Skip to main content

Abstract

Philosophy is highly speculative. Yet not anything goes in philosophy: it is not a matter of thinking or saying whatever takes your fancy. Philosophers have standards to keep. They seek to evaluate and grade their speculations. Some speculations are assigned higher credences — are judged to be more likely — than others. But on what basis is this done? What distinguishes philosophy from sheer or idle speculation is the fact that philosophers argue about their speculations. Philosophy then involves two components: in speculating it devises interesting, novel, and general claims; and in arguing it provides persuasive reasons for accepting (or rejecting) those claims. The centrality of the role of argument in philosophy raises at least three questions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 189.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Alexander, Joshua (2012). Experimental Philosophy: An Introduction. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, Robert (1999). ‘Self-evidence’, Philosophical Perspectives 13: 205–228.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, Robert (2008). ‘Intuition, Inference and Rational Disagreement in Ethics’, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 11: 475–492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J.L. (1946). ‘Other Minds’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society supplementary volume 20: 148–187.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J.L. (1957). ‘A Plea for Excuses: The Presidential Address’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supplementary volume 57: 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, A.J. (1936). Language, Truth and Logic. London: Victor Gollancz.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baz, Avner (2012). When Words Are Called For: A Defense of Ordinary Language Philosophy. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Beebee, Helen and Julian Dodd (eds) (2005). Truthmakers: The Contemporary Debate. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, Karen (2011). ‘Truthmaking and Case-making’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 83: 187–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bigelow, John (1988). The Reality of Numbers: A Physicalist’s Philosophy of Mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, Simon (1984). Spreading the Word: Groundings in the Philosophy of Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braddon-Mitchell, David and Robert Nola (eds) (2009). Conceptual Analysis and Philosophical Naturalism. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, Herman (2012). Philosophy without Intuitions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, Rudolf (1928). The Logical Structure of the World; Pseudoproblems in Philosophy, translated by Rolf A. George. Berkeley, California: University of California Press, 1967.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, Rudolf (1932). ‘The Elimination of Metaphysics through Logical Analysis of Language’, translated by Arthur Pap, in A.J. Ayer (1959) (ed), Logical Positivism. New York: Free Press, pp. 60–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, Rudolf (1950). Logical Foundations of Probability. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, David J. (2012). Constructing the World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, David J. (2015). ‘Why Isn’t There More Progress in Philosophy?’, Philosophy 90:3–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chase, James and Jack Reynolds (2011). Analytic versus Continental: Arguments on the Methods and Value of Philosophy. McGill: Queen’s University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, Roderick, M. (1957). Perceiving: A Philosophical Study. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, Roderick M. (1976). Person and Object: A Metaphysical Study. London: George Allen and Un win.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam (1988). Language and Problems of Knowledge. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, David (2000). ‘Diachronic Coherence versus Epistemic Impartiality’, Philosophical Review 109: 349–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chudnoff, Elijah (2013). Intuition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Conee, Earl (2001). ‘Comments on Bill Lycan’s “Moore Against the New Skeptics’”, Philosophical Studies 103: 55–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Correia, Fabrice and Benjamin Schnieder (2012). Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cullen, Simon (2010). ‘Survey-driven Romanticism’, Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1:275–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daly, Chris (2010). Introduction to Philosophical Methods. Peterborough, Ontario: Broadview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, Norman (1979). ‘Wide Reflective Equilibrium and Theory Acceptance in Ethics’, Journal of Philosophy 76: 256–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald (1975). ‘Thought and Talk’, in Samuel Guttenplan (ed), Mind and Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 7–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel C. (2013). Intuition Pumps and Other Tools for Thinking. New York: W. W. Norton and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • DePaul, Michael DePaul and William Ramsey (eds) (1998). Rethinking Intuition: The Psychology of Intuition and Its Role in Philosophical Inquiry. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, Fred (1981). Knowledge and the Flow of Information. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, Michael (1973). Frege: Philosophy of Language. London: Duckworth Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, Michael (1978). ‘The Justification of Deduction’, in his Truth and Other Enigmas. London: Duckworth Press, pp. 290–318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Durrant, R.G. (1970). ‘Identity of Properties and The Definition of “Good”’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 48: 360–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dyke, Heather (2007). Metaphysics and the Representational Fallacy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, Paul (1949). ‘Bertrand Russell’s Doubts about Induction’, Mind 58: 141–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Enç, Berent (2005). How We Act: Causes, Reasons and Intentions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feigl, Herbert and Grover Maxwell (1961). ‘Why Ordinary Language Needs Reforming’, Journal of Philosophy 58: 488–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fetzer, James H. (1984). Principles of Philosophical Reasoning. Totowa: New Jersey: Rowman and Allanheld.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry A. (1975). The Language of Thought. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foley, Richard (1983). ‘Epistemic Conservatism’, Philosophical Studies 43: 165–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, John F. (1987). ‘Truthmaker’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 65: 188–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frappier, Melanie, Letitia Meynell and James Robert Brown (eds) (2012) Thought Experiments in Science, Philosophy, and the Arts. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, Gottlob (1879). Begriffsschrift, edited and translated by T.W. Bynum as Conceptual Notation. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1972.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, Gottlob (1884). The Foundations of Arithmetic: A Logico-Mathematical Enquiry into the Concept of Number, translated by J.L. Austin, 2nd edition, 1974. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, David (1967). ‘Morality and Advantage’, Philosophical Review 76: 460–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, Tamar Szabo (2010). Intuition, Imagination, and Philosophical Methodology: Selected Papers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, Nelson (1955). Fact, Fiction andForecast. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H.P. (1957). ‘Meaning’, The Philosophical Review 66: 377–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H.P. (1968). ‘Utterer’s Meaning, Sentence Meaning and WordMeaning’, Foundations of Language 4: 225–242.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H.P. (1975). ‘Logic and Conversation’, in Peter Cole, John P. Kimball and Jerry L. Morgan (eds), Syntax and Semantics volume 3: Speech Acts. New York: Academic Press, pp. 41–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H.P. (1978). ‘Further Notes on Logic and Conversation’, in Peter Cole (ed), Syntax and Semantics Volume 9: Pragmatics. New York, NY: Academic Press, pp. 113–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H.P. (1981). ‘Presupposition and Conversational Implicature’, in Peter Cole (ed), Radical Pragmatics. New York: Academic Press, pp. 183–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H.P. and P.F. Strawson (1956). ‘In Defense of a Dogma’, The Philosophical Review 65: 141–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grim, Patrick, Gary Mar and Paul St Denis (1998). The Philosophical Computer: Exploratory Essays in Philosophical Computer Modeling. Massachusetts, Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gutting, Gary (2009). What Philosophers Know: Case Studies in Recent Analytic Philosophy Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hacker, P.M.S. (1996). Wittgenstein’s Place inTwentieth Century Analytic Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanfling, Oswald (2000). Philosophy and Ordinary Language: The Bent and Genius of Our Tongue. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, Gilbert (1965). ‘The Inference to the Best Explanation’, Philosophical Review 74: 88–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, Gilbert (1973). Thought Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, Gilbert (1986). Changein View: Principles of Reasoning. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, W.D. (1977). ‘Review of Mark Steiner, Mathematical Knowledge’, journal of Philosophy 74: 118–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haug, Matthew C. (2014). Philosophical Methodology: The Armchair or the Laboratory. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heil, John (2003). From an Ontological Point of View. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, Carl G. (1945). ‘Studies in the Logic of Confirmation’, Mind 54: 1–26 and 97–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, Carl G. (1950). ‘Problems and Changes in the Empiricist Criterion of Meaning’, Revue Internationale de Philosophie 41: 41–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, Jaakko (1970). ‘The Semantics of Modal Notions and the Indeterminacy of Ontology’, Synthese 21: 408–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horvath, Joachim and Thomas Grundmann (eds) (2012) Experimental Philosophy and Its Critics. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horwich, Paul (2013). Wittgenstein’s Metaphilosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howson, Colin and Peter Urbach (1989). Scientific Reasoning: the Bayesian Approach, 3rd edition 2005. Chicago and La Salle: Open Court Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, Michael (1999). ‘The Problem of Memory Knowledge’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 80: 346–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, Frank (1982). ‘Epiphenomenal Qualia’, Philosophical Quarterly 32: 127–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, Frank (1998). From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Defence of Conceptual Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jenkins, C.S. (2008). ‘Modal Knowledge, Count erfactual Knowledge and the Role of Experience’, Philosophical Quarterly 58: 693–701.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, Mark (1987). ‘Human Beings’, Journal of Philosophy 84: 59–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keller, Simon (2009). ‘Review of Trenton Merricks, Truth and Ontology’, Philosophical Review 118: 273–276.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, Thomas and Sarah McGrath (2015). ‘Are There Any Successful Philosophical Arguments?’, in John-Christopher Keller (ed), Being, Freedom, and Method: Themes from van Inwagen. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, Joshua and Shaun Nichols (eds) (2008). Experimental Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, Hilary (2012). ‘Is Philosophical Knowledge Possible?’, in Diego E. Machuca (ed), Disagreement and Skepticism. London: Routledge, pp. 260–276.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, Saul (1972). ‘Naming and Necessity’, in Gilbert Harman and Donald Davidson (eds), Semantics of Natural Language. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 253–355, 763–769.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, Jonathan L. (1989). ‘Conservatism and Its Virtues’, Synthese 79: 143–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langford, C.H. (1942). ‘The Notion of Analysis in Moore’s Philosophy’, in P.A. Schilpp (ed), The Philosophy of G.E. Moore. La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, pp. 321–342.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, Joseph (2001). Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, David (1968). ‘Counterpart Theory and Quantified Modal Logic’, Journal of Philosophy 65: 113–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, David (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, David (1986). On The Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, David (2001). ‘Truthmaking and Difference-Making’, Nous, 35: 602–615.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, William G. (1975). ‘Occam’s Razor’, Metaphilosophy 6: 223–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, William G. (2013). ‘On Two Main Themes in Gutting’s What Philosophers Know’, Southern Journal of Philosophy 51: 112–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCain, Kevin (2008). ‘The Virtues of Epistemic Conservatism’, Synthese 164: 185–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDaniel, Kris (2011). ‘Trenton Merricks’, Truth and Ontology’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 83: 203–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, Michael (2007). ‘Memory and Epistemic Conservatism’, Synthese 157: 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McTaggart, J.M.E. (1908). ‘The Unreality of Time’, Mind 17: 457–473.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, Edouard and Elizabeth O’Neill (2014). Current Controversies in Experimental Philosophy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malcolm, Norman (1949). ‘Defending Common Sense’, Philosophical Review 58: 201–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marcus, Ruth Barcan (1967). ‘Essentialism in Modal Logic’, Nous 1: 91–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melia, Joseph (1995). ‘On What There’s Not’, Analysis 55: 223–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merricks, Trenton (2007). Truth and Ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Montague, Richard (1973). ‘The Proper Treatment of Quantification in Ordinary English’, in K. J. J. Hintikka, J. M. E. Moravcsik, and Patrick Suppes (eds), Approaches to Natural Language. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 221–242

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G.E. (1903). Principia Ethica, revised edition, 1993. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G.E. (1925). ‘A Defence of Common Sense’, in J. H. Muirhead (ed), Contemporary British Philosophy, second series. London: George Allen and Unwin, pp. 193–223.

    Google Scholar 

  • Naess, Arne (1960). ‘Typology of Questionnaires Adapted to the Study of Ex-pressions with Closely Related Meanings’, Synthese 12: 481–494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, Jennifer, Valerie San Juan and Raymond A. Mar (2013). ‘Lay Denial of Knowledge for Justified True Beliefs’, Cognition 129: 652–661.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, Derek (1984). Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Passmore, John (1961). Philosophical Reasoning. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petitot, Jean, Francisco J. Varela, Bernard Pachoud, and Jean-Michel Roy (1999). Naturalizing Phenomenology: Issues in Contemporary Phenomenology and Cognitive Science. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petrinovich, Lewis and Patricia O’Neill (1996). ‘Influence of Wording and Framing Effects on Moral Intuitions’, Ethology and Sociobiology 17: 145–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Predelli, Stefano (2002). ‘Holmes’ and Holmes: A Millian Analysis of Names from Fiction’, Dialectica 56: 261–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pust, Joel (2001). ‘Against Explanationist Skepticism Regarding Philosophical Intuitions’, Philosophical Studies 106: 227–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Hilary (1975). ‘The Meaning of “Meaning”’, in his Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical Papers volume 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 215–271.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.O. (1951). ‘Two Dogmas of Empiricism’, Philosophical Review 60: 20–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.O. (1953). ‘Reference and Modality’, in From a Logical Point of View, 2nd edition. New York: Harper and Row, 1961, pp. 139–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.O. (1960). Word and Object. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.O. (1969a). ‘Epistemology Naturalized’, in his Epistemology Naturalized and Other Essays. Columbia: Columbia University Press, pp. 69–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.O. (1969b). ‘Natural Kinds’, in Epistemology Naturalized and Other Essays. Columbia: Columbia University Press, pp. 114–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.O. (1970). Philosophy of Logic. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John (1974). ‘The Independence of Moral Theory’, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 48: 5–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rey, Georges (1983). ‘A Reason for Doubting the Existence of Consciousness’, in Richard J. Davidson, Gary E. Schwartz and D. H. Shapiro (eds), Consciousness and Self-Regulation. New York: Plenum, pp. 1–39.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Reynolds, Jack James Chase, James Williams and Edwin Mares (eds) (2010). Postanalytic and Metacontinental: Crossing Philosophical Divides. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieber, Steven (1992). ‘Understanding Synonyms without Knowing that They Are Synonyms’, Analysis 52: 224–228

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rinard, Susanna (2013). ‘Why Philosophy Can Overturn Common Sense’, in Tamar Szabo Gendler and John Hawthorne (eds), Oxford Studies in Epistemology volume 4. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 185–212.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard (1967). The Linguistic Turn: Recent Essays in Philosophical Method. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand (1903). Principles of Mathematics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand (1905). ‘On Denoting’, Mind 14: 479–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand (1911). The Problems of Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand (1914). Our Knowledge of the External World as a Field for Scientific Method in Philosophy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand (1919). Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy. London: George Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, Gilbert (1949). The Concept of Mind. London: Hutchinson Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, Gilbert (1954). Dilemmas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, Thomas (2002). ‘Rawls on justification’, in Samuel Freeman (ed), The Cambridge Companion to Rawls. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 139–167.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, Jonathan (2008). ‘Truth-maker Commitments’, Philosophical Studies 141: 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, Stewart (1991). Foundations without Foundationalism: A Case for Second-Order Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, Theodore (2005). Four Dimensionalism: An Ontology of Persistence and Time. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silverman, Hugh J. and Donn Welton (eds) (1988). Postmodernism and Continental Philosophy. Albany, New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simons, Peter (2000). ‘The Four Phases of Philosophy: Brentano’s Theory and Austria’s History’, The Monist 83: 68–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, Brian (1996). Evolution of the Social Contract. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Joel and Peter Sullivan (2011). Transcendental Philosophy and Naturalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Soames, Scott (2003a). Philosophy in the Twentieth Century, volume 1: The Dawn of Analysis. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soames, Scott (2003b). Philosophy in the Twentieth Century volume 2: The Age of Meaning. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, Elliott (1988). Reconstructing the Past: Parsimony, Evolution, and Inference. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen, Roy (1992). Thought Experiments. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stampe, Dennis A. (1977). ‘Toward a Causal Theory of Linguistic Representation’, in Peter French, Howard K. Wettstein, and T. E. Uehling (eds), Midwest Studies in Philosophy, volume 2. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 42–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stevenson, C.L. (1944). Ethics and Language. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stove, David (1991). The Plato Cult and Other Philosophical Follies. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P.F. (1950). ‘On Referring’, Mind 59: 320–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P.F. (1952). Introduction to Logical Theory. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P.F. (1963). ‘Carnap’s Views on Constructed Systems versus Natural Languages in Analytic Philosophy’, in P.A. Schilpp (ed), The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. La Salle, IL: Open Court, pp. 503–518.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, Patrick (1968). ‘The Desirability of Formalization in Science’, Journal of Philosophy 65:651–664.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, Alfred (1933). ‘The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages’, in John Corcoran (ed), Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics: Papers from 1923 to 1938, translated by J. H. Woodger, 2nd edition. Indianapolis: Hackett, pp. 152–278.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, Judith (1971). ‘A Defense of Abortion’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 1: 47–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Unger, Peter (2014). Empty Ideas: A Critique of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Cleve, James (1979). ‘Foundationalism, Epistemic Principles, and the Cartesian Circle’, Philosophical Review 88: 55–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, Peter (2006). The Problem of Evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weatherson, Brian (2003). ‘What Good Are Counterexamples?’, Philosophical Studies 115: 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, Jonathan M., Shaun Nichols and Stephen Stich (2001). ‘Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions’, Philosophical Topics 29: 429–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, Alfred North and Bertrand Russell (1910, 1912, 1913). Principia Mathematica, volumes 1–3. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkes, Kathleen V. (1988). Real People: Personal Identity without Thought Experiments. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, Timothy (2007a). The Philosophy of Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, Timothy (2007b). ‘Philosophical Knowledge and Knowledge of Counterfactuals’, Grazer Philosophische Studien 74: 89–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1953). Philosophical Investigations, translated by G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2015 Chris Daly

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Daly, C. (2015). Introduction and Historical Overview. In: Daly, C. (eds) The Palgrave Handbook of Philosophical Methods. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137344557_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics