Skip to main content

When Ownership and Agency Collide: The Phenomenology of Limb-Disownership

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Body Disownership in Complex Posttraumatic Stress Disorder
  • 703 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter explores the complex relationship between the sense of body-ownership (SBO) and sense of agency (SA) with respect to limb ownership. It contends that in the case of a contradiction between these mechanisms, an individual is liable to develop limb-disownership .

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Body-ownership has been linked to processing in several regions. These include the premotor cortex (PMC), intraparietal cortex (IPC), temporoparietal junction (TPJ), sensorimotor cortex, extrastriate body area (EBA), and insula (Arzy, Thut, Mohr, Michel, & Blanke, 2006; Blanke, 2012; Tsakiris, Hesse, Boy, Haggard, & Fink, 2006). The processing of interoceptive information occurs on well-defined pathways from the dorsal root of spinal nerves to the thalamus, nucleus of the solitary tract. This is then relayed to the central cortical processing regions of the anterior cingulate cortex (ACC) and insular cortex (Craig, 2003; Critchley & Harrison, 2013‏). Essentially, although neural processing connected to agency, ownership and interoception are subserved by distinct brain systems, they show some partial convergence in the insular and medial frontal regions.

  2. 2.

    For an in-depth analysis of a number of cases, see Appendix 2.

  3. 3.

    Denial and lack of awareness are not equivalent phenomena or mechanisms.

  4. 4.

    What Guterstam and Ehrsson define (2012) as body-disownership (see the detailed discussion in Chapter 3) is in fact the lack of sense of body-ownership .

  5. 5.

    It may be that Coltheart’s (2010) two-factor theory suggests at least a partial (theoretical in nature) solution. According to this approach, in order for a delusional belief to emerge, two mechanisms are necessary: “(a) the presence of a neuropsychological impairment that initially prompts the delusional belief and (b) the presence of a second neuropsychological impairment that interferes with processes of belief evaluation that would otherwise cause the delusional belief to be rejected” (p. 16). Hence, we suggest that when the second mechanism ceases to function, the outcome is disownership.

  6. 6.

    However, some have suggested that “this phenomenon, although almost certainly rare, may be more common than was originally appreciated” (First & Fisher, 2011, p. 4).

  7. 7.

    A few decades ago scholars identified and described BIID in terms of Psychopathia Sexualis—sexual attraction to amputees or others with disabilities (Wakefield, Frank, & Meyers, 1977). However, more recent findings argue strongly against this thesis (Furth & Smith, 2000). Based on pre/postoperative evaluations, scholars have argued that individuals who undergo this elective amputation (a) do not reveal psychiatric illnesses, and (b) are not sexually attracted to amputees (Fisher & Smith, 2000). Nevertheless, according to a 2005 survey study, the underlying motivation behind these individuals’ desire for amputation is multifaceted and may include both identity and sexual elements. Indeed, two-thirds reported that sexual arousal to the image of themselves as disabled also constituted an important aspect of their desire (First, 2005). Yet the majority (77%) of subjects reported that their primary motivation for desiring amputation was “to feel whole, complete, or set right again” (i.e., correcting an identified mismatch). The question of the sexual component of BIID is fundamental and cannot be ignored. That being said, in the last few years, scholars have reached at least partial agreement that “sexual arousal is rarely the primary explanation of the desire to change one’s own anatomy” (Brugger, Lenggenhager, & Giummarra, 2013, p. 3), yet nevertheless “it is worthy of attention with respect to the ontogeny and phenomenology of the condition” (p. 3).

  8. 8.

    We should also note that approximately two-thirds of individuals with BIID who have undergone amputation of a major limb (i.e., arms or legs) used methods that risked serious injury or death (i.e., shotgun, chainsaw, wood chipper, and dry ice) to dispose of the unwanted limb. The remaining third in this study managed to convince a surgeon to perform the surgery (First, 2005).

  9. 9.

    Anyone who is closely familiar with cardiac patients knows how aware these patients are of what normal people are incapable of discerning the amount of air that enters their lungs. For most of us, this information is beneath the threshold of consciousness. These patients also notice every minor incline on the sidewalk, because even the smallest change in their oxygen consumption has a dramatic impact on them.

  10. 10.

    Interestingly, when patients suffering from somatoparaphrenia saw their affected hand directly in the mirror (as a reflection), they once again felt a sense of ownership toward their hand. However, “the habitual disownership returned seconds after the mirror was removed and was repeatedly remitted every time the mirror feedback was provided.” Thus essentially, “the two opposite judgements (i.e., this arm is mine vs. this arm belongs to someone else) alternated within seconds and this did not seem to be noteworthy to either patient” (Fotopoulou, et al., 2011, p. 3591). Based on these findings it seems at least possible to suggest that there is a fundamental gap between 1pp and 3pp, that is it to say that experiencing one’s body from a first person perspective, on the one hand, and experiencing one’s body from a third person perspective, on the other, are rooted in different kinds of mechanism.

References

  • Arzy, S., Thut, G., Mohr, C., Michel, C. M., & Blanke, O. (2006). Neural basis of embodiment: Distinct contributions of temporoparietal junction and extrastriate body area. Journal of Neuroscience, 26(31), 8074–8081.

    Google Scholar 

  • Banks, G., Short, P., Martínez, A. J., Latchaw, R., Ratcliff, G., & Boller, F. (1989). The alien hand syndrome. Clinical and postmortem findings. Archives of Neurology, 46(4), 456–459.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biran, I., Giovannetti, T., Buxbaum, L., & Chatterjee, A. (2006). The alien hand syndrome: What makes the alien hand alien? Cognitive Neuropsychology, 23(4), 563–582. https://doi.org/10.1080/02643290500180282.

  • Blanke, O. (2012). Multisensory brain mechanisms of bodily self-consciousness. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 13(8), 556–571.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanke, O., Morgenthaler, F. D., Brugger, P., & Overney, L. S. (2009). Preliminary evidence for a fronto‐parietal dysfunction in able‐bodied participants with a desire for limb amputation. Journal of Neuropsychology, 3(2), 181–200. https://doi.org/10.1348/174866408x318653.

  • Bogen, J. E. (1993). The callosal syndromes. In K. M. Heilman & E. Valenstein (Eds.), Clinical neuropsychology (3rd ed., pp. 337–407). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brion, S., & Jedynak, C. P. (1972). Troubles du transfert interhemispherique. A propos de trois observations de tumeurs du corps calleux. Le signe de la main. Revue Neurologique, 126(4), 257–266.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brugger, P., Lenggenhager, B., & Giummarra, M. J. (2013). Xenomelia: A social neuroscience view of altered bodily self-consciousness. Frontiers in Psychology, 4(204), 1–7. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00204.

  • Cogliano, R., Crisci, C., Conson, M., Grossi, D., & Trojano, L. (2012). Chronic somatoparaphrenia: A follow-up study on two clinical cases. Cortex, 48(6), 758–767. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cortex.2011.08.008.

  • Coltheart, M. (2010). The neuropsychology of delusions. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1191(1), 16–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craig, A. D. (2003). Interoception: The sense of the physiological condition of the body. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 13(4), 500–505.

    Google Scholar 

  • Critchley, H. D., & Harrison, N. A. (2013). Visceral influences on brain and behavior. Neuron, 77(4), 624–638.

    Google Scholar 

  • Critchley, M. (1953). The parietal lobe. New York: Hafner Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Critchley, M. (1973). Misoplegia or hatred of hemiplegia. Mount Sinai Journal of Medicine, 41(1), 82–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M., Coltheart, M., Langdon, R., & Breen, N. (2002). Monothematic delusions: Towards a two-factor account. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, 8(2–3), 133–158. https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2001.0007.

  • de Saint-Exupéry, A. (1971). The little prince (K. Woods, Trans.). Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Vignemont, F. (2010). Embodiment, ownership and disownership. Consciousness and Cognition, 20(1), 82–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Della Sala, S., Marchetti, C., & Spinnler, H. (1994). The anarchic hand: A frontomesial sign. In F. Boller & J. Grafman (Eds.), Handbook of neuropsychology (Vol. IX, pp. 233–255). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farrer, C., Franck, N., Georgieff, N., Frith, C., Decety, J., & Jeanneroda, M. (2003). Modulating the experience of agency: A positron emission tomography study. NeuroImage, 18, 324–333.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, T. E., Venneri, A., Simone, A. M., Fan, Y., & Northoff, G. (2010). The neuroanatomy of asomatognosia and somatoparaphrenia‏. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery & Psychiatry, 81(3), 276–281. https://doi.org/10.1136/jnnp.2009.188946.

  • First, M. B. (2005). Desire for amputation of a limb: Paraphilia, psychosis, or a new type of identity disorder. Psychological Medicine, 35(6), 919–928.

    Google Scholar 

  • First, M. B., & Fisher, C. E. (2011). Body integrity identity disorder: The persistent desire to acquire a physical disability‏. Psychopathology, 45(1), 3–14. https://doi.org/10.1159/000330503.

  • Fisher, K., & Smith, R. (2000). More work is needed to explain why patients ask for amputation of healthy limbs. BMJ, 320(7242), 1147. http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/bmj.320.7242.1147/a.

  • Fotopoulou, A., Jenkinson, P. M., Tsakiris, M., Haggard, P., Rudd, A., & Kopelman, M. D. (2011). Mirror-view reverses somatoparaphrenia: Dissociation between first-and third-person perspectives on body ownership. Neuropsychologia, 49(14), 3946–3955. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2011.10.011.

  • Frith, C. D., Blakemore, S. J., & Wolpert, D. M. (2000). Abnormalities in the awareness and control of action. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B: Biological Sciences, 355(1404), 1771–1788.

    Google Scholar 

  • Furth, G., & Smith, R. (2000). Apotemnophia: Information, questions, answers, and recommendations about self-demand amputation. Bloomington: 1st Books Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2000). Philosophical conceptions of the self: Implications for cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4(1), 14–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2007). The natural philosophy of agency. Philosophy Compass, 2(2), 347–357. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1747-9991.2007.00067.x.

  • Gallagher, S. (2011). Multiple aspects in the sense of agency. New Ideas in Psychology, 30(1), 15–31. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.newideapsych.2010.03.003.

  • Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2008). The phenomenological mind: An introduction to philosophy of mind and cognitive science. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerstmann, J. (1942). Problem of imperception of disease and of impaired body territories with organic lesions: Relation to body scheme and its disorders. Archives of Neurology and Psychiatry, 48(6), 890–913.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giummarra, M. J., Bradshaw, J. L., Nicholls, M. E., Hilti, L. M., & Brugger, P. (2011). Body integrity identity disorder: Deranged body processing, right fronto-parietal dysfunction, and phenomenological experience of body incongruity. Neuropsychology Review, 21(4), 320–333. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11065-011-9184-8.

  • Guterstam, A., & Ehrsson, H. H. (2012). Disowning one’s seen real body during an out-of-body illusion. Consciousness and Cognition, 21(2), 1037–1042. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2012.01.018.

  • Halligan, P. W., Marshall, J. C., & Wade, D. T. (1995). Unilateral somatoparaphrenia after right hemisphere stroke: A case description. Cortex, 31(1), 173–182. https://doi.org/10.1016/s0010-9452(13)80115-3.

  • Hilti, L. M., & Brugger, P. (2010). Incarnation and animation: Physical versus representational deficits of body integrity. Experimental Brain Research, 204(3), 315–326. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00221-009-2043-7.

  • Hilti, L. M., Hanggi, J., Vitacco, D. A., Kraemer, B., Palla, A., Luechinger, R., …, Brugger, P. (2013). The desire for healthy limb amputation: Structural brain correlates and clinical features of xenomelia‏. Brain, 136(1), 318–329. https://doi.org/10.1093/brain/aws316.

  • Kalckert, A., & Ehrsson, H. (2012). Moving a rubber hand that feels like your own: A dissociation of ownership and agency. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 6(40), 1–14. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2012.00040.

  • Kritikos, A., Breen, N., & Mattingley, J. B. (2005). Anarchic hand syndrome: Bimanual coordination and sensitivity to irrelevant information in unimanual reaches. Cognitive Brain Research, 24(3), 634–647. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cogbrainres.2005.03.015.

  • Leiguarda, R., Starkstein, S., & Berthier, M. (1989). Anterior callosal haemorrhage. A partial interhemispheric disconnection syndrome. Brain, 112, 1019–1037. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/brain/112.4.1019.

  • Lewis, J. S., Kersten, P., McCabe, C. S., McPherson, K. M., & Blake, D. R. (2007‏). Body perception disturbance: A contribution to pain in complex regional pain syndrome (CRPS). Pain, 133(1), 111–119.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loetscher, T., Regard, M., & Brugger, P. (2006). Misoplegia: A review of the literature and a case without hemiplegia. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery & Psychiatry, 77(9), 1099–1100. https://doi.org/10.1136/jnnp.2005.087163.

  • Mailis, A. (1996). Compulsive targeted self-injurious behaviour in humans with neuropathic pain: A counterpart of animal autotomy? Four case reports and literature review‏. Pain, 64(3), 569–578. https://doi.org/10.1016/0304-3959(95)00173-5.

  • Marchetti, C., & Sala, S. D. (1998). Disentangling the alien and anarchic hand. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, 3(3), 191–207. https://doi.org/10.1080/135468098396143.

  • Moss, A. D., & Turnbull, O. H. (1996). Hatred of the hemiparetic limbs (misoplegia) in a 10 year old child. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery, and Psychiatry, 61(2), 210.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearce, J. M. (2007). Misoplegia. European Neurology, 57(1), 62–64. https://doi.org/10.1159/000102172.

  • Rahmanovic, A., Barnier, A. J., Cox, R. E., Langdon, R., & Coltheart, M. (2012). “That’s not my arm”: A hypnotic analogue of somatoparaphrenia. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, 17(1), 36–63. https://doi.org/10.1186/cc12494.

  • Romano, D., Gandola, M., Bottini, G., & Maravita, A. (2014). Arousal responses to noxious stimuli in somatoparaphrenia and anosognosia: Clues to body awareness‏. Brain, 137(4), 1–11. https://doi.org/10.1093/brain/awu009.

  • Sato, A., & Yasuda, A. (2005). Illusion of sense of self-agency: Discrepancy between the predicted and actual sensory consequences of actions modulates the sense of self-agency, but not the sense of self-ownership. Cognition, 94(3), 241–255.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sedda, A. (2011). Body integrity identity disorder: From a psychological to a neurological syndrome‏. Neuropsychology Review, 21(4), 334–336. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11065-011-9186-6.

  • Synofzik, M., Vosgerau, G., & Newen, A. (2008). I move, therefore I am: A new theoretical framework to investigate agency and ownership. Consciousness and Cognition, 17(2), 411–424. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2008.03.008.

  • Tsakiris, M., & Haggard, P. (2005). The rubber hand illusion revisited: Visuotactile integration and self-attribution. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 31(1), 80–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsakiris, M., Hesse, M. D., Boy, C., Haggard, P., & Fink, G. R. (2006). Neural signatures of body ownership: A sensory network for bodily self-consciousness. Cerebral Cortex, 17(10), 2235–2244.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsakiris, M., Longo, M., & Haggard, P. (2010). Having a body versus moving your body: Neural signatures of agency and body-ownership. Neuropsychologia, 48(9), 2740–2749.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vallar, G., & Ronchi, R. (2009). Somatoparaphrenia: A body delusion. A review of the neuropsychological literature. Experimental Brain Research, 192(3), 533–551. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00221-008-1562-y.

  • Van der Kolk, B. A., Perry, C., & Herman, J. L. (1991). Childhood origins of self-destructive behavior. American Journal of Psychiatry, 148(12), 1665–1671. https://doi.org/10.1176/ajp.148.12.1665.

  • Wakefield, P. L., Frank, A., & Meyers, R. W. (1977). The hobbyist: A euphemism for self-mutilation and fetishism.‏ Bulletin of the Menninger Clinic, 41(6), 539.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Ataria, Y. (2018). When Ownership and Agency Collide: The Phenomenology of Limb-Disownership. In: Body Disownership in Complex Posttraumatic Stress Disorder. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-349-95366-0_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics