Skip to main content

Nietzsche: The Therapeutic Function of Genealogy

  • Chapter
  • 155 Accesses

Abstract

Throughout this book, we have been developing, with Freudian resources, an account of qualified freedom. Human interpretation crucially enters into inheriting our personal and cultural histories, negotiating the demands of society, and expressing the basic drives possessed by embodied beings, but that activity also emerges out of these different conditions and is constrained by them. Nineteenth-century German philosophy tries to make sense of a divided self whose relation to the world and its own psyche are deeply troubled — limited epistemically and afflicted by forces that problematize its capacity for rational self-determination. We have discussed various attempts to come to terms what it means to be a situated subject: Fichte’s appeal to the Anstoss, the hermeneutic circle, and Marx’s challenge to the distinction between thinking and matter, among others. However, no philosopher challenges the model of the sovereign, self-possessed subject more than Nietzsche, whose work decisively rejects the faith in reason and progressive history that reaches its culmination in the work of Hegel.

We are all suffering from a consuming fever of history and ought at least to recognize that we are suffering from it.

Friedrich Nietzsche, “On the Uses and Disadvantages of History for Life”

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Comparisons between Freud and Nietzsche include Daniel Chapelle, Nietzsche and Psychoanalysis (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1993);

    Google Scholar 

  2. Ronald Lehrer, Nietzsche’s Presence in Freud’s Life and Thought: On the Origins of a Psychology of Dynamic Unconscious Mental Functioning (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1995);

    Google Scholar 

  3. Reinhard Gasser, Nietzsche und Freud (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1997);

    Book  Google Scholar 

  4. and Paul-Laurent Assoun, Freud and Nietzsche, trans. Richard L. Collier, Jr. (London: Athlone Press, 2000).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morals, trans. Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale, ed. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Vintage, 1967), I:2.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ibid., I:12. Many scholars have compared the will to power to Freud’s conception of the drives. See the sources listed in Note 1 above as well as Ofelia Schutte, “Willing Backwards: Nietzsche on Time, Pain, Joy, and Memory,” in Nietzsche and Depth Psychology, ed. Jacob Golomb, Weaver Santaniello, and Ronald Lehrer (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1999), 111–26;

    Google Scholar 

  7. and Robert Grimwade, “Freud’s Philosophical Inheritance: Schopenhauer and Nietzsche in Beyond the Pleasure Principle,” Psychoanalytic Review 99, no. 3 (June 2012): 359–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Nietzsche’s claims about the will to power have an ambiguous status, because he suspects that what counts as natural is humanly constructed and then treated as if it were objective. In Beyond Good and Evil, Nietzsche accuses the Stoics of constructing a view of nature and then justifying their moral account with reference to that supposedly unchanging nature, discovered through reason (Friedrich Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, trans. Walter Kaufmann [New York: Vintage, 1966], §9). Given this understanding of how the concept of nature is used, it is not clear whether the description of the will to power is a literal metaphysical account of human nature (along the lines of Schopenhauer’s position) or an interpretation of nature from our historical perspective.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Friedrich Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols, trans. R. J. Hollingdale (New York: Penguin, 1968), “The Four Great Errors,” §7.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Friedrich Nietzsche, “On the Uses and Disadvantages of History for Life,” in Untimely Meditations, trans. R. J. Hollingdale, ed. Daniel Breazeale (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), §3.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  11. Friedrich Nietzsche, The Gay Science, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Vintage, 1974), §344.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Susan Bordo, Unbearable Weight: Feminism, Western Culture, and the Body (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2003), 144.

    Google Scholar 

  13. See Michel Foucault, “What is Enlightenment?” trans. Catherine Porter, in The Foucault Reader, ed. Paul Rabinow (New York: Pantheon, 1984), 32–50.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Richard Schacht, “Nietzschean Normativity,” in Nietzsche’s Postmoralism: Essays on Nietzsche’s Prelude to Philosophy’s Future, ed. Richard Schacht (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 152.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Friedrich Nietzsche, Ecce Homo, trans. and ed. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Vintage, 1967), “Why I Am A Destiny,” §1.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Maria Talero, “Temporality and the Therapeutic Subject: The Phenomenology of Transference, Remembering, and Working-Through,” in Rereading Freud: Psychoanalysis through Philosophy, ed. Jon Mills (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2004), 176.

    Google Scholar 

  17. On the issue of trauma as a breach in the mind’s experience of time, see Cathy Caruth, Unclaimed Experience: Trauma, Narrative, and History (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1996), 10–24, 57–72. Caruth emphasizes the unmediated nature of trauma (how an event is imprinted on the psyche without being interpreted in any way), which contrasts with our reading in this chapter. Ruth Leys critiques Caruth’s view, on the basis that it ignores the role of the retrospective investment of meaning (Trauma: A Genealogy [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000], 266–97). Nonetheless, in both interpretations, trauma distorts the relationship between present and past, and hampers the subject’s ability to construct a coherent narrative about her own life.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Jean Laplanche, “Notes on Afterwardsness,” in Essays on Otherness, ed. John Fletcher (London: Routledge, 1999), 260–65.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Judith Butler, The Psychic Life of Power: Theories in Subjection (Stanford, Cal.: Stanford University Press, 1997), 99.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Friedrich Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra, trans. Walter Kaufmann (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1966), II:20 (“On Redemption”).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2013 Matthew C. Altman and Cynthia D. Coe

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Altman, M.C., Coe, C.D. (2013). Nietzsche: The Therapeutic Function of Genealogy. In: The Fractured Self in Freud and German Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137263322_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics