Skip to main content

Abstract

Is critique a machine invented in the seventeenth century, an instrument among many others designed to destroy the remains of a feudalist and theological worldview? Is it a machine that during the nineteenth and twentieth centuries constantly adapted itself to new challenges, feeding itself on targets produced by the very modernity from which it issued? Is critique a machine that today, at the beginning of the twenty-first century, has finally run out of steam, as Bruno Latour has recently suggested?1 And if critique may seem to have come to a standstill, is this because it does not find new targets anymore or rather because it has torn to pieces the very possibility of distinguishing between a truth grasped by the critic, a set of norms to be criticised and masses in need of enlightenment? Has critique thereby devoured its very condition of possibility?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. B. Latour, ‘Why Has Critique Run out of Steam? From Matters of Fact to Matters of Concern’, Critical Inquiry, 30/2, 2004, 225–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. A. Badiou, Deleuze: The Clamor of Being (Minneapolis, MN and London: University of Minneapolis Press, 1999), 45–46.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Of the few books devoted to philosophical and theoretical forms of critique only Kurt Röttgers’ Kritik und Praxis: Zur Geschichte des Kritikbegriffs von Kant bis Marx (Berlin and New York: Walter de Gruyter, 1975) adopts a historical perspective. Röttgers covers one of the most productive eras of critical philosophy, but hardly relates his findings to contemporary questions. Two recent collections of essays, on the other hand, focus on contemporary challenges to philosophical theories of critique:

    Book  Google Scholar 

  4. R. Sinnerbrink et al. (eds), Critique Today (Leiden and Boston, MA: Brill, 2006); and

    Google Scholar 

  5. R. Jaeggi and T. Wesche (eds), Was ist Kritik? (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 2009). A third volume defends the political impact of contemporary theoretical accounts of critique:

    Google Scholar 

  6. B. Mennel, S. Nowotny and G. Raunig (eds), Kunst der Kritik (Vienna: Turia + Kant, 2010). Contrary to these works, the present volume is based on the view that discussions about the contemporary relevance of particular forms of critique cannot be divorced from investigations into their history.

    Google Scholar 

  7. See the transcripts of Foucault’s last courses at the Collège de France for an account of the strong affinity between modern critical philosophy and its precursors in antiquity: M. Foucault, The Government of Self and Others: Lectures at the College de France, 1982–1983 (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010); and

    Book  Google Scholar 

  8. M. Foucault, The Courage of Truth: Lectures at the College de France, 1983–1984 (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2011).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  9. This passage is taken from Kant’s critical response to the review of the Critique of Pure Reason by Garve and Feder, which he presented as an appendix to the Prolegomena. See I. Kant, Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics That Will Be Able to Come Forward as Science, translated by G. Hatfield (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 133–134, translation modified. Kant’s conception of critique is in line with the meaning of the Greek krinein, which means to separate, discriminate, discern or judge. Cf.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  10. R. Sonderegger, ‘Kritik’, in S. Gosepath, W. Hinsch and B. Rössler (eds), Handbuch der politischen Philosophie und Sozialphilosophie (Berlin and New York: de Gruyter, 2008), 669–674.

    Google Scholar 

  11. By no means does this amount to claiming that critique is an exclusively Western practice. See, for instance, A. Sen, The Argumentative Indian: Writings on Indian Culture, History and Identity (London and New York: Penguin Books, 2005).

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ricoeur famously referred to Marx, Nietzsche and Freud as ‘masters of suspicion’. P. Ricoeur, Freud and Philosophy: An Essay on Interpretation, translated by D. Savage (New Haven, CT and London: Yale University Press, 1970), 32–33.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2012 Karin de Boer and Ruth Sonderegger

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

de Boer, K., Sonderegger, R. (2012). Introduction. In: de Boer, K., Sonderegger, R. (eds) Conceptions of Critique in Modern and Contemporary Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9780230357006_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics