Heidegger, Hegel’s ‘Phenomenology of Spirit’, trans. by Parvis Emad and Kenneth Maly (Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1994).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Martin Heidegger, ‘The Theory of the Categories and Meaning in Duns Scotus’, in Supplements, trans. by Roderick M. Stewart and van Buren (New York: State University of New York Press, 2002), p. 68.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Theodor W. Adorno, The Jargon of Authenticity, trans. by Knut Tarnowski (London: Routledge, 2002), pp. 102–3.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Theodor W. Adorno, ‘Progress’, in Critical Models: Interventions and Catchwords, trans. by Henry W. Pickford (New York: Columbia University Press, 1998), p. 151.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Walter Benjamin, The Arcades Project, trans. by Howard Eiland and Kevin McLaughlin (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2002), p. 107.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Theodor W. Adorno, ‘Free Time’, in Critical Models: Interventions and Catchwords, trans. by Henry W. Pickford (New York: Columbia University Press, 1998), p. 171.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Martin Heidegger, ‘Letter on Humanism’, in Basic Writings, ed. by David Farrell Krell, trans. by Frank A. Capuzzi and J. Glenn Gray (London: Routledge, 1993), p. 231.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Theodor W. Adorno, ‘Resignation’, in Critical Models: Interventions and Catchwords, trans. by Henry W. Pickford (New York: Columbia University Press, 1998), p. 293.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Martin Heidegger, The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essay, trans. by William Lovitt (New York & London: Harper and Row, 1977), p. 35.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Martin Heidegger, ‘Only a God Can Save Us’, in Philosophical and Political Writings, ed. by Manfred Stassen, trans. by Maria P. Alter and John D. Caputo (New York and London: Continuum, 2003), p. 42. Translation amended.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2015 Wesley Phillips

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Phillips, W. (2015). The Expression of Waiting in Vain. In: Metaphysics and Music in Adorno and Heidegger. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137487254_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics