Skip to main content

The Sublime, Revisited

  • Chapter
Why Music Moves Us
  • 159 Accesses

Abstract

Throughout this book we have been trying to make sense of responses to music like the one recounted by the unnamed volunteer in the first epigraph to this chapter. I have described these as “strong emotional” and as “sublime” responses, thereby placing them in a philosophical tradition extending from Longinus to Kant and beyond. In doing so, I have used “sublime” in a way that, while not opposed to traditional usage, does not fully cohere with it either. Steering clear of value judgements and ontological commitments, I have remained neutral as to whether the musical works that seem to arouse such responses were themselves “really” sublime or not. In this chapter we face these more normative issues squarely. What is the relationship between the sublime and beauty, and between the sublime and artistic greatness? How are feelings of the sublime related to other possible types of responses to music? What is gained and what is lost in treating sublime responses as fundamentally emotional in nature?

In certain passages it evokes sobs and I feel totally crushed — my listening is fully concentrated, and the rest of the world disappears in a way, and I become merged in the music or the music in me, it fills me completely. I also get physical reactions…wet eyes, a breathing that gets sobbing in certain passages, a feeling of crying in my throat and chest. Trying to find words for the emotions themselves, I would like to use words as: crushed, shaken, tragedy, maybe death, absorption, but also tenderness, longing, desire (vain), a will to live, prayer. The whole experience also has the character of a total standstill, a kind of meditative rest, a last definite and absolute end, after which nothing else can follow.

Unnamed volunteer, report to the SEM Project

A lofty passage does not convince the reason of the reader, but takes him out of himself. That which is admirable ever confounds our judgement, and eclipses that which is merely reasonable or agreeable. To believe or not is usually in our own power; but the Sublime, acting with an imperious and irresistible force, sways every reader whether he will or no.

Longinus, On the Sublime (i)

that which excites in us, without any reasoning about it, but in the mere apprehension of it, the feeling of the sublime may appear, as regards its form, to violate purpose in respect of the judgment, to be unsuited to our presentative faculty, and as it were to do violence to the imagination; and yet it is judged to be only the more sublime. (§23)

For just as we charge with want of taste the man who is indifferent when passing judgment upon an object of nature that we regard as beautiful, so we say of him who remains unmoved in the presence of that which we judge to be sublime: He has no feeling. (§29)

Kant, Critique of Judgement

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 44.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 59.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 59.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Bibliographic Notes

  • Jeanette Bicknell, “Music, Listeners, and Moral Awareness,” Philosophy Today 45 (Fall 2001) 266–74, where I wrote about the connections between music and morality.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • E. F. Carritt, The Theory of Beauty (London: Methuen, 1962).

    Google Scholar 

  • Stephen Davies, “Profundity in Instrumental Music,” British Journal of Aesthetics 42:4 (October 2002) 343–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eduard Hanslick, On the Musically Beautiful, trans. Geoffrey Payzant (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1986).

    Google Scholar 

  • Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgement, trans. J.H. Bernard (New York: Hafner Press, 1951).

    Google Scholar 

  • Peter Kivy, Music Alone: Philosophical Reflections of the Purely Musical Experience (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1994).

    Google Scholar 

  • Peter Kivy, “Another Go at Musical Profundity: Stephen Davies and the Game of Chess,” British Journal of Aesthetics 43:4 (October 2003), pp. 401–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deborah Knight, “Why We Enjoy Condemning Sentimentality,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 57:4 (1999).

    Google Scholar 

  • Jerrold Levinson, “Musical Profundity Misplaced,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 50:1 (Winter 1992) 58–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longinus, On the Sublime, trans. H. L. Havell, Essays in Classical Criticsm (London: Dent, 1953).

    Google Scholar 

  • Leonard Meyer, “Some Remarks on Value and Greatness in Music,” in Music, the Arts and Ideas: Patterns and Predictions in Twentieth-Century Culture (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1967), pp. 22–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mary Mothersill, Beauty Restored (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984).

    Google Scholar 

  • Mary Mothersill, “Sublime,” in A Companion to Aesthetics, ed. David Cooper (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997), pp. 407–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mary Mothersill, “Beauty and the Critic’s Judgment: Remapping Aesthetics,” in The Blackwell Guide to Aesthetics ed. Peter Kivy (Oxford: Blackwell, 2004), pp. 152–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ira Newman, “Learning from Tolstoy: Forgetfulness and Recognition in Literary Edification,” Philosophia 36:1 (March 2008) 43–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colin Radford, “How Can Music Be Moral?” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 16 (1991) 421–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett Reimer, “The Experience of Profundity in Music,” Journal of Aesthetic Education 29:4 (Winter 1995) 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aaron Ridley, The Philosophy of Music: Theme and Variations (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2004).

    Google Scholar 

  • Roger Scruton, The Aesthetics of Music (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998).

    Google Scholar 

  • R. A. Sharpe, “Sounding the Depths,” British Journal of Aesthetics 40:1 (January 2000) 64–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guy Sircello, A New Theory of Beauty (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1975).

    Google Scholar 

  • David A. White, “Towards a Theory of Profundity in Music,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 50 (1992) 23–34.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Copyright information

© 2009 Jeanette Bicknell

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bicknell, J. (2009). The Sublime, Revisited. In: Why Music Moves Us. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9780230233836_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics