Skip to main content

The Dialectical Image of Music

  • Chapter
  • 191 Accesses

Abstract

Adorno’s essay of 1938, ‘On the Fetish-Character in Music and the Regression of Listening’, has been received in the Anglophone context (since its appearance in English in 1991) by discourses of both cultural studies and new musicology.1 The essay can, however, be read as an eminently philosophical reflection upon the temporal experience of modernity. In this chapter, ‘On the Fetish-Character’ will serve to introduce a hitherto neglected philosophy of time in Adorno’s thought — one that can further elucidate the meaning of ‘waiting in vain’, as ‘music alone’ can express. It will be argued that Adorno’s evaluations of both ‘modern music’ and ‘commodity music’ can be understood according to music’s relation to time and to the image. And it is in this latter respect that Adorno’s dialectical understanding of music can be read in terms of Benjamin’s ‘dialectical image’, a concept largely formulated in his Arcades Project. As we have seen, Adorno is more critical of the later than then earlier Benjamin, even though Adorno appears to have appropriated several of the later concepts. Without claiming a direct appropriation of the dialectical image, a structural affinity will nevertheless be proposed between the dialectical image and Adorno’s philosophy of music — or rather, of musical experience. Moreover, it will be shown how Adorno came to appreciate the complex relationships between music, image and space through the ‘new music’ that he himself experienced in Darmstadt during the 1950s and 60s. Though largely unacknowledged by Adorno, the music of Luigi Nono can be shown to illustrate an expression of waiting in vain.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Karl Marx, Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, trans. by Ben Fowkes (London: Penguin, 1976), i, p. 165.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Adorno states, not entirely accurately, that Marx ‘defines the fetish-character of the commodity as the veneration of the thing made by oneself which, as exchange-value, simultaneously alienates itself from producer to consumer.’ Theodor W. Adorno, ‘On the Fetish Character in Music and the Regression of Listening’, in Essays on Music, ed. by Richard Leppert, trans. by Susan H. Gillespie (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2002), pp. 295–6.

    Google Scholar 

  3. The ‘veneration’ that Adorno attributes to Marx seems to come closer to Freud’s contention that the fetishist ‘reveres his fetish’. Sigmund Freud, ‘Fetishism’, in The Future of an Illusion, Civilization and its Discontents and Other Works, trans. by James Strachey (London: Hogarth Press, 1964), p. 157.

    Google Scholar 

  4. G. W. F. Hegel, Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. by A. V. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), p. 55.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Theodor W. Adorno, Hegel: Three Studies, trans. by Shierry Weber Nicholsen, New edition (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1994), p. 53.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Theodor Adorno to Walter Benjamin, November 10th, 1938, in Aesthetics and Politics: The Key Texts of the Classic Debate Within German Marxism, ed. by Ronald Taylor (London: New Left Books, 1977), p. 129.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Walter Benjamin, ‘On Some Motifs in Baudelaire’, in Selected Writings, Volume 4, ed. by Howard Eiland and Michael W. Jennings, trans. by Harry Zohn (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), p. 343.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Walter Benjamin, ‘The Storyteller: Observations on the Works of Nikolai Leskov’, in Selected Writings, Volume 3, trans. by Harry Zohn (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996), p. 143.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Walter Benjamin, ‘On the Concept of History’, in Selected Writings, Volume 4, trans. by Harry Zohn, Howard Eiland, and Michael W. Jennings (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), p. 392.

    Google Scholar 

  10. ‘Perhaps the strict and pure concept of art is applicable only to music, while great poetry or great painting — precisely the greatest — necessarily brings with it an element of subject-matter transcending aesthtic confines, undissolved in the autonomy of form’. Theodor W. Adorno, Minima Moralia: Reflections on a Damaged Life, trans. by Edmund Jephcott (London & New York: Verso Books, 1978), p. 223.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Theodor W. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, trans. by Robert Hullot-Kentor (London: Athlone Press, 1997), p. 21.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Theodor W. Adorno, ‘Sacred Fragment: Schoenberg’s Moses und Aron’, in Quasi una Fantasia, trans. by Rodney Livingstone (London: Verso, 1992), p. 230.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe, Musica Ficta: Figures of Wagner, trans. by Felicia McCarren (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1994), pp. xvi–xvii.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Nigel Fortune, ‘Monteverdi and the Secconda Prattica’, in The Monteverdi Companion, ed. by Nigel Fortune and Denis Arnold (London: Faber and Faber, 1968), p. 183. There is of course a relationship to the image here — the rise of monody paralleling linear figuration in baroque painting.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Martin Heidegger, ‘The Age of the World Picture’, in Off the Beaten Track, trans. by Julian Young and Kenneth Hayes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), p. 67.

    Google Scholar 

  16. The deconstruction of presence is anticipated in the Kantbuch. Heidegger states that the concept of the understanding is the ‘regulative unity’ (not regulating unity) of a ‘range of possibilities’. Heidegger does not want to do away with logic — he wants to loosen the grip, Griff, of the concept, Begriff. The dualism of intuition and understanding arises from a need to determine the concept as non-finite — as Kant puts it, ‘never [to] be encountered in an intuition’ (intuition being finite for Kant). The form-content problem is the finitude problem — in Kant’s terms, the antinomy. But the schema refers both to the regulative unity and to the horizon of possibility; the ‘intuiting look’. Hence, ‘beyond the representation of [the] regulative unity of the rule, the concept is nothing. What logic refers to as a concept is grounded in the schema.’ Heidegger cites Kant. The concept ‘always refers immediately to the schema.’ The subsumed object, by way of the schema-image, would equally be nothing. Martin Heidegger, Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, trans. Richard Taft, 5th edition (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1997), p. 69. Emphasis added.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Theodor W. Adorno, ‘On Some Relationships Between Music and Painting’, trans. by Susan H. Gillespie, The Musical Quarterly, 1995, p. 69. Translation amended.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Theodor W. Adorno, Negativ Dialektik (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1966), p. 207.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Hanns Eisler and Theodor W. Adorno, Composing for the Films (London & New York: Athlone Press, 1994), pp. 20–21. The chapter from which this citation is taken was written by Adorno.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Guy Debord, The Society of the Spectacle, trans. by Donald Nicholson-Smith (New York: Zone Books, 1994), p. 112.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), p. 212.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Theodor W. Adorno, Kant’s ‘Critique of Pure Reason’, trans. by Rolf Tiedemann (Cambridge & New York: Polity Press, 2001), pp. 133–4. Adorno promised a more detailed lecture on the schematism chapter, which was never given.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. by John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson (Oxford: Blackwell, 2000), p. 45.

    Google Scholar 

  24. F. W. J. Schelling, System of Transcendental Idealism, trans. by Peter Heath (Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press, 1993), p. 137.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Andrew Bowie, Aesthetics and Subjectivity: From Kant to Nietzsche (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1990), p. 38. Bowie develops the parallel between music and schematism in his essay, ‘Adorno, Heidegger, and the Meaning of Music’, in, ed. Tom Huhn, The Cambridge Companion to Adorno (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), pp. 262–3.

    Google Scholar 

  26. ‘Perhaps there is no more sublime passage in the Jewish Law than the commandment: Thou shalt not make unto thee a graven image, or any likeness of any thing that is in heaven or on earth, or under the earth, etc.’ Immanuel Kant, The Critique of Judgement, trans. by James Creed Meredith (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978), p. 127.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Martin Heidegger, ‘The Origin of the Work of Art’, in Off the Beaten Track, trans. by Julian Young and Kenneth Hayes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), p. 22.

    Google Scholar 

  28. F. W. J. Schelling, The Philosophy of Art, trans. by Douglas W. Stott (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1989), p. 109.

    Google Scholar 

  29. August Wilhelm Schlegel, Vorlesungen Über Philosophische Kunstlehre (Leipzig: Theodor Weicher, 1911), pp. 224–7.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Theodor W. Adorno, Beethoven: The Philosophy of Music, trans. by Edmund Jephcott (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1998), p. 8.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Curt Sachs, Rhythm and Tempo (New York: Dent, 1953), p. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Theodor W. Adorno, ‘Vers Une Musique Informelle’, in Quasi una Fantasia: Essays on Modern Music, trans. by Rodney Livingstone (London & New York: Verso, 1992), p. 312.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Henri Bergson, Key Writings, ed. by Keith Ansell-Pearson (London & New York: Continuum, 2002), p. 60.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Hussurl considers the ‘tone’ as the being the ‘temporal object’ of immediate consciousness, the preceding tones the having-been objects, and the expected tones the anticipated objects. Music (the melody) is the analogy for time itself. And as in Bergson, the ‘tone’ is the analogy for the ‘now’ that is in time. Edmund Husserl, On the Phenomenology of the Consciousness of Internal Time, ed. by Martin Heidegger, trans. by John Barnett Brough (Dordrecht & Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1991), pp. 24–5.

    Google Scholar 

  35. G. W. F. Hegel, Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature: Being Part Two of the ‘Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences’ (1830), trans. by A. V. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1970), p. 35. Cf. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit: ‘History, is a conscious, self-mediating process — Spirit emptied out into Time’, p. 492.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Ludwig Feuerbach, The Fiery Brook, trans. by Zawar Hanfi (Minnesota: Anchor, 1972), pp. 57–8.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Wilhelm Heinrich Wackenroder, ‘The Marvels of the Musical Art’, in German Essays on Music, ed. by Jost Hermand and Michael Gilbert (New York: Continuum, 1994), p. 36.

    Google Scholar 

  38. E. T. A. Hoffmann, ‘Beethoven’s Instrumental Music’, in German Essays on Music, ed. by Jost Hermand and Michael Gilbert (New York: Continuum, 1994), pp. 60–1.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Theodor W. Adorno, ‘On the Contemporary Relationships of Philosophy and Music’, in Essays on Music, trans. by Susan H. Gillespie (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2002), p. 138.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Theodor W. Adorno, Dream Notes, ed. by Christoph Gödde and Jan Philipp Reemsta, trans. by Rodney Livingstone (Cambridge: Polity, 2007).

    Google Scholar 

  41. Ernst Kurth, Musikpsychologie, 2nd edn (Bern: Krompholz, 1947), pp. 85–7.

    Google Scholar 

  42. This is not to say that the goal of modern music is its origin. It does not negate ‘expendable conventions’, in pursuit of its essential medium. In contradistinction to Clement Greenberg, Adorno suggests that the arts converge in a manner that cannot be assumed to be progressive. For Adorno, music has historically lagged behind painting, in that it sought to imitate it, catching up only in the twentieth century. It had been late since the late renaissance of the stile rapprasentativo. Greenberg argues, by contrast, that painting and literature took music, which matured early, for their model. ‘Because of its “absolute” nature, its remoteness from imitation … music had come to replace poetry as the paragon of art. It was the art which the other avant-garde arts envied most, and whose effects they tried hardest to imitate.’ Clement Greenberg, ‘Towards a Newer Laocoon’, in Art in Theory, 1900–2000, ed. by Charles Harrison and Paul Wood (Oxford: Blackwell, 2000), p. 565.

    Google Scholar 

  43. ‘Notizen zum Musiktheater heute’, in Luigi Nono, Texte: Studien zu seiner Musik, ed. Jürg Stenzl (Atlantis, 1975), 64.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Theodor W. Adorno, ‘The Aging of the New Music’, in Essays on Music, ed. by Richard Leppert, trans. by Susan H. Gillespie (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2002), p. 191.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Theodor W. Adorno, ‘On the Relationship Between Painting and Music Today’, in Night Music: Essays on Music 1928–1962, trans. by Wieland Hoban (London: Seagull Books, 2009), p. 415.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Theodor W. Adorno, ‘New Music Today’, in Night Music: Essays on Music 1928–1962, trans. by Wieland Hoban (London: Seagull Books, 2009), pp. 398–9.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Heinz-Klaus Metzger, ‘Intermezzo I: Just Who Is Growing Old?’ ed. by Karlheinz Stockhausen and Herbert Eimert, trans. by Leo Black, Die Reihe, 4 (1960), p. 73.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Theodor W. Adorno, ‘Vienna’, in Quasi una Fantasia: Essays on Modern Music, trans. by Rodney Livingstone (London: Verso, 1992), p. 219.

    Google Scholar 

  49. See, ‘On Astrology’ (1932), ‘Doctrine of the Similar’ (1933), and ‘On the Mimetic Faculty’ (1933), in Walter Benjamin, Selected Writings, Vol. 2, 1931–1934, ed. by Howard Eiland & Michael W. Jennings (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2005).

    Google Scholar 

  50. David Osmond-Smith, Break-out from the Concert Hall: Luigi Nono and the New Music, Concert Program (Queen Elizabeth Hall, London, 2005), p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Cited in, Theodor W. Adorno, In Search of Wagner, trans. by Rodney Livingstone (London: Verso, 2005), p. 88.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Theodor W. Adorno, ‘Wagner’s Relevance for Today’, in Essays on Music, ed. by Richard Leppert, trans. by Susan H. Gillespie (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2002), p. 594.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Helmut Lachenmann, ‘Touched by Nono’, Contemporary Music Review, 18 (1999), p. 19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  54. Georg Lukács, History and Class Consciousness. Studies in Marxist Dialectics, trans. by Rodney Livingstone (London: Merlin Press, 1971), p. 89.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Luigi Nono, ed. by Heinz-Klaus Metzger and Rainer Riehn (Munich: edition text + kritik, 1981), pp. 304–5.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Alastair Williams, ‘New Music, Late Style: Adorno’s “Form in the New Music”’, Music Analysis, 27 (2008), p. 196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  57. György Ligeti and Carl Dahlhaus, ‘A Debate on Contemporary Music’, in Contemplating Music: Essence, ed. by Carl Dahlhaus and Ruth Katz, Source Readings in the Aesthetics of Music (Hillsdale, NY: Pendragon Press, 1992), iii, p. 795.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Jürg Stenzl, Luigi Nono (Reinbek bei Hamburg: Rowohlt, 1998), pp. 97–8.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Irvine Arditti, Nono’s Fragmente-Stille …, Concert Program (Queen Elizabeth Hall, London, 2007), p. 7.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Michele Bertaggia, ‘Prometeo — Conversation Entre Luigi Nono et Massimo Cacciari’, in Programme Luigi Nono (Paris: Contrechamps, 1987), p. 138.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Cf. Jonathan Rée, I See a Voice: A Philosophical History of Language, Deafness and the Senses (London: Harper Collins, 1999).

    Google Scholar 

  62. In his essay on Prometeo, Cacciari refers to the ‘tempo’ of ‘The Master of the Game’ as, ‘the a-rhythmic succession of the punctual’, according to which, the past is nothing more than having-been… and the present is a space from which we throw ourselves ‘all together’ into the future; or, as Michelstaedter used to say, we ‘enfuture’ ourselves. On the other hand, the tempo of the Master is polyphonic; his dimensions are given simultaneously; the past of such a line, of such thought, of such speech, may be the future of any other. The present is not a space common to ‘all’, but the irreplaceable instant, fugitive, clear and living, of the Unique. Like a New Angel, he chants the instant, but this instant, precisely, is unique and non-reproducible, and by the very fact of this uniqueness and of this unrepeatable quality, it never-ceases-to-be; it is necessary. To think necessity and creation simultaneously, snatching something from the instant — the fugitive nature of the instant — that which can break the ‘movimentum’, is infinite temporality, the ‘development’ from one being to another, as from death to death: this is what constitutes the unique quality of the Master of the Game, his ‘weak messianic force’. Massimo Cacciari, ‘Verso Prometeo’, in Programme Luigi Nono, (Paris: Contrechamps, 1987), p. 153. Translation by Adeline Mannarini.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Walter Benjamin, The Arcades Project, trans. by Howard Eiland and Kevin McLaughlin (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2002), p. 462.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Theodor W. Adorno, ‘Die Oper Wozzeck’, in Musikalische Schriften V, ed. Rolf Tiedemann, vol. III, Gesammelte Schriften (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1986), p. 479.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2015 Wesley Phillips

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Phillips, W. (2015). The Dialectical Image of Music. In: Metaphysics and Music in Adorno and Heidegger. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137487254_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics