Skip to main content

Thought Experiments and Experimental Philosophy

  • Chapter
The Palgrave Handbook of Philosophical Methods

Abstract

In recent years, there has been a lot of debate in philosophical methodology about the best rational reconstruction of philosophical thought experiments. Concerning this debate, I will first argue against the current consensus that our intuitive judgments about Gettier thought experiments should be interpreted in modal terms.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 189.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Alexander, J., Mallon, R. & Weinberg, J. (2009). ‘Accentuate the Negative’, Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1(2), pp. 297–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, J. & Weinberg, J. (2007). ‘Analytic Epistemology and Experimental Philosophy’, Philosophy Compass, 2, pp. 56–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balcerak Jackson, M., ms. ‘Intuitions as Inferential Judgments — or Why Intuition Is More Like Logic Than Like Perception’.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balcerak Jackson, M. & Balcerak Jackson, B. (2013). ‘Reasoning as a Source of Justification’, Philosophical Studies, 164(1), pp. 113–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bealer, G. (2002). ‘Modal Epistemology and the Rationalist Renaissance’, In T. Szabo Gendler & J. Hawthorne (eds), Conceivability and Possibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 71–125.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bürge, T. (1979). ‘Individualism and the Mental’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4, pp. 73–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H. (2012). Philosophy Without Intuitions, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H. & Winblad, D. (1999). ‘Intuitions’, Facta Philosophica, 1, pp. 197–216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2002). ‘Does Conceivability Entail Possibility?’ In T. Szabo Gendler & J. Hawthorne (eds), Conceivability and Possibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 145–200.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2004). ‘Epistemic Two-Dimensional Semantics’, Philosophical Studies, 118, pp. 153–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2012). Constructing the World, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colaço, D. et al. (2014). Epistemic Intuitions in Fake-Barn Thought Experiments, Episteme, 11, pp. 199–212.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (1996). ‘Knowledge, Assertion and Lotteries’, Australasian journal of Philosophy, 74(4), pp. 568–580.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feltz, A. & Cokely, E. (2009). ‘Do Judgments About Freedom and Responsibility Depend on Who You Are? Personality Differences in Intuitions About Compatibilism and Incompatibilism’, Consciousness and Cognition, 18(1), pp. 342–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E. (1963). ‘Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?’, Analysis, 23(6), pp. 121–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1967). ‘A Causal Theory of Knowing’, The journal of Philosophy, 64(12), pp. 357–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grundmann, T. & Horvath, J. (2014). ‘Thought Experiments and the Problem of Deviant Realizations’, Philosophical Studies, 170(3), pp. 525–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hales, S. (2006). Relativism and the Foundations of Philosophy, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2004). Knowledge and Lotteries, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horvath, J., ms. ‘Conceptual Analysis and Natural Kinds: The Case of Knowledge’.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horvath, J. (2010). ‘How (Not) to React to Experimental Philosophy’, Philosophical Psychology, 23(4), pp. 447–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horvath, J. (2011). In Defense of Conceptual Analysis. Dissertation. University of Cologne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ichikawa, J.J. & Jarvis, B. (2009). ‘Thought-Experiment Intuitions and Truth in Fiction’, Philosophical Studies, 142(2), pp. 221–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ichikawa, J.J. & Jarvis, B. (2012). ‘Rational Imagination and Modal Knowledge’, Noûs, 46(1), pp. 127–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ichikawa, J.J. & Jarvis, B. (2013). The Rules of Thought, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1998). ‘Reference and Description Revisited’, Noûs, 32(S12), pp. 201–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kipper, J. (2012). A Two-Dimensionalist Guide to Conceptual Analysis, Frankfurt a.M.: Ontos Verlag.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (2002). Knowledge and Its Place in Nature, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and Necessity, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kumar, V. (2013). ‘Knowledge’ as a Natural Kind Term’, Synthese, 191(3), pp. 439–457

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. (1965). ‘Knowledge, Truth and Evidence’, A nalysis, 25(5), pp. 168–175.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ludwig, K. (2007). ‘The Epistemology of Thought Experiments: First Person versus Third Person Approaches’, Midwest Studies In Philosophy, 31(1), pp. 128–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. et al. (2004). ‘Semantics, Cross-Cultural Style’, Cognition, 92, pp. 1–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malmgren, A.-S. (2011). ‘Rationalism and the Content of Intuitive Judgements’, Mind, 120(478), pp. 263–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, J. (2012). ‘Intuitions and Experiments: A Defense of the Case Method in Epistemology’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85(3), pp. 495–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, J., San Juan, V. & Mar, R.A. (2013). ‘Lay Denial of Knowledge for Justified True Beliefs’, Cognition, 129, pp. 652–661.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S. & Knobe, J. (2007). ‘Moral Responsibility and Determinism: The Cognitive Science of Folk Intuitions’, Noûs, 41(4), pp. 663–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett, R. et al. (2001). ‘Culture and Systems of Thought: Holistic Versus Analytic Cognition’, Psychological Review, 108(2), pp. 291–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). ‘The Meaning of ‘Meaning.’ In Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical Papers Vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 215–271.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (2005). What If? Thought Experimentation in Philosophy, New Brunswick, N.J.: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seyedsayamdost, H. (2014). ‘On Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions: Failure of Replication’, Episteme, First View, pp. 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2009). ‘A Defense of the Use of Intuitions in Philosophy.’ In M. Bishop & D. Murphy (eds), Stich and his Critics. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 101–112.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. & Weinberg, J.M. (2001). ‘Jackson’s Empirical Assumptions’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62(3), pp. 637–643.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swain, S., Alexander, J. & Weinberg, J. (2008). ‘The Instability of Philosophical Intuitions: Running Hot and Cold on Truetemp’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76(1), pp. 138–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Unger, P. (1968). ‘An Analysis of Factual Knowledge’, The Journal of Philosophy, 65(6), pp. 157–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vaidya, A. (2010). ‘The Epistemology of Modality.’ In E. N. Zalta, ed. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2010 Edition). Available at: http://plato.Stanford.edu/archives/sum2010/entries/modality-epistemology/.

  • Velleman, J.D. (2000). ‘On the Aim of Belief.’ In The Possibility of Practical Reason. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 244–281.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wedgwood, R. (2007). The Nature of Normativity, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J. et al. (2012). ‘Intuition & Calibration’, Essays in Philosophy, 13(1). Available at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/eip/vol13/iss1/15.

  • Weinberg, J., Nichols, S. & Stich, S. (2001). ‘Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions’, Philosophical Topics, 29, pp. 429–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and Its Limits, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2007). The Philosophy of Philosophy, Maiden, Mass.: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2011). ‘Philosophical Expertise and the Burden of Proof, Metaphilosophy, 42(3), pp. 215–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (1993). ‘Is Conceivabilitya Guide to Possibility?’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 53(1), pp. 1–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2015 Joachim Horvath

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Horvath, J. (2015). Thought Experiments and Experimental Philosophy. In: Daly, C. (eds) The Palgrave Handbook of Philosophical Methods. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137344557_16

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics