Advertisement

Recognition as the Grounds of a General Theory of Crime as Social Harm?

  • Majid Yar

Abstract

In evaluating the capacity of recognition theory to furnish a general theoretical framework for grasping social processes, relations, and problems, it is worth remembering the origins of Critical Theory. Despite the foundation of the Frankfurt Institute for Social Research in 1923, its distinctive critical project was not explicitly formulated until 1931, on the occasion of Max Horkheimer’s assumption of the Directorship of the Institute (Honneth 1992, p. 3). Horkheimer’s opening address, titled ‘The Present Situation of Social Philosophy and the Tasks of an Institute for Social Research’, presented the ambition of Critical Theory as

the philosophical interpretation of the vicissitudes of human fate — the fate of humans not as mere individuals, however, but as members of a community. It is thus above all concerned with phenomena that can only be understood in the context of human social life: with the state, law, economy, religion

(Horkheimer 1993[1931], p. 1)

Horkeheimer distinguished this social-philosophical endeavour from that of Enlightenment philosophy (exemplified by Kant), which while attending to matters of art, culture, law, and moral life did so only with reference to the ‘isolated subject’.

Keywords

Critical Theory Social Harm Causal Hypothesis Legal Positivism Social Subject 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Adorno, T. and Horkheimer, M. (1997[1947]) Dialectic of Enlightenment (London: Verso).Google Scholar
  2. Ayer, A.J. (2001[1936]) Language, Truth and Logic (London: Penguin).Google Scholar
  3. Benhabib, S. (1986) Critique, Norm and Utopia: A Study in the Foundations of Critical Theory (New York: Columbia University Press).Google Scholar
  4. Conkin, W.E. (2001) The Invisible Origins of Legal Positivism: A Re-Reading of a Tradition (Dordrecht: Kluwer).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Dyzenhaus, D. (1999) Legality and Legitimacy: Carl Schmitt, Hans Kelsen, and Hermann Heller in Weimar (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Ferguson, D.M. and Lynskey, M.T. (1997) ‘Physical Punishment/Maltreatment During Childhood and Adjustment in Young Adulthood’, Child Abuse & Neglect, 21(7), 617–630.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Gadamer, H.-G. (2004[1975]) Truth and Method (London/New York: Continuum).Google Scholar
  8. Gadd, D. (2000) ‘Masculinities, Violence and Defended Psychosocial Subjects’, Theoretical Criminology, 4(4), 429–449.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Gadd, D. (2003) ‘Reading Between the Lines: Subjectivity and Men’s Violence’, Men and Masculinities, 5(4), 333–354.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Gadd, D. (2006) ‘The Role of Recognition in the Desistance Process: A Case Analysis of a Former Far-Right Activist’, Theoretical Criminology, 10(2), 179–202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Gadd, D. and Jefferson, T. (2007) Psychosocial Criminology: An Introduction (London: Sage).Google Scholar
  12. Gay, P. (1998) Freud: A Life For Our Time (New York: Norton).Google Scholar
  13. Giddens, A. (1986) The Constitution of Society: Outline of a Theory of Structuration (Cambridge, MA: Polity Press).Google Scholar
  14. Habermas, J. (1992) The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere: Inquiry into a Category of Bourgeois Society (Cambridge, MA: Polity Press).Google Scholar
  15. Habermas, J. (1998[1972]) Knowledge and Human Interests (Cambridge, MA: Polity Press).Google Scholar
  16. Hillyard, P. and Tombs, S. (2008) ‘Beyond Criminology’, in D. Dorling et al. (eds.), Criminal Obsessions: Why Harm Matters Than Crime (London: Kings College Centre for Crime and Justice Studies), 6–23.Google Scholar
  17. Hillyard, P., Pantazis, C., Tombs, S., and Gordon, D. (eds.) (2004) Beyond Criminology: Taking Harms Seriously (London: Pluto Press).Google Scholar
  18. Honneth, A. (1992) ‘Integrity and Disrespect: Principles of a Conception of Morality Based on the Theory of Recognition’, Political Theory, 20(2), 187–201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Honneth, A. (1994) ‘The Social Dynamics of Disrespect’, Constellations, 1(2), 255–269.Google Scholar
  20. Honneth, A. (1996) The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts (Cambridge, MA: Polity Press).Google Scholar
  21. Honneth, A. (2007) Disrespect: The Normative Foundations of Critical Theory (Oxford: Polity Press).Google Scholar
  22. Horkheimer, M. (1986[1937]) ‘Traditional and Critical Theory’, in Critical Theory: Selected Essays (London: Continuum), 188–243.Google Scholar
  23. Horkheimer, M. (1993[1931]) Between Philosophy and Social Science. Selected Early Writings (Boston, MA: MIT Press).Google Scholar
  24. Jasso, G. (2006) ‘Formal Theory’, in J.H. Turner (ed.), Handbook of Sociological Theory (New York: Springer).Google Scholar
  25. Kelly, M. (1994) Critique and Power: Recasting the Foucault/Habermas Debate (Boston, MA: MIT Press).Google Scholar
  26. Kramer, M.H. (2003) In Defence of Legal Positivism: Law Without Trimmings (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Malinosky-Rummell, R. and Hansen, D.J. (1993) ‘Long-Term Consequences of Childhood Physical Abuse’, Psychological Bulletin, 114(1), 68–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Marcuse, H. (1991[1964]) One Dimensional Man: Studies in the Ideology of Advanced Industrial Society (London: Routledge).Google Scholar
  29. Misak, C.J. (1995) Verificationism: Its History and Prospects (London: Routledge).Google Scholar
  30. Muncie, J. (2000) ‘Decriminalising Criminology’, in G. Lewis, S. Gerwitz, and J. Clarke (eds.), Rethinking Social Policy (London: SAGE).Google Scholar
  31. Popper, K. ([1959] 2002) The Logic of Scientific Discovery (London: Routledge).Google Scholar
  32. Ryle, G. (2000[1949]) The Concept of Mind (London: Penguin).Google Scholar
  33. Sayer, A. (1999) Realism and Social Science (London: Sage).Google Scholar
  34. Sayer, A. (2004) ‘Restoring the Moral Dimension in Social Scientific Accounts: A Qualified Ethical Naturalist Approach’, in M. Archer and W. Outhwaite (eds.), Defending Objectivity: Essays in Honour of Andrew Collier (London: Routledge).Google Scholar
  35. Shotter, J. (1993) Cultural Politics of Everyday Life: Social Constructionism, Rhetoric and Knowing of the Third Kind (Milton Keynes: Open University Press).Google Scholar
  36. Sutherland, E.H. (1947) Principles of Criminology (Philadelphia, PA: Lippincott).Google Scholar
  37. van Swaaningen, R. (1999) ‘Reclaiming Critical Criminology: Social Justice and the European Tradition’, Theoretical Criminology, 3(1), 5–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Wittgenstein. L. (2001[1953]) Philosophical Investigations: The German Text, with a Revised English Translation (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
  39. Yar, M. (2001) ‘Beyond Nancy Fraser’s “Perspectival Dualism”’, Economy & Society, 30(3), 288–303.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Yar, M. (2010) ‘“And Every Cruelty Will Cloud It”: On Love, Damaged Selfhood and Criminal Harm’, in S. Thompson, and M. Yar (eds.), The Politics of Misrecognition (Aldershot: Ashgate).Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Majid Yar 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  • Majid Yar

There are no affiliations available

Personalised recommendations