Skip to main content

Nietzsche on Language: Interpretation as Religious Practice

  • Chapter
  • 37 Accesses

Part of the book series: Studies in Literature and Religion ((SLR))

Abstract

In ‘Maxims and Arrows,’ the first part of the Twilight of the Idols, Nietzsche speculated that ‘[i]f we possess our why of life we can put up with almost any how.1 The possibility of possessing the ‘why’ of life, of believing that human experience has meaning, is an integral part of his reflection on the relationship between the religious imagination and language — between creativity and meaning. In the aftermath of the death of God, meaninglessness is the sign of powerlessness. Not only has humanity lost its will to truth — which of itself is among the causes of meaninglessness — but it has ‘grown one stage poorer, no longer possessing the strength to interpret, to create fictions …’ of which even the will to truth avails itself (WP 585A). The revaluation of values is Nietzsche’s attempt to recover the ‘strength to interpret, to create fictions’ in order to lend meaning to human existence. His rejection of metaphysics, the notion of a transcendent referent and the certainty vested in objective truth, signifies the emergence of a new and dynamic understanding of values.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Friedrich Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols, trans. R. J. Hollingdale (1968; revised ed., Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1990), p. 23. Hereafter cited parenthetically as TI with numbers referring to pages.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Herbert Schnadelbach, Philosophy in Germany 1831–1933, trans. Eric Mathews (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), pp. 161–7.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See, Makarushka, ‘Nietzsche’s Critique of Modernity,’ 199ff. Also, Ernest L. Fortin, ‘Nietzsche and Nihilism,’ in Leroy Rouner, ed. Meaning, Truth and God (Notre Dame, Ind.: Notre Dame University Press, 1982), p. 206.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Friedrich Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Vintage Books, 1966), §230. Hereafter cited parenthetically as BGE with numbers referring to sections.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Paul Ricoeur, The Rule of Metaphor, trans. Robert Czerny (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1975), pp. 284ff.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Friedrich Nietzsche, ‘The Philosopher: Reflections on the Struggle between Art and Knowledge,’ in Philosophy and Truth: Selections from Nietzsches Notebooks of the Early 1870’s, ed. and trans. Daniel Breazeale (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1979), pp. 3–61. Hereafter cited parenthetically as P with numbers referring to sections.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Friedrich Nietzsche, ‘On Truth and Lies in a Nonmoral Sense,’ Philosophy and Truth: Selections from Nietzsches Notebooks of the Early 1870’s, ed. and trans. Daniel Breazeale (New Jersey: Humanities Press, 1979), pp. 79–100. Hereafter cited parenthetically as TLNS with numbers referring to pages.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Paul Ricoeur, ‘The Status of Vorstellung in Hegel’s Philosophy of Religion,’ in Leroy S. Rouner, ed., Meaning, Truth, and God (Notre Dame, Ind. and London: University of Notre Dame Press, 1982), pp. 70–90. He pointed out that absolute knowledge defined as ‘the thoughtfulness of picture-thinking’ allows for ‘the possibility of reinterpreting the hermeneutics of religious thinking as an endless process thanks to which representative and speculative thought keep generating one another.’ There is an inner dynamism that directs ‘figurative thought toward speculative thought without ever abolishing the narrative and symbolic features of the figurative mode’ (p. 86). Nietzsche did not hold with the notion of absolute knowledge or truth, however, he did note in several instances the role of image or picture thinking in the creation of concepts (P 115–16).

    Google Scholar 

  9. Hayden White, Metahistory, (Baltimore and London: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1973), p. 374.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Friedrich Nietzsche, ‘Description of Ancient Rhetoric,’ in Sander Gilman, Carole Blair, David J. Parent, eds and trans., Friedrich Nietzsche on Rhetoric and Language (New York: Oxford University Press, 1989), p. 25. For an incisive commentary on these early lectures on language and rhetoric, see: Sander Gilman, Carole Blair, David J. Parent, ‘Introduction,’ in Friedrich Nietzsche on Rhetoric and Language (New York: Oxford University Press, 1989), pp. ix–xxi.

    Google Scholar 

  11. David B. Allison, ‘Introduction,’ in David B. Allison, ed., The New Nietzsche (New York: Dell Publishing, 1977), p. xv. Allison’s introduction offered not only a clear assessment of Nietzsche’s understanding of language and metaphor, but also an analysis of metaphor as an analogue for the will to power. His intention is to suggest that by coming to understand Nietzsche’s general semiotics, some of the problems that Nietzsche’s aphoristic style presents for the reader can be elucidated.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Jacques Derrida, ‘White Mythology: Metaphor in the Text of Philosophy,’ trans. F. C. T. Moore, in New Literary Review, 6, no. 1 (Autumn 1974), p. 15. For an opposing view to Derrida’s ‘white mythology’ see: Ricoeur, The Rule of Metaphor, pp. 284ff. His insistence on living metaphor is consonant with Nietzsche’s view of metaphor as a redescription of reality inaccessible to conceptual explanation. For an exploration of the relationship between metaphor and metamorphosis with regard to Nietzsche’s philosophical method, see: Allison, ‘Introduction’ in The New Nietzsche, p. xvi–xix.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Ophelia Schutte, Beyond Nihilism (Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 1984), pp. 35–6.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Friedrich Nietzsche, Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks, trans. Marianne Cowan (Chicago, Ill.: Regnery, 1962). Hereafter cited as parenthetically as PTAG with numbers referring to pages.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Johan Huizinga, Homo Ludens (Boston: Beacon Press, 1955). For Heraclitus play is at the root of the notion that contradictory forces give rise to cosmic order (116–17). He remarked that Nietzsche had been blamed ‘for having re-adopted the old agnostic attitude of philosophy. If indeed he did so, then he has led philosophy back to its antique origins’ (p. 152). On Nietzsche and the Heraclitean notion of play, see also: Breazeale, ‘Introduction; p. xlii n. 36; and Nietzsche, ‘On the Pathos of Truth,’ in Nietzsche, Philosophy and Truth, p. 64. The notion of play figures in the development of the concept of the creative imagination and to the romantic understanding of the cult of genius. See: James Engell, The Creative Imagination (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1981). He pointed out that Schiller described the creative imagination as ‘Spieltriebe,’ play-instinct (pp. 231–6).

    Google Scholar 

  16. Friedrich Nietzsche, ‘Homer’s Contest,’ in Early Greek Philosophy & Other Essays, vol. 2 of The Complete Works of Friedrich Nietzsche, Oscar Levy, ed., trans. Maximillian A. Mugge, 18 vols., (1909–11, reprinted New York: Russell and Russell, 1964), p. 51.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morals, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York, Vintage Books, 1969), pt III: 24. Hereafter cited parenthetically as GM with numbers referring to parts and sections.

    Google Scholar 

  18. J. Hillis Miller, ‘The Disarticulation of the Self in Nietzsche,’ The Monist 64, no. 2 (April 1981): 247–61. He offered a deconstructionist interpretation of Nietzsche’s understanding of interpretation and maintained that Nietzsche is fundamentally a deconstructionist.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morals, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Vintage Books: 1969), § 2:1. Hereafter cited parenthetically as GM with numbers referring to book and essay.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Arthur O. Lovejoy, The Great Chain of Being: A Study of the History of an Idea (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1936). He traced the idea of metaphysical theology from Plato through its demise in the nineteenth century.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Joan Stambaugh, Nietzsches Thoughts on the Eternal Recurrence (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1972), p. 1.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 1994 Irena S. M. Makarushka

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Makarushka, I.S.M. (1994). Nietzsche on Language: Interpretation as Religious Practice. In: Religious Imagination and Language in Emerson and Nietzsche. Studies in Literature and Religion. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9780230375307_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics